Skip to main content

Speech, Expression, and the Sense of History

  • Chapter
Maurice Merleau-Ponty

Part of the book series: Theoretical Traditions in the Social Sciences ((TTSS))

  • 21 Accesses

Abstract

Few concerns play as central a role in the evolution of Merleau-Ponty’s thought as the problem of expression. His inquiries took him beyond linguistics and aesthetics to grapple with questions that were basic to his studies of politics, society, and history. He hoped that by turning to the models suggested by linguistics and aesthetics he could acquire the categories needed to understand the social world and thus bring to completion the project he had begun with The Structure of Behaviour and the Phenomenology of Perception. But his attempt to elaborate a theory of expression ultimately led him to question the standpoint he had adopted in his first two books and thus to submit his entire project to radical criticism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. PrP, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  2. PrP, pp. 12–13.

    Google Scholar 

  3. PrP, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  4. SNS, p. 94, ft. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  5. PrP, pp. 7–9.

    Google Scholar 

  6. PrP, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Husserl’s essay was, as noted above, first published in the 1939 issue of the Revue internationale de philosophie devoted to Husserl. It has been translated as an appendix to the Crisis (pp. 353–78).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Crisis, pp. 354–5, 377–8.

    Google Scholar 

  9. PW, p. xvi.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Jean-Paul Sartre, What is Literature?, trans. B. Frechtman (New York: Harper & Row, 1965) p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., pp. 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid, pp. 7, 9, 3–4. For discussions of Sartre’s argument, see Joseph P. Fell, Heidegger and Sartre (New York: Columbia University Press, 1979) pp. 268–301; Aronson, pp. 122–53. and LaCapra, pp. 63–91.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Kurt Goldstein, ‘L’Analyse de l’aphasie et l’etude de l’essence du langage’, Journal de Psychologie Normale et Pathologique, 30 (1933) pp. 430–96; Kurt Goldstein and Adhémar Gelb, ‘Uber Farbennamenamnesie’, Psychologische Forschung, 6 (1924) pp. 127–86; and Roman Jakobson, Child Language, Aphasia, and Phonological Universals, trans. A. R. Keiler (The Hague: Mouton, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Wallon, Les origines; Guillaume, Imitation in Children; and Jean Piaget, The Language and Thought of the Child, trans. M. and R. Gabain (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1932). Piaget, it should be mentioned, succeeded Merleau-Ponty at the Sorbonne and has recalled that when he corrected his first set of examinations ‘some candidates, not noticing that the professor had changed, explained that Piaget had understood nothing whatever, “as M. Merleau-Ponty has demonstrated” ’. See Piaget, Insights and Illusions of Philosophy, trans. W. Mays (New York: Meridian, 1971) p. 24. For Gustave Guillaume, see L’architectonique du temps dans les langues classique (Copenhagen, 1945).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Roland Barthes, Elements of Semiology, p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  16. The most accessible general introduction to Saussure’s work is Jonathan Culler, Ferdinand de Saussure (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1977).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Stephen H. Watson, ‘Merleau-Ponty’s Involvement with Saussure’, in Hugh J. Silverman (ed.), Continental Philosophy in America (Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1983) suggests that Merleau-Ponty was aware of Saussure’s work as early as 1935 when he assisted Aron Gurwitsch on his article ‘Psychologie de langage’, Revue Philosophique de la France et de ΓEtranger, LXX (1935) pp. 399–439. Gurwitsch makes, however, only a passing reference to Saussure in a discussion of the work of M. K. Bühler (see p. 402). Watson further suggests that Merleau-Ponty ‘probably’ was making reference to Saussure’s distinction between langue and parole in his discussion of expression in the Phenomenology of Perception (p. 196), but Merleau-Ponty garbles the distinction slightly, producing an opposition of ‘parole’ and ‘langages’. Watson does not feel that Merleau-Ponty addresses Saussure’s work ‘in its specificity’ until his 1949–50 course on Consciousness and the Acquisition of Language. See Watson, pp. 209–12.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Watson, p. 212.

    Google Scholar 

  19. ‘The Metaphysical in Man’, in SMS, esp. pp. 86–8; PW, pp. 22–46 and ff.

    Google Scholar 

  20. IPP, pp. 54–8.

    Google Scholar 

  21. TFL, pp. 5, 19–20.

    Google Scholar 

  22. SNS, pp. 86, 87; CAL, p. 97; PW, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  23. PW, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  24. PW, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Culler, p. 4, quoting Saussure’s letter of 4 January 1894 to Meillet.

    Google Scholar 

  26. IPP, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, trans. W. Baskin (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966). The Course is a compilation of Saussure’s lectures from 1906–7, 1908–9, and 1910–11 edited by his students, Charles Bally and Albert Sechehaye in 1915. Their choice and ordering of materials has been the subject of much recent discussion. For a critical edition of the Course, with helpful notes, see Saussure, Cours de linguistique générale, édition critique préparée par Tullio de Mauro (Paris: Payot, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  29. For a discussion of the various ways Saussure posed the distinction and the various ways it can be translated, see de Mauro’s note, Cours, pp. 419–27.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Course, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Course, pp. 18–19, 33; see Baskin’s note, Course, p. 32, for a discussion of Saussure’s peculiar use of the term ‘phonology’.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Course, p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Course, p. 87.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Course, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  35. For a discussion of the methodological implications of Saussure’s distinction, see Barthes, pp. 13–34.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Course, p. 79; de Mauro notes that the discussions Saussure seems to have been alluding to here were those of Menger and Schmoller (Cours, p. 451). For a critique of Saussure’s distinction which takes Marx’s critique of political economy as its model, see Jean Baudrillard, For a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign, trans. C. Levin (St Louis: Telos Press, 1981) pp. 143–63.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Course, pp. 81, 90.

    Google Scholar 

  38. James Edie, for example, offers an intelligent defence of Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation which explains everything except how Merleau-Ponty worked himself into a position where he needed such a complex argument to bail him out. Granting that the object of synchronic linguistics is of course ‘the “form” or “system” of the present state of a given language and not the speech act itself’, Edie goes on to insist that this object, nevertheless, is ‘nothing other than the presently given, incubating and changing structure of the sum total of all presently recognized acts of speaking that take place within a given community’ and hence that synchronic linguistics might well be said to be ‘nothing but the description of the structure of these acts’: see James M. Edie, Speaking and Meaning: The Phenomenology of Language (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1976) p. 219, ft.55. But did Saussure in fact see the structure of a community’s speech acts as ‘incubating and changing’? Wasn’t he concerned to stress that while what is said in speech acts varies enormously, the basic structure of a language, the social fact which allows speakers to understand one another, varies only gradually over time and never as a result of innovations intentionally introduced by speakers? We might well say that the concern of synchronic linguistics lies with the structure underlying individual speech acts, but that structure is precisely what Saussure denotes as langue. Gary Brent Madison’s explanation of how Merleau-Ponty came to identify synchrony with parole and diachrony with langue is a good deal simpler: Merleau-Ponty ‘confused’ Saussure’s arguments with von Watburg’s (Madison, p. 322, ft.1). It is difficult to believe that Merleau-Ponty would be this confused in the early 1950s after having taught several courses on Saussure. Watson offers a more convincing explanation, suggesting that Merleau-Ponty might have been seeking to follow up on Saussure’s own argument that ‘everything diachronic in language is diachronic only by virtue of speaking. It is in speaking that the germ of all change is found’ (Course, p. 98). Watson, however, does not develop the argument very far (see Watson, pp. 219–20).

    Google Scholar 

  39. TFL, pp. 19–20.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Course, pp. 65–7.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Course, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Maurice Lagueux, ‘Merleau-Ponty et la linguistique de Saussure’, pp. 357, 361.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid, pp. 362–3.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Roland Barthes, ‘The Imagination of the Sign’, in Barthes, Critical Essays, trans. R. Howard (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1972) p. 205.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid, pp. 206–8; for an example of this type of approach, see Paul Ricoeur’s contrasting of the work of M.-D. Chenu with that of Lévi-Strauss, in The Conflict of Interpretations, pp. 54–61.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Saussure, pp. 67–70; see the critique of Saussure’s more extended argument in Emile Benveniste’s famous essay ‘The Nature of the Linguistic Sign’, in Benveniste, Problems in General Linguistics, trans. M. E. Meek (Coral Gabels: University of Miami Press, 1971) pp. 43–8.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Barthes, Critical Essays, pp. 207–9.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid, p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid, p. 209.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Lagueux, p. 361.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Barthes, Critical Essays, p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid, p. 208.

    Google Scholar 

  54. PP, p. 174.

    Google Scholar 

  55. PP, pp. 193, 136, 157, 168–9.

    Google Scholar 

  56. PP, p. l97.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  58. PP, p. 183.

    Google Scholar 

  59. PP, pp. 183, 193.

    Google Scholar 

  60. PP, p. 185.

    Google Scholar 

  61. PP, p. 405.

    Google Scholar 

  62. PP, p. 193.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  64. PP, p. 177; see also PP, p. 212.

    Google Scholar 

  65. PP, p. 430; see also PP, p. 253, ‘the very significance of the object… must be linked to its orientation, as indeed is indicated by the double usage of the French word sens’.

    Google Scholar 

  66. PP, p. 176.

    Google Scholar 

  67. PP, p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  68. PP, p. 429.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  70. PP, pp. 185–6.

    Google Scholar 

  71. For an analysis of gestures which proceeds from a rather different set of assumptions, see Julia Kristeva, Semioticé: Recherches pour une sémanalyse (Paris: Seuil, 1969) pp. 90–112.

    Google Scholar 

  72. PP, pp. 186–7.

    Google Scholar 

  73. PP, pp. 196–7; it should again be noted that Saussure distinguishes between parole and langue and reserves the term langage to refer to the fusion of the two.

    Google Scholar 

  74. PP, p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  76. PP, p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  78. See Heidegger, Being and Time, pp. 211–14.

    Google Scholar 

  79. PP, pp. 187–8.

    Google Scholar 

  80. PP, p. 187; cf. CAL, p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  81. PrP, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  83. SNS, p. l9.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  85. SNS, p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  86. SNS, p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  87. SNS, pp. 37, 40.

    Google Scholar 

  88. SNS, pp. 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Η&, pp. 62, 7–12, 15.

    Google Scholar 

  90. H&T, pp. 52, 55, 62–3.

    Google Scholar 

  91. H&T, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  92. H&T, p. 100; cf. Koestler, Darkness at Noon, trans. D. Hardy (New York: Modern Library, 1941) pp. 82–3.

    Google Scholar 

  93. H&T, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  94. H&T, pp. 95, 65–6.

    Google Scholar 

  95. H&T, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  96. H&T, pp. 61–2.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Stephen F. Cohen, Bukharin and the Bolshevik Revolution (New York: Vintage, 1975) pp. 359–63.

    Google Scholar 

  98. See Roy A. Medvedev, Let History Judge: The Origins and Consequences of Stalinism, trans. C. Taylor (New York: Vintage, 1973) pp. 349–54, 464–5.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Cohen, pp. 373–4.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Cohen, p. 377; see also his meticulous analysis of Bukharin’s testimony, pp. 377–80; for the arrest of Bukharin’s wife and his son, see p. 375. They were released twenty years after his execution.

    Google Scholar 

  101. PP, p. 448.

    Google Scholar 

  102. PP, pp. 448–9.

    Google Scholar 

  103. PP, p. 450.

    Google Scholar 

  104. For an earlier discussion of Marx’s philosophy of history, see ‘Concerning Marxism’, in SNS, pp. 99–124.

    Google Scholar 

  105. H&T, p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  106. H&T, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  107. H&T, p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  108. H&T, pp. 129–30.

    Google Scholar 

  109. H&T, p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  110. H&T, pp. 155–6.

    Google Scholar 

  111. H&T, p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  112. SNS, p. 121.

    Google Scholar 

  113. SNS, pp. 121–2.

    Google Scholar 

  114. H&T, pp. l18–9.

    Google Scholar 

  115. AD, pp. 230–2.

    Google Scholar 

  116. PP, p. 450.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Kojève, Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, pp. 29–30; Georg Lukács, History and Class Consciousness, trans. R. Livingston (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1971) pp. 121, 142, 147, 159.

    Google Scholar 

  118. For a discussion of these tensions, see James Miller, History and Human Existence: From Marx to Merleau-Ponty (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1979) pp. 207–19.

    Google Scholar 

  119. IPP, p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  121. IPP, p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  122. IPP, pp. 53–4.

    Google Scholar 

  123. IPP, pp. 55–6.

    Google Scholar 

  124. CAL, p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  125. IPP, p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  126. IPP, p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  127. PrP, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  128. Lefort, ‘Editor’s Preface’ to PW, p. xxiv; see also the anticipations of these discussions in PW, pp. 83–4, 112–13.

    Google Scholar 

  129. PW, pp. 3–6.

    Google Scholar 

  130. PW, pp. 31–3, 36.

    Google Scholar 

  131. PW, pp. 43, 36.

    Google Scholar 

  132. See the discussion of Sartre in PW, pp. 61–2.

    Google Scholar 

  133. The relationship of ‘Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence’ to The Prose of the World is as follows. The essay begins with a long section on signs which is essentially a summary of the second chapter of The Prose of the World (cf. S, pp. 39–44 and PW, pp. 22–43). This is followed by a discussion of Malraux’s writings on painting (5, pp. 45–76) which is taken, with only a few stylistic modifications, from the book (see PW, pp. 43–88). This, in turn, is followed by a discussion of the parallels between writing and painting (5, pp. 76–82) which is taken, with considerable editing, from PW, pp. 89–113. One section not taken over into ‘Indirect Language’, a discussion of problems in the writing of histories of philosophy (with particular reference to Descartes), bears a certain resemblance to Merleau-Ponty’s later essay on the problem of treating philosophers historically: ‘Everywhere and Nowhere’ (cf. PW, pp. 91–9 and S, pp. 126–33, 147–52).

    Google Scholar 

  134. PW, pp. 123–4; see also the summary in PrP, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  135. The most important aspects of this discussion have been analysed above in Chapter 3.

    Google Scholar 

  136. PW, pp. 147–52; Merleau-Ponty had discussed the parallels between drawing and language acquisition in CAL, pp. 11 and 61.

    Google Scholar 

  137. PW, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  138. TFL, pp. 27–38; see Métraux’s notes in Vorlesungen, pp. 284–5, for a discussion of the relationship of the course to Merleau-Ponty’s earlier writings.

    Google Scholar 

  139. Kruks ignores the book altogether, as does Cooper. Spurling’s discussion of language is confined almost exclusively to the Phenomenology of Perception (pp. 48–75) and Rahil’s work was published before The Prose of the World was available. There is a suggestive discussion of the relation between Merleau-Ponty’s notion of ‘instruction’ and his philosophy of expression in O’Neill, pp. 46–64, which draws on ‘Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence’.

    Google Scholar 

  140. PW, p. 31; cf. pp. 33, 115 and CAL, pp. 28–9.

    Google Scholar 

  141. PW, pp. 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  142. PW, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  144. PW, p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  145. PW, pp. 31–2; 116.

    Google Scholar 

  146. S, p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  147. S, pp. 41–2; cf. CAL, p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  148. 5, pp. 44–5; PW, p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  149. PW, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  150. PW, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  151. PW, p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  152. S, pp. 54–5, 75–6; PW, pp. 60–1, 87–8.

    Google Scholar 

  153. S, p. 55; PW, p. 61.

    Google Scholar 

  154. S, p. 81; PW, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  155. For a discussion of the treatment of questions of reference in structuralist approaches to language, see Paul Ricoeur, ‘Structure, Word, Event’, in The Conflict of Interpretations, pp. 84–5.

    Google Scholar 

  156. By ‘object’, Saussure meant the telos towards which a science moves, as opposed to the ‘material’ which a number of sciences can share; see de Mauro’s note, Cours, pp. 414–5.

    Google Scholar 

  157. CAL, p. 101.

    Google Scholar 

  158. PW, p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  159. AD, p. 19; see the parallel discussion in ‘Everywhere and Nowhere’, S, pp. 126–7.

    Google Scholar 

  160. 4D, pp. 3–4.

    Google Scholar 

  161. S, p. 73; PW, p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  162. Barthes, Elements of Semiology, pp. 23–5 (the discussion, however, misses the point of Merleau-Ponty’s use of the concept of ‘advent’ and presents him as simply reiterating the distinction between structure and event); and Ricoeur, Conflict of Interpretations, pp. 86–8.

    Google Scholar 

  163. Fernand Braudel, On History, trans. S. Matthews (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980) pp. 27–34, 74–6.

    Google Scholar 

  164. S, pp. 60–2, 68–70; PW, pp. 71–2, 80–3.

    Google Scholar 

  165. Ricoeur, Objectivity and Subjectivity in History’, in History and Truth, pp. 33–6. The essay dates from 1952; Merleau-Ponty attributes the notion to Ricoeur in ‘Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence’ but does not cite the article itself.

    Google Scholar 

  166. Crisis, p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  167. Ibid, pp. 354, 359.

    Google Scholar 

  168. S, p. 59; PW, p. 68. The term is defined (‘fondation ou éstablissement’) only in ‘Indirect Language and the Voices of Silence’. The words ‘foundation, institution’ which follow the German term in PW, p. 68, have been added by the translator.

    Google Scholar 

  169. PW, p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  170. S, p. 60; PW, p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  171. PW, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  172. PW, pp. 23, 36 (both are marginal notes to the text).

    Google Scholar 

  173. S, p. 61; PW, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  174. 5, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  175. S, p. 61; PW, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  176. AD, pp. 16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  177. Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of Weber’s account of rationalisation was guided by Karl Löwith’s great 1932 essay, Max Weber and Karl Marx, trans. H. Fantel (London: Allen & Unwin, 1982).

    Google Scholar 

  178. AD, p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  179. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  180. AD, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  181. AD, p. ll; cf. the discussions of Weber in Alfred Schutz, The Phenomenology of the Social World, pp. 31–8; 234–6.

    Google Scholar 

  182. Weber, Economy and Society, ed. G. Roth and C. Wittich (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978) pp. 3–26. It is this discussion which serves as the basis for Schutz’s analysis.

    Google Scholar 

  183. AD, pp. 13–14.

    Google Scholar 

  184. AD, p. 13; cf. Schutz, Phenomenology, pp. 224–9.

    Google Scholar 

  185. S, p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  186. Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans. T. Parsons (New York: Scribner, 1958) p. 175; see AD, p. 15. Weber’s footnote to the Wesley quotation is worth noting as it bears out Merleau-Ponty’s reading rather nicely: ‘The reading of this passage may be recommended to all those who consider themselves today better informed on these matters than the leaders and contemporaries of the movements themselves. As we see, they knew very well what they were doing and what dangers they faced’: Weber, Protestant Ethic, p. 280. See also Merleau-Ponty’s discussion of Lucien Febvre’s study of Rabelais in SNS, p. 92, for a similar argument.

    Google Scholar 

  187. AD, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  188. AD, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  189. AD, p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  190. AD, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  191. PW, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  192. AD, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  193. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  194. AD, pp. 30–31.

    Google Scholar 

  195. Paul Breines and Andrew Arato described Adventures of the Dialectic as ‘the most lucid brief commentary on History and Class Consciousness’. See The Young Lukàcs and the Origins of Western Marxism (New York: Seabury, 1979) p. 220.

    Google Scholar 

  196. The earliest citation of History and Class Consciousness comes in an article from 1946 (SNS, p. 126) but it is likely that he read the book much earlier. In the same year, he and Lukács were present at the Recontre Internationales de Genève, although at this point Lukács had renounced his earlier work and devoted his talk to a critique of ‘irrational’ and ‘aristocratic’ doctrines such as the writings of Nietzsche and Spengler, which brought on a series of exchanges with Karl Jaspers; Merleau-Ponty, who had delivered a talk at the meetings which stressed the importance of Husserl’s Crisis of the European Sciences for a renovation of the concept of reason, responded to the Lukács-Jaspers exchange with an attempt to recall certain of the dimensions of voluntarism and contingency which had stood at the centre of Lukács’s 1923 discussion of Marx; see VEsprit européen. Recontres internationales de Genève (Neuchátel: Editions de la Baconniére, 1947) pp. 74–7, 252–6. See also Merleau-Ponty’s 1949 note on one of Lukács’s many self-criticisms and disavowals of his earlier work, reprinted in S, pp. 261–2.

    Google Scholar 

  197. AD, p. 30; for Lukács’s own account, see ‘Mein Weg zur Marx’, in Lukács, Schriften zur Ideologie und Politik (Neuwied: Luchterhand, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  198. AD, pp. 30, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  199. AD, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  200. AD, pp. 30–1.

    Google Scholar 

  201. AD, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  202. AD, p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  203. AD, pp. 35–6; in the passages that follow I have retained Merleau-Ponty’s own translation of the German as ’devenir-société de la société’. Merleau-Ponty’s English translator employs a translation based on the German: ‘the socialization of society’.

    Google Scholar 

  204. AD, p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  205. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  206. AD, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  207. AD, pp. 38, 57.

    Google Scholar 

  208. AD, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  209. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  210. AD, p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  211. AD, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  212. AD, p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  213. AD, p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  214. AD, pp. 51–3.

    Google Scholar 

  215. AD, p. 57; for a discussion of the fate of the book, see Arato and Breines, pp. 163–89.

    Google Scholar 

  216. AD, p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  217. AD, pp. 61–2.

    Google Scholar 

  218. AD, p. 62.

    Google Scholar 

  219. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  220. AD, p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  221. AD, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  222. For the relation of the two books, see Arato and Breines, pp. 170–5.

    Google Scholar 

  223. AD, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  224. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  225. AD, p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  226. AD, pp. 64–5.

    Google Scholar 

  227. AD, p. 221.

    Google Scholar 

  228. AD, pp. 72–3.

    Google Scholar 

  229. AD, p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  230. AD, p. 221.

    Google Scholar 

  231. AD, p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  232. See the Introduction to Signs: ‘Man is hidden, well hidden, and this time we must make no mistake about it: this does not mean that he is there beneath the mask, ready to appear … there are no faces underneath the masks, historical man has never been human, and yet no man is alone’ (S, pp. 33–4).

    Google Scholar 

  233. AD, p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  234. AD, p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  235. S, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  236. S, p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  237. PW, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  238. S, p. 70; PW, p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  239. See the qualifying statements in the text and the marginal note in PW, pp. 80–1.

    Google Scholar 

  240. S, p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  241. S, p. 67; PW, p. 78; PW, pp. 18, 123.

    Google Scholar 

  242. PP, p. 402.

    Google Scholar 

  243. PP, p. 403.

    Google Scholar 

  244. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  245. See Stephen Watson, ‘Pretexts: Language, Perception, and the Cogito in Merleau-Ponty’s Thought’, in Sallis (ed.), Merleau-Ponty: Perception, Structure, Language, pp. 149, 153; see alsoPP, p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  246. VI, p. 171.

    Google Scholar 

  247. VI, p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  248. VI, pp. 171, 179.

    Google Scholar 

  249. VI, p. l79.

    Google Scholar 

  250. VI, p. 176.

    Google Scholar 

  251. VI, p. 201.

    Google Scholar 

  252. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  253. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  254. VI, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  255. VI, p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  256. VI, p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  257. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  258. VI, pp. 154–5.

    Google Scholar 

  259. VI, p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  260. VI, p. 224.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1985 James Schmidt

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schmidt, J. (1985). Speech, Expression, and the Sense of History. In: Maurice Merleau-Ponty. Theoretical Traditions in the Social Sciences. Palgrave, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-17869-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics