Skip to main content

Civic Liberalism and the “Dialogical Model” of Judicial Review

  • Chapter
Virtue Jurisprudence
  • 62 Accesses

Abstract

Consider the following scenarios which could occur in any affluent, liberal democratic society:

Scenario 1: Intelligence gathering operatives believe that there is a good chance that the country will be the target of a terrorist attack within the next 48 hours. The exact nature of the attack is unknown, but there is good reason to believe that the risk of attack is significant. Military personnel and equipment have been stationed at airports and some airlines have cancelled flights. Much debate takes place in the media concerning how much is being done to guard against this possible attack. Critics of the existing government claim that more should be done. One prominent critic complains that “citizens should not have to be fearful of such attacks in their own homes, schools or airports; the government needs to do more to eliminate these threats!”

In a world that is inherently indeterminate, a suitable theory of distributive justice must perhaps itself be indeterminate, and its indeterminacies must accommodate those of the world where relevant.

Russell Hardin, Indeterminacy and Society1

For their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I am grateful to the members of the democracy reading group at Waterloo University (especially my colleague Jan Narveson) and two anonymous referees for this journal.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Russell Hardin, Indeterminacy and Society (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2003), p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971) and Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  4. The literature on state neutrality is extensive. A partial list of its main proponents include Rawls, A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism; Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia; Bruce Ackerman, Social Justice and the Liberal State (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1980);

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ronald Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985);

    Google Scholar 

  6. Brian Barry, Justice as Impartiality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (New York: Basic Books, 1983);

    Google Scholar 

  8. David Miller, Principles of Social Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Walzer, Spheres of Justice; Miller, Principles of Social Justice; Serena Olsaretti (ed.), Desert and Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Cécil Fabre, Social Rights Under the Constitution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Martha Nussbaum, Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000);

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Stuart White, The Civic Minimum (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. David Gauthier, Morals by Agreement (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Proponents of the dialogical model of judicial review include Peter Hogg and Allison Bushell, “The Charter Dialogue Between Courts and Legislatures”, 35(1) Osgoode Hall Law J. 75–124 (1997); and Kent Roach, The Supreme Court on Trial: Judicial Activism or Democratic Dialogue (Toronto: Irwin Law, 2001).

    Google Scholar 

  15. See Bork, The Tempting of America: The Political Seduction of the Law (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1990), pp. 139–143.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  17. K. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (2nd edn) (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Some have tried to remedy this deficiency in Rawls’s account by adding health care to the list of things governed by the principle of fair equality of opportunity. See, for example, Norman Daniels’s Just Health Care (Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1985). Rawls actually endorses Daniels’s strategy in Political Liberalism. However, such a strategy is rife with problems as such a cost-blind approach to health care is ill-equipped to deal with the problem of prioritizing limited resources in health care. For a discussion of these concerns, see Dan Brock, “Broadening the Bioethics Agenda”, 10 Kennedy Inst. Ethics J. 21–38 (2000).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  19. Jeremy Waldron, “Judicial Review and the Conditions of Democracy”, 6(4) J. Pol. Phil. 337–338 (1998). Also see Waldron’s Law and Disagreement (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Stephen Holmes and Cass Sunstein, The Costs of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes (New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 1999), p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998). Scanlon describes the subject matter of judgments of right and wrong as:

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000), p. 351.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See J. S. Mill, On Liberty (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1982).

    Google Scholar 

  25. This vision of the self is endorsed, for example, by Michel Sandel in Democracy’s Discontent and by David Miller in On Nationality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ronald Dworkin, Freedom’s Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996), p. 345.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2008 Colin Farrelly & Lawrence B. Solum

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Farrelly, C. (2008). Civic Liberalism and the “Dialogical Model” of Judicial Review. In: Farrelly, C., Solum, L.B. (eds) Virtue Jurisprudence. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-60073-1_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics