Abstract

There was a time when everything was simple. Today, everything has to be interpreted and reinterpreted. How did this change take place? Why is it that nowadays all historical texts seem to be ‘difficult’, so that they have to be endlessly explained, provided with commentaries and perhaps also polished up a bit? Why is it that hermeneutics — the science of interpretation — has changed from being an insignificant minor discipline into a universal practice in the humanities and even a completely separate school of philosophical thought?

Keywords

Tate Avant Clarification Metaphor Verse 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    P. Ricoeur, De l’interprétation, Essai sur Freud (Paris: Du Seuil, 1965), p. 174.Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    H.-G. Gadamer, ‘The Problem of Historical Consciousness’, Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, 5 (1975), p. 8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. 3.
    P. Lapide, Original title: Die Bergpredigt — Utopie oder Programm (Mainz: Matthias Grünewald Verlag, 1982).Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    See N. Wolterstorff, John Locke and the Ethics of Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 218 ff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. 6.
    See Th. de Boer, Tamara A., Awater en andere verhalen over subjectiviteit (Amsterdam: Boom, 1993), pp. 47, 196.Google Scholar
  6. 7.
    P. Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory. Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth, Texas: Texas Christian University Press, 1976), pp. 32 ff.Google Scholar
  7. 8.
    See R. Jakobson, ‘Linguistics and Poetics’ in Style in Language, ed. T. A. Sebeok (Cambridge Mass.: MIT Press, 1960), pp. 350 ff.Google Scholar
  8. 9.
    P. Ricoeur, La métaphore vive (Paris: Du Seuil, 1975).Google Scholar
  9. 10.
    J. Huizinga, Herfsttij der middeleeuwen, 18th edn (Groningen: Wolters Noordhoff, 1985) p. 304 ff.; The Waning of the Middle Ages (Harmonsdworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books, 1976), pp. 281 ff.Google Scholar
  10. 11.
    J. Derrida, Marges de la philosophie (Paris: De Minuit, 1972), pp. 265–6, 304.Google Scholar
  11. See also N. Wolterstorff, John Locke and the Ethics of Belief (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 156 ff., 219. Locke rejects figurative speech as out of place and obstructive. We have to set before our mind’s eye the very ideas themselves. Wolterstorff argues that Locke condemns metaphors by using metaphors himself. These metaphors of perception and luminosity are deeper than any other in Locke. I have made no attempt in my discussion to eliminate them. For the pictures are not decorative features of Locke’s presentation of his thought but an indispensable feature of the thought itself.’CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. 13.
    See Th. de Boer, De God van de filosofen en de God van Pascal, 3rd edn. (Zeetermeer: Meinema, 1995), p. 15.Google Scholar
  13. 14.
    Nederlandse literatuur, een geschiedenis, ed. M. A. Schenkeveld-van der Dussen (Groningen: Martinus Nijhoff, 1993), pp. 422, 428.Google Scholar
  14. 17.
    H.-G. Gadamer, Wahrheit und Methode (Tübingen: J. C. B. Mehr, 1965), pp. 81 ff, 111 ff.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Palgrave Macmillan, a division of Macmillan Publishers Limited 2000

Authors and Affiliations

  • Theo de Boer

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations