Advertisement

International Political Economy as a Culture of Competition

Chapter

Abstract

That the international political economy is competitive is not controversial. Competition usually is seen as endemic to the anarchic structure of international life. As members of an international society, states are constituted as independent actors who must rely primarily on their own resources and efforts to achieve their goals and purposes. This requirement of ‘self-help’ becomes ‘competitive self-help’ where the goals and purposes of states are incompatible. If, as we are often told, states are compelled to define important goals in terms of relative gains, then competition assumes a prominent and defining role in international life.

Keywords

World Market International Relation Political Community World Politics Economic Competition 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 2.
    See, for example, James N. Rosenau, Turbulence in World Politics: A Theory of Change and Continuity (Princeton: Princeton University, 1990)Google Scholar
  2. Ernst B. Haas, When Knowledge is Power: Three Models of Change in International Organizations (Berkeley: University of California, 1990)Google Scholar
  3. R.B.J. Walker, One World, Many Worlds: Struggles for a Just World Peace (Boulder: Lynne Rienner, 1988).Google Scholar
  4. 3.
    Huntington’s article, ‘The Clash of Civilizations?’, Foreign Affairs 72:3 (Summer 1993), pp. 22–49, engendered a strong response in the pages of Foreign Affairs. See especially the response by Fouad Ajami, ‘The Summoning’, Foreign Affairs 72:4 (September/October 1993), pp. 2–9. Huntington tends to treat the terms ‘civilization’ and ‘culture’ as synonymous (see p. 22). This practice is not uncommon. For a brief history of the relation between these two terms, see A.L. Kroeber and Clyde Kluckhohn, Culture: a Critical Review of Concepts and Definitions (New York: Vintage, 1963), pp. 15–25.Google Scholar
  5. 4.
    See, for example, Ali A. Mazrui, Cultural Forces in World Politics (London, Nairobi, and Portsmouth: James Currey and Heinemann, 1990)Google Scholar
  6. R.B.J. Walker, ‘The Concept of Culture in the Theory of International Relations’, and Richard A. Falk, ‘Culture, Modernism, and Postmodernism: A Challenge to International Relations’, both in Jongsuk Chay (ed)., Culture and International Relations (New York: Praeger, 1990), pp. 3–17 and 267–79 respectivelyGoogle Scholar
  7. Nicholas J. Rengger, ‘Culture, Society, and Order in World Politics’, in John Bayliss and N.J. Rengger, (eds), Dilemmas of World Politics: International Issues in a Changing World (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), pp. 85–103Google Scholar
  8. Adda B. Bozeman, The Future of Law in a Multicultural World (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1971)Google Scholar
  9. Alan Pleydell, ‘Language, Culture and the Concept of International Political Community’, in James Mayall (ed.), The Community of States: A Study in International Political Theory (London: Allen and Unwin, 1982), pp. 167–81.Google Scholar
  10. 5.
    See, especially, Hedley Bull and Adam Watson (eds), The Expansion of International Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), Adam Watson, The Evolution of International Society: A Comparative Historical Analysis (London and New York: Routledge, 1992), and Adam Watson,’ systems of States’, Review of International Studies 16:6 (1990), pp. 99–109. The unease of a multicultural international society is examined particularly well by Bull and Watson in the ‘Conclusion’ and Bull in ‘The Revolt against the West’, both in The Expansion of International Society, pp. 425–35 and 217–28 respectively. The centrality of the Bull/Watson project to current debates is suggested by Barry Buzan, ‘From International System to International Society: Structural Realism and Regime Theory Meet the English School’, International Organization 47:3 (1993), pp. 327–52 and Ole Waever, ‘International Society — Theoretical Promises Unfulfilled’, Cooperation and Conflict 27:1 (1992), pp. 97–128.Google Scholar
  11. 6.
    See, for example, Ronnie D. Lipschtz, ‘Reconstructing World Politics: The Emergence of Global Civil Society’, Millennium 21:3 (1992), pp. 389–420CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Paul Ghils, ‘International Civil Society: International Nogovernmental Organizations in the International System’, International Social Science Journal 133 (August 1992), pp. 417–29Google Scholar
  13. and, in a more critical spirit, Craig N. Murphy and Enrico Augelli, ‘International Institutions, Decolonization, and Development’, International Political Science Review 14:1 (1993), pp. 71–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. 7.
    See, for example, P. Iyer, Video Night in Kathmandu (New York: Knopf, 1988)Google Scholar
  15. A. Mattelart, Transnationals and Third World: The Struggle for Culture (South Hadley: Bergin and Garvey, 1983)Google Scholar
  16. E. Gans, The End of Culture: Toward a Generative Anthropology (Berkeley: University of California, 1985)Google Scholar
  17. Wolfgang Sachs, ‘One World’, in W. Sachs (ed.), The Development Dictionary (London: Zed Books, 1992).Google Scholar
  18. 8.
    See Jonathan Friedman, ‘Culture, Identity and World Process’, in Daniel Miller et al. (eds), Domination and Resistance (London: Unwin and Hyman, 1989), pp. 246–60 and ‘Being in the World: Globalization and Localization’, Theory, Culture and Society 7:2–3 (1990), pp. 311–28Google Scholar
  19. Arjun Appadurai, ‘Disjuncture and Difference in the Global Cultural Economy’, Public Culture 2:2 (Spring 1990), pp. 1–24CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Ulf Hannerz, ‘Notes on the Global Ecumene’, Public Culture 1:2 (Spring 1989), pp. 66–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Anthony D. Smith, ‘Towards a Global Culture?’, Theory, Culture and Society 7:2–3 (1990), pp. 171–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. 9.
    Several recent articles attempt this more ambitious task. See Thomas H. Eriksen and Iver B. Neumann, ‘International Relations as a Cultural System: an Agenda for Research’, Cooperation and Conflict 28:3 (1993), pp. 233–64, and Marco Verweij, ‘Cultural Theory and the Study of International Relations’, Millennium 24:1 (1995), pp. 87–111. SeeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Naeem Inayatullah and David L. Blaney, ‘Knowing Encounters: Beyond Partiality and Parochialism’, in Y. Lapid and F. Kratochwil (eds), The Return of Culture and Identity in IR Theory (Boulder: Lynne Rienner, 1995).Google Scholar
  24. 13.
    Here we draw on the language of Ashis Nandy, Traditions, Tyranny and Utopias: Essays in the Politics of Awareness (Delhi: Oxford University, 1987), and Tzvetan Todorov, ‘A Dialogic Criticism?’, in Todozov, Literature and its Theorists: A Personal View of Twentieth Century Literature (Ithaca: Cornell University, 1987), p. 160.Google Scholar
  25. 14.
    Marshall Sahlins, Culture and Practical Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1976, p. viii. Sahlins elaborates this point later (at p. 209) in the text: … nature is to culture as the constituted is to the constituting. Culture is not merely nature expressed in another form. Rather the reverse: the action of nature unfolds in the terms of culture; that is, in a form no longer its own but embodied as meaning. Nor is this a mere translation. The natural fact assumes a new mode of existence as a symbolized fact, its cultural deployment and consequences now governed by the relation between its meaningful dimension and other such meanings, rather than the relation between its natural dimension and other such facts. All of this of course within material limits. Perhaps similarly, Kroeber and Kluckhohn (Culture, pp. 12 and 368) place culture as’ superorganic’, as an ‘intervening variable’ between human beings as organisms and the human environment.Google Scholar
  26. 15.
    See, for instance, the claims of Francis Fukuyama, ‘The End of History’, The National Interest 16 (1989), pp. 3–18Google Scholar
  27. V.S. Naipaul, ‘Our Universal Civilization’, New York Times (5 November 1990)Google Scholar
  28. Lucian W. Pye, ‘Political Science and the Crisis of Authoritarianism’, American Political Science Review 84 (1990), pp. 3–19. See also the citations in note 6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. 16.
    We draw on Thomas Eriksen’s formulation that cultural identity is ‘relational and processual’. Thus, it is possible to emphasize the process of maintaining a sense of cultural identity — integrity and bound-edness — in relation to the wider world, rather than the preservation of some ‘fixed, monolithic entity,’ or immutable cultural essence. Thomas H. Eriksen, ‘The Cultural Context of Ethnic Differences’, Man 26:1 (1991), pp. 127–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. 17.
    This is an issue not so easily decided by evidence, as Alfie Kohn suggests, though he weighs in against the claim that competition is natural. See Alfie Kohn, No Contest: The Case against Competition (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1986), chapter 2. Our argument might be stated in this way: though the physiological qualities of the species make it amenable to competition (as well as cooperation we might add) the specific character of competition — its meaningful and purposeful character in the modern era — cannot be read off from the ‘facts’ of nature. In the international relations literature it is Kenneth Waltz who makes (perhaps) the strongest case against reading competition as a natural fact in his rejection of ‘first image’ thinking in Man, the State, and War (New York: Columbia University, 1959), chapters II and III. Of course, our account of competition as a structure of meaning and purpose deviates from Waltz’s view of competition as a causal effect of anarchy.Google Scholar
  31. 18.
    George Marcus and Michael Fischer, Anthropology as Cultural Critique: An Experimental Moment in the Social Sciences (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992), p. 78, approvingly cite Raymond Williams to the effect that explanations necessarily ‘merge … the understanding of their subject’s point of view in circumscribed social settings with the difficulties of also representing accurately the penetration of larger forces’. Following Marcus and Fischer, we aim, then, to present the ‘outside forces’ of political economy as ‘an integral part of the construction and constitution of the “inside”’ (p. 77).Google Scholar
  32. 19.
    See Isaac Kraminick, ‘Equal Opportunity and the Race of Life’, Dissent 28:2 (1981), pp. 178–87.Google Scholar
  33. 20.
    Friedrich A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. 3: The Political Order of a Free People (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1979), pp. 67–8.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. 21.
    Hayek hopes to dispute the idea of ‘rewards to merit’ as the legitimating value of a modern competitive society, directing our attention to other purposes, that we highlight below, although he acknowledges the general appeal of and to that notion. See Friedrich Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. 2: The Mirage of Social Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976), chapter 8.Google Scholar
  35. 22.
    Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. 2, pp. 72–8, 115, and Frank H. Knight, The Ethics of Competition and Other Essays (London: Allen and Unwin, 1936), p. 56.Google Scholar
  36. 23.
    See Friedrich Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago, 1960), chapter 6. The quoted phrases are from p. 86.Google Scholar
  37. 24.
    See Friedrich A. Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. 1: Rules and Order (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993) and Thomas E. Flanagan, ‘Hayek’s Concept of Constructivism’, in J. M. Porter (ed.), Sophia and Praxis: The Boundaries of Politics (Chatham, NJ: Chatham House, 1984) on the need for rules and order (albeit without an orderer) in Hayek’s system.Google Scholar
  38. 26.
    It should be clear by now that we do not use the terms ‘competitive’ or ‘competition’ to refer to the internal structure of markets. Competition is not a static state, as in the parameters and equilibrium solution of a model of perfect competition. Rather, competition is a process, a series of competitive struggles and strategies. See Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (New York: Harper Colophon, 1976), chapter VII, and Paul J. McNulty, ‘Economic Theory and the Meaning of Competition’, Quarterly Journal of Economics 82 (1968), pp. 639–56.Google Scholar
  39. 28.
    Knight, p. 49. For Hayek, the market is both an expression of and the unintended outcome of the particular and independent actions of individuals. See, for example, Hayek’s Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. 2, p. 107. Marx is also eloquent on the status of the individual in the market in Capital. Vol. I (New York: Vintage, 1977), chapter 1 and in his discussion of Aristotle’s limited capacity to conceive the economy (pp. 151–2). See also Karl Marx, Grundrisse (New York: Vintage, 1973), pp. 243–5Google Scholar
  40. G.W.F. Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ed. Allen W. Wood (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), Part 1, Sections 1 and 2 (on ‘Property’ and ‘Contract’) and Part 3, Section 2 (on ‘Civil Society’)Google Scholar
  41. David P. Levine, Economic Theory. Vol. I: The Elementary Relations of Economic Life (London, Henley, and Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978), chapter 1.Google Scholar
  42. 29.
    We express this argument mostly in language drawn from Hayek, Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. II, chapter 10 (the quoted phrase is from p. 107) and The Constitution of Liberty, chapter 5. See also the discussion of the valuation of individuals and the social good of wealth production within a society centering on competition in Knight, pp. 47–53, and Justin Rosenberg, The Empire of Civil Society (New York: Verso, 1994), chapter 5. These themes of the mutual dependence of economic actors and the spur to human production are central to Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (New York: The Modern Library, 1937), Book I, Chapter 1, and Karl Marx, Capital. Vol. III (New York: International Publishers, 1967), p. 250 and Grundrisse, pp. 325 and 541. James A. Caporaso and David P. Levine, Theories of Political Economy (Cambridge: Cambridge University, 1992), chapter 2, provide a nice summary discussion of the treatment of these themes in the classical political economy tradition.Google Scholar
  43. 30.
    The phrase in quotation marks is drawn from R.B.J. Walker, Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), p. 9.Google Scholar
  44. 31.
    Hinsley is quite succinct. Sovereignty is the ‘idea that there is a final and absolute political authority in the political community … and no final and absolute authority exists elsewhere’. F.H. Hinsley, Sovereignty, 2nd edn (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986), p. 26.Google Scholar
  45. 32.
    Richard K. Ashley, ‘Untying the Sovereign State: A Double Reading of the Anarchy Problematiaue’. Millennium 17:2 (1988). pp. 227–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. 33.
    Cornelia Navari, ‘Knowledge, the State and the State of Nature’, in Michael Donelan (ed.), The Reason of States: A Study in International Political Theory (London: Allen and Unwin, 1978), p. 119.Google Scholar
  47. 34.
    Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics (New York: Columbia University Press, 1977), chapter 1, and Adam Watson,’ systems of States’.Google Scholar
  48. 36.
    Leo Gross, ‘The Peace of Westphalia — 1648–1948’, in Richard Falk and Wolfram Hanrieden (eds), International Law and Organization (New York: J.B. Lippincott, 1968), p. 54.Google Scholar
  49. 37.
    See Michael Walzer, ‘The Moral Standing of States: a Response to Four Critics’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 9:3 (1980), pp. 209–29, and Robert H. Jackson, ‘Martin Wight, International Theory and the Good Life’, Millennium 19:2 (1990), pp. 261–72.Google Scholar
  50. 38.
    On the connection of state sovereignty and the principle of self-determination, see Yael Pamir, ‘The Right to National Self-Determination’, Social Research 58 (1991), pp. 565–90, and Allen Buchanan,’ self Determination and the Right to Secede’, Journal of International Affairs 45 (1992), pp. 348–65. Of course the right to secession/self-determination may conflict with the current drawing of sovereignties. For a detailed discussion of the tensions involved, see Hurst Hannum, Autonomy, Sovereignty, and Self-Determination: The Accommodating of Conflicting Rights (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1990).Google Scholar
  51. 41.
    Hinsley, Sovereignty, p. 158, and Martin Wight, ‘The Origins of the States-System: Chronological Limits’, in Hedley Bull (ed.), Systems of States (Leicester: Leicester University Press, 1977), p. 135.Google Scholar
  52. 42.
    See Cynthia Weber, ‘Reconstructing Statehood: Examining the Sovereignty/Intervention Boundary’, Review of International Studies 18 (1992), pp. 199–216, and Hedley Bull, ‘Introduction’, in H. Bull, (ed.), Intervention in World Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), pp. 1–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. 44.
    The quotation is from Benedict Anderson’s important account of this ‘imagining’ process in Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism (London: Verso, 1983). For a similar set of claims about the salience of nationalism and international statehood, see Anthony D. Smith, Nationalism in the Twentieth Century (New York: New York University Press, 1979), ‘Introduction: The Formation of Nationalist Movements’, in Anthony D. Smith (ed.), Nationalist Movements (New York: St. Martin’s, 1976), and ‘Towards a Global Culture?’.Google Scholar
  54. 45.
    Charles Tilly, ‘National Self-Determination as a Problem for All of Us’, Daedalus 122:3 (1993), p. 29.Google Scholar
  55. 46.
    Charles R. Beitz, ‘Sovereignty and Morality in International Affairs’, in David Held (ed.), Political Theory Today (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1991), p. 243.Google Scholar
  56. 48.
    See Naeem Inayatullah and David L. Blaney, ‘Realizing Sovereignty’, Review of International Studies 21:1 (1995), pp. 3–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Raymond Vernon and Ethan B. Kapstein, ‘National Needs, Global Resources’, Daedalus 120:4 (1991)Google Scholar
  58. Robert B. Reich, ‘What is a Nation?’ Political Science Quarterly 106:2 (1991), pp. 193–209CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Sally Falk Moore, ‘The Production of Cultural Pluralism as a Process’, Public Culture 1:2 (Spring 1989): 26–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. 49.
    Friedrich A. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1944), p. 220.Google Scholar
  61. 50.
    See Richard Rosecrance, The Rise of the Trading State: Commerce and Conquest in the Modern World (New York: Basic Books, 1986).Google Scholar
  62. 51.
    See, for example, Janice E. Thomson and Stephen D. Krasner, ‘Global Transactions and the Consolidation of Sovereignty’, in Ernst-Otto Czempiel and James N. Rosenau (eds), Global Changes and Theoretical Challenges: Approaches to World Politics (Lexington: Lexington Books, 1989), pp. 196–8, 214–16Google Scholar
  63. David K. Tarullo, ‘Logic, Myth, and the International Economic Order’, Harvard International Law Journal 26:2 (1985), pp. 533–52Google Scholar
  64. Stephen Gill and David Law, ‘Global Hegemony and the Structural Power of Capital’, in S. Gill (ed.), Gramsci, Historical Materialism and International Relations (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), pp. 93–124. The term’ social structure of accumulation’ is from Gill and Law, p. 95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. 52.
    This description is drawn from Susan Strange, ‘States, Firms and Diplomacy’, International Affairs 68:1 (January 1992), pp. 1–15; Reich, ‘What is a Nation?’, pp. 201CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Clyde V. Prestowitz, Jr, ‘The Fight over Competitiveness: A Zero-Sum Debate?’, Foreign Affairs (July/August 1994), pp. 186–9.Google Scholar
  67. 53.
    Charles Bright and Michael Geyer, ‘For a Unified History of the World in the Twentieth Century’, Radical History Review 39 (1987): 69–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. 54.
    Smith, Book IV, chapter 1. Also, see Craig Murphy’s detailed discussion of this logic in International Organization and Industrial Change (New York: Oxford University Press, 1994).Google Scholar
  69. 55.
    See the related claims of Gustavo Esteva (Development’) and C. Douglas Lummis (‘Equality’), in Wolfgang Sachs (ed.), The Development Dictionary (London: Zed Books, 1992).Google Scholar
  70. 56.
    The construction of productive capacities as facts of nature is clear in Ricardo. In contemporary theories, factor endowments, whether conceived as natural or constructed endowments, are treated as given outside of the process by which returns from trade are determined. See Robert Gilpin, The Political Economy of International Relations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1987), chapter 5.Google Scholar
  71. 59.
    John H. Herz, International Politics in the Atomic Age (New York: Columbia University Press, 1959), pp. 14 and 40.Google Scholar
  72. 60.
    See Ashley, ‘Untying the Sovereign State’; Robert Jervis, ‘Cooperation Under the Security Dilemma’, World Politics 30 (1978), pp. 167–214CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. John H. Herz, ‘Idealist Internationalism and the Security Dilemma’, World Politics 2 (1950), pp. 157–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. 61.
    See Ian Clark, The Hierarchy of States: Reform and Resistance in the International Order (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), pp. 218–19, and Bull, Anarchical Society, p. 205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. 62.
    Bull employs all of these gradations, plus the idea of ‘quasi-states’, in Anarchical Society, chapter 9. All of these terms are common usages, except for the idea of ‘quasi-states’ which has recently become popular in academic circles only due to the efforts of Robert H. Jackson, Quasi-States: Sovereignty, International Relations, and the Third World (Cambridee: Cambridge University Press, 1990.Google Scholar
  76. 63.
    We adapt the analysis of Geoffrey Blainey, The Causes of War (New York: The Free Press, 1988), chapter 8.Google Scholar
  77. 66.
    In Bull’s terms, the Great Powers maintain a ‘hegemony’, based on some combination of force and legitimacy. See Anarchical Society, pp. 215–18. This usage appears somewhere between a Gramscian and a realist notion of hegemony as Stephen Gill and David Law draw the distinction in The Global Political Economy (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1988), pp. 76–80.Google Scholar
  78. 68.
    See Paul Johnson, ‘Colonialism Back — and not a Moment too Soon’, New York Times 18 March 1993, and Robert Jackson, Quasi-States.Google Scholar
  79. 72.
    The interrelation of military and economic power is well captured in Paul Kennedy’s The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers (New York: Random House, 1987). While there is no simple correlation between military strength and a country’s wealth at any one point in time, Kennedy makes clear that economic success is necessary to sustain military strength for any length of time. Certainly, Kennedy also suggests the role that military power may play in economic success although this relationship may be weakening in the present.Google Scholar
  80. 76.
    See Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann, The Social Construction of Reality (Garden City, NY: Anchor, 1966)Google Scholar
  81. Lev S. Vygotsky, Thought and Language (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1962)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Heinz Kohut, The Restoration of the Self (New York: International Universities Press, 1977); Inayatullah and Blaney, ‘Realizing Sovereignty’Google Scholar
  83. Rob Walker, Inside/Outside; and Alexander Wendt, Anarchy is What States Make of it: The Social Construction of Power Politics’, International Organization 46:2 (Spring 1992), pp. 391–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. 77.
    See David L. Blaney and Naeem Inayatullah, ‘Prelude to a Conversation of Cultures in International Society? Todorov and Nandy on the Possibility of Dialogue’, Alternatives 19:1 (1994), pp. 23–51.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Palgrave Macmillan, a division of Macmillan Publishers Limited 1998

Authors and Affiliations

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations