Skip to main content
  • 6 Accesses

Abstract

Sir Isaac Newton was not a particularly Hobbyhorsical character. He even expressed the opinion that his system of philosophy was not Hobbyhorsical—as for instance in Rule One, from ‘The System of the World’, Book III of the Principia: ‘We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances’.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. Isaac Newton, Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687, 3rd ed. 1726), ‘De Mundi Systemate’, Liber Tertius, Regula 1: ‘Causes rerum naturalium non plures admitti debere, quam quae et verae sint et earum phaenomenis explicandis sufficiant’.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago and London, 1962, 2nd impr. 1963), p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Christiaan Huygens, Discours de la Cause de la Pesanteur (Leyden, 1690), Oeuvres Complètes de Christiaan Huygens, publiées par la Société Hollandaise des Sciences, 22 vols. (La Haye, 1888–1950), XXI, 471, quoted by Dijksterhuis, the Mechanization of the World-Picture (trans. C. Dikshoorn, Oxford, 1961), p. 480.

    Google Scholar 

  4. George Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (1710), Section 103, ed. and intro. G. J. Warnock (London and Glasgow, 1962), 6th impr. October 1972, p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  5. John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690), Book 2, Chapter 33 (‘Concerning the Association of Ideas’), of the 4th and subsequent editions of the Essay, ed. P. H. Nidditch, Clarendon edition of the Works of John Locke, Vol. I (Oxford, 1975), pp. 394–401. (Hereafter cited as Essay.)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. The list of twenty Locke-invoking critics is given by R. S. Hafter, ‘Sterne’s Affective Art and Eighteenth-Century Psychology’ (PhD Dissertation, Brandeis, 1970), p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Other recent examples could be added to his list, e.g. Helene Moglen, The Philosophical Irony of Laurence Sterne (Florida, 1975). Hume’s three categories of association are mentioned by Hafter, pp. 156–7; they are from Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature (1739–40), Book I, Part 1, Section 4, ‘Of the Connection or Association of Ideas’, Everyman edition (London and NY, 1911), rpt. 1974, ed. and intro. A. D. Lindsay, 2 vols., Vol. I, p. 19. (Hereafter cited as Treatise.

    Google Scholar 

  8. John Passmore, Hume’s Intentions (Cambridge, 1952), revised ed. 1968, p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  9. David Hartley, Observations on Man: his Frame, his Duty, and his Expectations (1749), Part II, Chapter 2 (Proposition 28), p. 146: ‘Association, i.e. Analogy, perfect and imperfect, is the only Foundation upon which we in fact do, or can, or ought to assent’. Hardey is using the word Analogy in its sense of argument by example, rather than by proportion.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Fred Gettings, The Book of the Hand: An Illustrated History of Palmistry (1965), p. 178, paraphrasing Paracelsus.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Kenelm Digby, A Late Discourse Made in a Solemne Assembly of Nobles and Learned Men at Montpellier… Touching the Cure of WOUNDS by the Powder of Sympathy, Rendred faithfully out of French into English by R. White (1658), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ephraim Chambers, Cyclopaedia (1713), article on ‘The Powder of Sympathy’.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Tobias Smollett, The Expedition of Humphry Clinker (1771), ed. Lewis M. Knapp (1966), p. 18. The Doctor finds relief not from bad breath but from low spirits.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Richard Mead, A Mechanical Account of Poisons in Several Essays (1702), p. 15. Newton is referred to on p. 14 with reference to Bellini’s cohesion, ‘which is indeed, tho’ express’d in other words, the very same thing with the Attraction of the Particles one to another; This Mr. Newton has demonstrated to be the great Principle of Action in the Universe’.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Samuel Bowden, Introductory poem (‘To Dr. Morgan’) to Thomas Morgan’s Philosophical Principles of Medicine (1726), pp. xlv–xlvi.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Thomas Morgan, Physico-Theology (1741), p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Alexander Pope, An Essay on Man (1733–4) Epistle I, 11. 289–93, Poems, ed. John Butt (1963), 5th printing 1973, p. 515.

    Google Scholar 

  18. George Cheyne, An Essay of Health and Long Life (1724), Chapter vi, prop. 4, p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  19. William King, An Essay on the Origin of Evil… To which is prefix’d A Dissertation Concerning the Fundamental Principle and Immediate Criterion of Virtue [by J. Gay] (1739). This is not John Gay the dramatist, but John Gay, Fellow of Sidney Sussex College, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Richard A. Lanham, in ‘Tristram Shandy’: The Games of Pleasure (Berkeley, LA, and London, 1973) p. 57.

    Google Scholar 

  21. P. McReynolds, Introduction to Four Early Works on Motivation, ed. McReynolds (Gainsville, Florida, 1969), p. xvii. The reference is to Locke’s Essay, Book II, Chapter xxi (‘Of Power’), paras. 31 and 40.

    Google Scholar 

  22. S. T. Coleridge, Biographia Literaria (1817), ed. J. Shawcross (Oxford, 1907), pp. 82, 92.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Earl R. Wasserman, ‘Nature Moralized: The Divine Analogy in the Eighteenth Century,’ ELH, 20 (1953), 39–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 1982 Mark Loveridge

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Loveridge, M. (1982). Sterne and the Scientific Study of Man. In: Laurence Sterne and the Argument about Design. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-05600-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics