Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Studies in Modern History ((SMH))

Abstract

This is an essay in intellectual history drawing generally and adaptively from that aspect of linguistic field theory which might conveniently be called rhetorical pragmatics. The result is to give a different emphasis to the study of the political literature of the seventeenth century and also to suggest some reconceptualisation of intellectual history itself. Field theory is that branch of modern linguistics which deals with the semantic organisation of distinct areas of experience. It concerns the relationships between groups of words forming a semantic field and an unpredicated content domain, or undifferentiated subject matter.1 A semantic field is thus something of a microcosm of the Saussurian notion of langue, the structurally related linguistic system which at any given time constitutes a resource for the language user.2 The selective use of langue is often referred to as parole, or langage, and pragmatics is the principal name given to its study. At least in part, this overlaps with rhetoric; for each deals with what people actually do with words for various purposes. Here, the later works of Wittgenstein and those of John Austin have been regarded as of seminal significance.3

I was walking along a farm-road close to Piltdown Common Fletching when I noticed that the road had been mended with some peculiar brown flints not usual in the district. On inquiry I was astonished to learn that they were dug up from a gravel-pit on the farm, and shortly afterwards I visited the place where two labourers were at work digging gravel for small repairs to the roads. Charles Dawson, in C. Dawson and A. S. Woodward, ‘On the Discovery of a Palaeolithic Human Skull and Mandible in Flint-bearing Gravel Overlying the Wealden at Piltdown (Fletching) Sussex’, The Quarterly Journal of the Geological Society of London, Vol. 69 (1912).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Valuable accounts are to be found in S. Ullmann, Semantics: An Introduction to the Science of Meaning (Oxford: Blackwell, 1972 edn), pp. 234f

    Google Scholar 

  2. E. Kittay, Metaphor: Its Cognitive Force and Linguistic Structure (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989), Ch. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  3. F. de Saussure, Cours de linguistique general, 1916, (eds) C. Bally and A. Sachehaye, trans. B. Harris, Course in General Linguistics (Illinois: Open Court, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  4. L. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, trans. G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, 1968 edn)

    Google Scholar 

  5. J. Austin, How to Do Things with Words (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1962)

    Google Scholar 

  6. on their significance in this area of linguistics, see S. Levinson, Pragmatics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987), pp. 227f.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See at length, J. Tully (ed.), Meaning and Context: Quentin Skinner and his Critics (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Saussure did recognise language as a part of society and advocated the systematic study of sign systems (semiology) in society, ibid., Pt 1, Ch. 3, sect. 3; but the drift of his analysis is always towards making language explicable in linguistic terms. Semiology looks at society as if it were language, or draws no distinction between language as a sign system and the sign systems taken to constitute society. See also R. Koselleck, Futures Past. On the Semantics of Historical Time, trans. K. Tribe (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1985), p. 79 on the ‘precarious marginality’ of semantics to linguistics because of the involvement with the non-linguistic.

    Google Scholar 

  9. D. Davidson, ‘On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme’, in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), pp. 183f.

    Google Scholar 

  10. J. Trier, Der Deutsche Wortschatz im Sinnbezirk des Verstandes (Heidelberg: Winter, 1931); see the discussion in Ullmann, Semantics pp. 244–50; and Kittay, Metaphor, pp. 223ff.

    Google Scholar 

  11. B. Berlin and P. Kay, Basic Colour Terms (California: University Press, 1969). Another phenomenon appropriate for field theory analysis can be found in Italian spoken in Australia. A simplified workplace subfield of terms (bottega, nuigazxino/shop; ufficio/office; fattoria/farm) has been brought about by the English context in which it is used. Fattoria is used for the English factory and so as to avoid the semantic elision between farm and factory, the English ‘farm’ has been introduced as farma. Michael Clyne, Community Languages in the Australian Experience (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991) is full of fascinating information of this sort.

    Google Scholar 

  12. M. Oakeshott, Experience and its Modes (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1933), Ch. 3; ‘Present, Future and Past’, in On History and Other Essays (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1983).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Conal Condren, The Status and Appraisal of Classic Texts: An Essay on Political Theory, Its Inheritance, and the History of Ideas (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. For example, J. T. Matthews, The Play of Faulkner’s Language (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1982), in which Faulkner’s language is so reified as to be an independent character in even an explanans for the author’s work.

    Google Scholar 

  15. R. Waswo, Language and Meaning in the Renaissance (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987), Chs 1 and 2; see the discussion between Waswo and J. Monfasini in Journal of the History of Ideas, 49 (1989), pp. 324f.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. For interesting and often subtle examples, see Jonathan Dollimore and Alan Sinfield (eds), Political Shakespeare: New Essays in Cultural Materialism (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1985). Michel Foucault is a figure who stands behind and is revered in such literature, and in much of his work we can see exactly what I have in mind and will touch on more below, namely the hypostatisation of a postulate of power.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Compare the contributions of J. G. A. Pocock and N. Rubenstein in A. Pagden (ed.), The Languages of Political Theory in Early Modern Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  18. For a lucid overview of Begriffsgeschichte see M. Richter, ‘Begriffsgeschichte and the History of Ideas’, The Journal of the History of Ideas, 48 (1987), pp. 247–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. see also the rather touchy exchange between J. Rayner, ‘On Begriffsgeschichte’, Political Theory 16, 3(1988) pp. 496–501, and M. Richter, ‘Understanding Begnffsgesichte: A Rejoinder’, ibid., 17, 2(1989), pp. 296–301. R. Koselleck, Futures Past, provides a theoretical overview of the project. In this Introduction, I am attempting only and somewhat obliquely to respecify what both Begnffsgeschichte and other forms of intellectual and conceptual history minimally entail.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Kenneth Grahame, The Wind in the Willows (London: Methuen, 1949 edn), pp. 53–5, with apologies to the Rat, who, of course, does genuinely discover the surface signs to Badger’s subterranean home.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Michael Oakeshott, ‘The Activity of Being an Historian’, in Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays (London: Methuen, 1962) on the difference between accounting for and giving an account of.

    Google Scholar 

  22. William Cavendish, letter of ‘Advice’, 1659–60, Bodleian Library, Clarendon MS 109; the MS is printed in Thomas Slaughter, Ideology and Politics on the Eve of the Restoration: Newcastle’s Advice to Charles II (Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Richard More, A True Relation of the Murders (London, 1643).

    Google Scholar 

  24. G. Shulman, Radicalism and Reverence: The Political Thought of Gerrard Winstanley (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989), Pt 1.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See Conal Condren, ‘The Rhetorical “Foundations” of Leuiathan,’ History of Political Thought, XI (1990), pp. 703f for comment on the different senses of rhetoric relevant to Leviathan; R. Prokhovnik, Rhetoric and Philosophy in Hobbes’s Leviathan (New York: Garland, 1991), Ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See especially Quentin Skinner, ‘Thomas Hobbes: Rhetoric and the Construction of Morality’, Proceedings of the British Academy, 76 (1991), pp. 1–61.

    Google Scholar 

  27. I make this extreme reduction for the purposes of clarification, although it is not too brisk a synopsis of much that has been written on Magna Carta to say that scholars have treated it as an ideological manifesto when they have not mistaken it for a constitutional law. It was never straightforwardly a legal document, as the impeccable J. C. Holt has shown; yet even he refers to it as a ‘party manifesto’: Magna Carta (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976 edn), p. 204.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Jorge Larrain, The Concept of Ideology (London: Hutchinson, 1984 edn), pp. 19–20; Mark Goldie is more subtle, but his genealogy of ideology which embraces Bacon is still not the history of an underlying concept. It is, rather, an account of a series of similar accusatory tactics in public rhetoric. See ‘Ideology’ in T. Ball, J. Farr and R. Hanson (eds), Political Innovation and Conceptual Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989). See also R. Koselleck, Futures Past, pp. 185 and 195, where he paraphrases both Richard Hooker and Karl Marx in the vocabulary of ideology. What is literally true of one’s language requires a semantic redescription of the other’s. By this process is created the impression of a conceptual continuity in language.

    Google Scholar 

  29. W. B. Gallie, Philosophy and the Historical Understanding (London: Chatto & Windus, 1964), pp. 105f

    Google Scholar 

  30. L. Wittgenstein, On Certainty, trans. D. Paul and G. E. M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, 1969), para. 78f.

    Google Scholar 

  31. C. Wright Mills, ‘Situated Actions and Vocabularies of Motif’, in M. Shapiro (ed.), Language and Politics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1984), pp. 13f.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1994 Conal Condren

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Condren, C. (1994). Introduction. In: The Language of Politics in Seventeenth-Century England. Studies in Modern History. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-23566-7_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-23566-7_1

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, London

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-349-23568-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-1-349-23566-7

  • eBook Packages: Palgrave History CollectionHistory (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics