Skip to main content

Lawful Government and Popular Control

  • Chapter
Hobbes and Locke
  • 45 Accesses

Abstract

Locke’s reasons for introducing the concept of trust into his political philosophy are not stated as explicitly as one might wish. However, the gap can be filled by considering the context in which he uses the notion, particularly in relation to his arguments about liberty and authority.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. For an example of the same point see P. Singer, Democracy and Disobedience, Oxford, 1973, p. 25: ‘Consent, to give rise to obligations, must be voluntary ⋯’; also pp. 46–51. Compare the repeated emphasis on ‘voluntarily’ in Plamenatz’s Man and Society, vol. I, p. 240,

    Google Scholar 

  2. And J. J. Jenkins, ‘Political Consent’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 20, 1970, 65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. See R. S. Hill, ‘David Hume’, in History of Political Philosophy, ed. L. Strauss and J. Cropsey, Chicago, 1963, p. 505. For Hume see A Treatise of Human Nature, Bk. III, Pt. ii, sects. 2–4.

    Google Scholar 

  4. J. D. Mabbott, The State and the Citizen, London, 1948, p. 21. See also J. Bentham, Leading Principles of a Constitutional Code for any State, Sect. I, paras. 5, 8, and 17 (Works, ed. J. Bowring, Edinburgh, 1843, vol. II, pp. 269 f.).

    Google Scholar 

  5. The background to the whole issue concerning the relationship between law and prerogative power was the lifelong antagonism between Sir Edward Coke and Francis Bacon. Coke had been the champion of the com-mon law and was in favour of subjecting the royal prerogative to definitive legal limitations. Bacon stood for a strong royal prerogative as part of the King’s sovereignty which he considered almost unlimited. The test-case was Coke’s attempt to define the legal limits of the use of Royal Proclamations which, according to him, were not part of the law of England (statute, common law, and custom) and hence could not change the principles of common law merely by the King’s own will: ‘The King hath no prerogative but that which the law of the land allows him’. Coke’s Reports, Pt. XII, pp. 74–5, London, 1656; Collected ed. 1777 (Proclamations, 1610/11). Also J. R. Tanner, Constitutional Documents of the Reign of James I, 1603–1625, Cambridge, 1930 (2nd ed.), p. 188.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Seneca, Letter 90. See R. W. and A. J. Carlyle, A History of Mediaeval Political Theory in the West, London and New York, 1903–36, vol. I, pp. 23 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. The Political Writings of Jean Jacques Rousseau, ed. C. E. Vaughan, Cambridge, 1915, vol. I, p. 184. In the Everyman ed. of Rousseau’s Social Contract and Discourses, p. 208. For Pliny see his Panegyricus, 55, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  8. For the exercise of discretionary power (see above, p. 145) in relation to the non-arbitrary aspect of prerogative see C. J. Friedrich, ‘Authority, Reason, and Discretion’, in Authority (Nomos I), ed. C. J. Friedrich, Cambridge, (Mass.), 1958, pp. 40–5.

    Google Scholar 

  9. H. R. Fox Bourne, The Life of John Locke, London, 1876, vol. I, p. 176;

    Google Scholar 

  10. C. A. Viano, Scritti editi e inediti sulla tolleranza, Turin, 1961, p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Sect. 95, lines 11–14. For a full exposition of Locke’s argument that the theory of majority-right is logically implied in his theory of popular sovereignty see W. Kendall, ‘John Locke and the Doctrine of Majority Rule’, Illinois Studies in the Social Sciences, 26, Urbana, Ill., USA, 1941, 117–19 (partly reprinted in Life, Liberty, and Property, Essays on Locke’s Political Ideas, pp. 168–77).

    Google Scholar 

  12. C. E. Vaughan, Studies in the History of Political Philosophy before and after Rousseau, Manchester, 1925, vol. I, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Leibniz, too, appears to have adopted a theory of ‘multiple sovereignty’ in connection with his preference for the constitutional state and concern for the public good (see C. J. Friedrich, ‘Philosophical Reflections of Leibniz on Law, Politics, and the State’, Natural Law Forum, vol. 11, Notre Dame, Indiana, 1966, pp. 87–8, and n. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  14. W. J. Rees, ‘The Theory of Sovereignty Restated’, Mind, LIX, 1950 (reprinted in Philosophy, Politics, and Society, ed. P. Laslett, First Series, Oxford, 1956, ch. iv).

    Google Scholar 

  15. S. I. Benn, ‘The Uses of “Sovereignty”’, Political Studies, III, 1955 (reprinted in Political Philosophy, ed. A. Quinton, London, 1967, ch. iv).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 1981 W. von Leyden

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

von Leyden, W. (1981). Lawful Government and Popular Control. In: Hobbes and Locke. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-349-05060-4_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics