Skip to main content
  • 17 Accesses

Abstract

A brief summary of the results so far obtained is in order at this point. We have seen that to say a being is omniscient is to say that that being justifiably believes all and only true propositions, and to say that a being is essentially omniscient is to say that that being is necessarily such that he justifiably believes all and only true propositions. Further, we have seen the failure of the arguments for the claim that there is an incompatibility between persons’ having freedom and a being’s having essential foreknowledge of what persons will do.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 24.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. Augustine, De Trinitate, XV, 13.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologia, Ia, 14, 8.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Charles Adams and Paul Tannery (eds) Oeuvres de Descartes, 12 volumes (Paris: Leopold Cerg, 1897–1910) vol. I, p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  4. That a view of this sort might be possible is defended in Thomas V. Morris’s recent piece, ‘Necessary Beings’, Mind, 94 (1985) pp. 263–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. I intend the notion of bringing about to be understood so that there are no causally sufficient conditions for an action in question when a person can be properly said to have brought about something.

    Google Scholar 

  6. An excellent discussion of Molina’s views can be found in Robert Adams, ‘Middle Knowledge and the Problem of Evil’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (1977) pp. 109–17.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  8. David Lewis, ‘Causation’, in Sosa (ed.) Causation and Conditionals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Jonathan Bennett, ‘Counterfactuals and Temporal direction’, Philosophical Review, 93 (1984) pp. 57–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Marshall Swain, Reasons and Knowledge (Ithaca: Cornell University Press) pp. 58–65.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Adams’s account of Suarez’s position in ‘Middle Knowledge’.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Adams, p. 110. I have altered his numbering of propositions in this passage and in the others which I shall quote to accord with mine.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., p. 111.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Adams gives the following locations for counter-examples to the law of CEM: Lewis, Counterfactuals, pp. 79f., and John Pollock, ‘Four Kinds of Conditionals’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 12 (1975) p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Adams, p. 111.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Adams, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Note that the ‘because’ in these explanations is not causal.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Anthony Kenny, The God of the Philosophers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., pp. 68–71.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Adams, pp. 113–14.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1986 Jonathan L. Kvanvig

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kvanvig, J.L. (1986). The Nature of God’s Knowledge. In: The Possibility of an All-Knowing God. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-18437-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics