Skip to main content

The Role of a Law Lord: Conflict and Change

  • Chapter
The Law Lords

Part of the book series: Oxford Socio-Legal Studies ((OSLS))

  • 18 Accesses

Abstract

Decision-making in the Lords involves group and community processes quite apart from those adverted to in the last chapter. This is because, as we saw earlier,2 a Law Lord is influenced not just by his own conception of his role but also by his fellow Law Lords and their predecessors, and to a lesser extent by other groups in the wider legal and non-legal community. ‘Pivotal’ to his role when deciding an appeal is the expectation, held within and without the legal community, that he should justify his decision by reasoned argument. Furthermore, within the legal community itself there are more or less shared understandings as to what constitutes a valid and acceptable argument for a Law Lord to employ, and as to what standards he may relevantly appeal when justifying his decision.3 Such understandings are in no small way the product of a common socialisation pattern, a traditional training with a received body of knowledge and learning.4 Indeed it has been argued that such traditional practices and ideas, nurtured by a legal caste, are the very essence of the common law.5

It is no doubt unsafe to generalise about judicial process. For after all it is a generalisation about the work of individual men. In no field of special knowledge does one man pursue its technique or exercise its art precisely in the same way as another .… There is no place where the inequalities and variations of men can be seen more clearly than when the men are up on a Bench

Sir Owen Dixon, ‘Concerning Judicial Method’1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 19.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. See Prott, loc. cit., and MacCormick, op. cit., chap. I.

    Google Scholar 

  2. A. W. B. Simpson, ‘The Common Law and Legal Theory’ in A. W. B. Simpson (ed.), Oxford Essays in Jurisprudence, Second Series (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See R. Dworkin, ‘Hard Cases’, 88 Harv. L.R.. (1975) 1057 and

    Google Scholar 

  4. J. Esser, Vorverstandnis und Methodenwahl in der Rechtsfindung (Frankfurt: Athenaum Verlag, 1970) reviewed by

    Google Scholar 

  5. L. V. Prott ‘Updating the Judicial “Hunch”’, 26 A.J.C.L.. (1978) 461.

    Google Scholar 

  6. R. W. M. Dias, Jurisprudence, 4th edn (London: Butterworths, 1976) p. 279.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Reported in M. Zander (ed.), Whats Wrong with the Law (London: BBC Publications, 1970) p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Roscoe Pound, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Law (Yale University Press, 1922) p. 19. See in similar vein,

    Google Scholar 

  9. W. Friedmann, ‘Judges, Politics and the Law’, 29 Can. B. Rev. (1951) 811 at p. 837.

    Google Scholar 

  10. J. Stone, Legal Systems and Lawyers’ Reasonings (London: Stevens, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Lord Reid, ‘The Law and the Reasonable Man’, LIV Proceedings of the British Academy (1968) at pp. 191 and 193.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Lord Radcliffe, The Law and its Compass (London: Faber and Faber, 1961) pp. 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  13. On the ‘all or nothing’ character of judicial decision-making and the contrast between a mediator and an adjudicator, see inter alia V. Aubert, ‘Law as a Way of Resolving Conflicts’ in L. Nader (ed.), Law in Culture and Society (Chicago Aldine Publishing Co., 1969) p. 282 and

    Google Scholar 

  14. T. Eckhoff, ‘The Mediator, the Judge and the Administrator in Conflict-resolution’, 10 Acta Sociologica (1967) 148.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Quoted by Frankfurter J, ‘The Social Views of Mr Justice Brandeis’ in E. Pollock (ed.), The Brandeis Reader (New York: Oceana Publications, 1956) p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See K. Vines ‘The Judicial Role in the American States’, J. Grossman and J. Tanenhaus (eds), Frontiers of Judicial Research (New York: John Wiley and Sons, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Pierre J. J. Olivier, Legal Fictions in Practice and Legal Science (Rotterdam University Press, 1975) p. 150. See also

    Google Scholar 

  18. Lon Fuller, Legal Fictions (Stanford University Press, 1967) p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  19. E. Goffman, ‘Role Distance’ in Encounters (London: Allen Lane, The Penguin Press, 1972) p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See R. Cross, Precedent in English Law, 3rd edn (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1977) pp. 35–7.

    Google Scholar 

  21. In E. London (ed.), The Law as Literature (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1960) p. 692. See also Buckley and Phillimore LJJ in Olympia Oil v. Produce Brokers at p. 750.

    Google Scholar 

  22. For an attack on this passive response see Lord Denning, The Road to Justice (London: Stevens, 1955) pp. 1–2.

    Google Scholar 

  23. The phrase is taken from Stevens, ‘The Role of A Final Appeal Court in a Democracy’, 28 M.L.R. (1965) 509 at p. 519. A similar observation was made in a book review by W. Friedmann in 15 M.L.R. (1952) 386 at p. 389.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Viscount Jowitt, 25 Austr. L.J. (1951) at p. 296.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Lord Cohen, ‘The Court of Appeal’, 11 C.L.J. (1951) 3 at pp. 13–14.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Thus a ‘passive’ approach to a precedent is one which demonstrates a preference for certainty and treating like cases alike as opposed to paying heed to the merits of the case and different social conditions. In this way an attempt to evade a precedent in order to do justice in the individual case is always activist. Similarly a preference for a flexible principle as opposed to a precedent is a creative preference. I would not deny that I had been using the terms evaluatively; they could equally well apply to a decision to stand by a precedent. (See Palley, op. cit., p. 58 and V. Radcliffe, book review 36 M.L.R. (1973) 559 at p. 563.)

    Google Scholar 

  27. In J. D. Wilson, Milestones on the Dover Road (London: Faber and Faber, 1969) p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  28. R. Cross, Precedent in English Law (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961) p. 17. See also p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See Lord Denning, ‘The Need for a New Equity’ in 5 C.L.P. (1952) 1.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Lord Radcliffe, The Law and Its Compass (London: Faber and Faber, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., p. 39. See also his comments in ‘Law and Order’, 61 Law Societys Gazette (1964) 821.

    Google Scholar 

  32. ‘The Lawyer and His Times’, pp. 14–15 in A. Sutherland (ed.), The Path of the Law from1967 (Harvard University Press, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Lord Radcliffe’s approach (which I shall hereafter call the ‘facade’ approach) has been accused of exhibiting ‘contempt for the democratic process’, by Professor Palley in ‘Decision-making in the Area of Public Order by English Courts’, p. 67. It has also attracted criticism from Professor Jaffe in English and American Judges as Lawmakers (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1969) pp. 7–8; Robert Stevens in ‘The Role of a Final Appeal Court in a Democracy’ pp. 535–7; and P. S. Atiyah in ‘Judges and Policy’, 15 Israel L.R. (1980) 346.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Professor Lloyd, Introduction to Jurisprudence, 2nd edn (London: Stevens & Sons, 1965) p. 377.

    Google Scholar 

  35. C. K. Allen, 81 L.Q.R. (1965) pp. 36 and 37.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See ‘Precedent in English and Continental Law’, 50 L.Q.R. (1934) 40; ‘Precedents in the Court of Appeal’, 9 C.L.J. (1947) 349; and ‘Precedents in Divisional Courts’, 64 L.Q.R. (1948) 40. Several previous Law Lords (apart from Lords Reid and Denning) had indicated their dislike of the doctrine or had even asserted that it did not really exist. E.g., Lord Wright, ‘Precedents’, 8 C.L.J. (1963) 144;

    Google Scholar 

  37. Lord Evershed in The Court of Appeal in England (London: Athlone Press, 1950) pp. 17–18; and

    Google Scholar 

  38. Lord Cohen in ‘The Court of Appeal’, 11 C.L.J. (1951) at p. 11. Surprisingly Lord Atkin was not in this camp (see his obituary written by Lord Wright in XXXII Proceedings of the British Academy (1946) 307 at pp. 316–17.

    Google Scholar 

  39. E.g. G. Williams in the 11th edn of Salmond on Jurisprudence (London: Sweet & Maxwell, 1957) at pp. 175–88 and 538–9; Cross, Precedent in English Law, 1st edn, p. 250; R. Dias, Jurisprudence, 2nd edn (London: Butterworth, 1964) p. 75; G. Paton, Jurisprudence, 2nd edn (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1951) pp. 162–3; and P. Fitzgerald, Salmond on Jurisprudence, 12th edn (London: Sweet and Maxwell, 1966) p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  40. For further details see 83 L. Q R. (1967) 176–7; T. B. Smith, ‘Authors and Authority’, 12 J.S.P.T.L. (1972) 3 at p. 5; and

    Google Scholar 

  41. L. Scarman ‘Law Reform — Lessons from English Experience’, 3 Manitoba L.J. (1968) 47 at p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  42. See Gardiner and Martin (eds), Law Reform NOW (London: Gollancz, 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  43. This of course was a problem which greatly exercised the commentators both before and after the Statement. See e.g. Julius Stone in ‘1966 and All That!’, 69 Columba L. R. (1969) 1163 at p. 1168 and the Bar Council statements quoted in the New York Times, 27 July 1966, p. 1. As we saw earlier (see p. 22 above) counsel in Cassell v. Broome raised the question of the constitutional validity of the Practice Statement, but did not press the point.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Professor Goodhart in 82 L. Q. R. (1966) 441 at p. 444 wrote that those who contributed to the change were Sir Frederick Pollock, Lord Wright, Lord Evershed and Lord Denning. I do not deny that they may have had some influence in producing a climate receptive to the change but none of them (with the possible exception of Lord Denning) played as large a part in the events immediately prior to the change as Lord Reid did.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Jurisprudence, 4th edn, pp. 180–1. See also A. L. Goodhart in 85 L. Q. R. (1969) 171 at p. 173;

    Google Scholar 

  46. Diplock LJ in Boys v. Chaplin (1968) at p. 35; and

    Google Scholar 

  47. Salmon LJ in Gallie v. Lee (1969) at p. 49.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Cross, op. cit., p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See Fitzgerald, Salmond on Jurisprudence, pp. 160–1; Dias, Jurisprudence, 4th edn, p. 181 fn 1; and J. Stone ‘1966 and All That!’, 69 Columbia L.R. (1969) 1162 at p. 1168.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1982 Alan Paterson

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Paterson, A. (1982). The Role of a Law Lord: Conflict and Change. In: The Law Lords. Oxford Socio-Legal Studies. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-06918-7_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics