Advertisement

The Search for Middle Ground: Disease Theory as Natural History

  • Margaret DeLacy

Abstract

DeLacy depicts the effort of established Restoration authors such as Thomas Willis and Robert Boyle to find a middle position between Galenism and Helmontianism that was informed by empiricism and the “natural history” approach of Thomas Sydenham and John Locke. She finds that their compromise proved less conducive to contagionism than those of Helmontians and sectarians. The Great Plague of London in 1665 led members of the Royal Society to discuss the mechanism of disease transmission and consider whether small “insects” or “worms” might carry plague as Athanasius Kircher had thought. They also collaborated on a project on artificial languages by John Wilkins that created a new taxonomy of diseases. A new approach to disease classification also appears in William Petty’s proposal for vital statistics in Dublin.

Keywords

Contagious Disease Royal Society Rheumatic Fever Scarlet Fever Spotted Fever 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. 1.
    Robert Kargon, Atomism in England from Hariot to Newton (Oxford: 1966), 27–8, 92; Michael Hunter, Science and Society in Restoration England (Cambridge: 1981), 173–7; and Margaret J. Osler, “Baptizing Epicurean Atomism: Pierre Gassendi on the Immortality of the Soul,” in Religion, Science and Worldview, eds. Margaret J. Osler and Paul Lawrence Farber (Cambridge: 1985), 163–84. Medieval atomism is discussed in Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, eds. Christoph Lüthy, John E. Murdoch, and William R. Newman (Leiden: 2001).Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    John Yolton, Thinking Matter: Materialism in Eighteenth-Century Britain (Minneapolis: 1984), 4.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Walter Charleton, Physiologia Epicuro-Gassendo-Charletoniana (London: 1654). For Charleton’s career, see below.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Kargon, Atomism, 92. During the Interregnum, Charleton had also translated two of Van Helmont’s works. See above, and Charles Webster, The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine and Reform, 1626–1660 (New York: 1976), 272.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    Richard G. Olson, Science and Religion, 1450–1900 (Baltimore: 2004), 95–106.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Margaret Candee Jacob, “John Toland and the Newtonian Ideology,” Journal of the Warburg and Courtauld Institutes (1969) 32:309–31, on 314. On the variable meaning of “Newtonian,” see R. E. Schofield, “An Evolutionary Taxonomy of Eighteenth-Century Newtonianisms,” Studies in Eighteenth-Century Culture (1998) 7:175–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. 7.
    Richard S. Westfall, “Newton and the Hermetic Tradition,” in Science, Medicine and Society in the Renaissance, ed. Allen G. Debus (New York: 1972), 2:183–98; Antonio Clericuzio, “Gassendi, Charleton, and Boyle on Matter and Motion,” in Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, eds. Christoph Lüthy, John E. Murdoch, and William R. Newman (Leiden: 2001), 467–82; and see for example Daniel Turner, A Discourse concerning Fever. In Two Letters. The First, Dissuading from All Hypotheses and Theories, whether Physical or Mechanical … 3rd ed. (London: 1739). Turner’s own approach is best described as Sydenhamian.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Brent S. Sirota, “The Trinitarian Crisis in Church and State: Religious Controversy and the Making of the Postrevolutionary Church of England, 16871702,” Journal of British Studies (January 2013) 52, no. 1:26–54, http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/jbr.2012.7 shows how religious claims were translated into disputes over authority and ultimately into party politics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. 9.
    Minsoo Kang, “From the Man-Machine to the Automaton-Man: The Enlightenment Origins of the Mechanistic Imagery of Humanity,” in Vital Matters: Eighteenth-Century Views of Conception, Life, and Death, eds. Helen Deutsch and Mary Terrall (Toronto: 2012), 148–73, esp. 158. Kang argues that popular disillusionment with government during the War of the Austrian Succession in the 1740s led to a revival of vitalism as an alternative to the mechanism that had by then become associated with an autocratic state.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Michael Hunter, Science and Society in Restoration England (Cambridge and New York: 1981), 186–7.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    For Newton’s own belief in a nonmechanical, alchemical “vegetable spirit,” see Betty Jo Teeter Dobbs, The Janus Faces of Genius: The Role of Alchemy in Newton’s Thought (Cambridge and New York: 1991).Google Scholar
  12. 13.
    The roots of this theory lay in Greek Methodism. See Henry Cohen [Lord Cohen of Birkenhead], “The Evolution of the Concept of Disease,” Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, Section of Medicine (March 1955) 48, no. 3:155–60, on 158.Google Scholar
  13. 14.
    Theodore M. Brown, “The College of Physicians and the Acceptance of Iatro-mechanism in England, 1665–1695,” Bulletin of the History of Medicine (1970) 44:12–30; Antonio Clericuzio, “The Internal Laboratory: The Chemical Reinterpretation of Medical Spirits in England (1650–1680),” in Alchemy and Chemistry in the 16th and 17th Centuries, eds. Piyo Rattansi and Antonio Clericuzio (Dordrecht: 1994), 51–84, on 73, n. 3.Google Scholar
  14. 15.
    Walter Pagel, Joan Baptista Van Helmont (Cambridge: 1982), 30. See also Johanna Geyer-Kordesch, “Passions and the Ghost in the Machine: Or What Not to Ask about Science in Seventeenth- and Eighteenth-century Germany,” in The Medical Revolution of the Seventeenth Century, eds. Roger French and Andrew Wear (Cambridge: 1989), 145–63, on 150–1. For the hostility of the Paracelsian author Severinus to “geometrical” medicine, see Jole Shackelford, A Philosophical Path for Paracelsian Medicine, (Copenhagen: 2004), 148–9, 404.Google Scholar
  15. 16.
    Niebyl, “Science and Metaphor in the Medicine of Restoration England,” Bulletin of the History of Medicine (1973) 47:356–74, on 360.Google Scholar
  16. 17.
    David E. Shuttleton, “’A Modest Examination,’ John Arbuthnot and the Scottish Newtonians,” British Journal for Eighteenth-Century Studies (1995) 18, no. 1:47–62, on 55. Shuttleton notes that in The History of John Bull, Arbuthnot equated this sort of Baconianism with Presbyterian enthusiasm. Michael Hunter, Science and Society, 17, describes it as the “indiscriminate collecting of information relevant to no particular hypothesis.”Google Scholar
  17. 19.
    H. F. Kearney, “Puritanism, Capitalism and the Scientific Revolution,” in The Intellectual Revolution of the Seventeenth Century, ed. Charles Webster (London: 1974), 218–42, on 234–5; cf. Webster, Instauration, 305. In 1668, Boyle returned to a very different London.Google Scholar
  18. 22.
    Andrew Cunningham, “Thomas Sydenham: Epidemics, Experiment and the ‘Good Old Cause,’” in French and Wear, Medical Revolution, 181–2. On chemistry and the “craftsman and scholar” thesis in the history of science, see Ursula Klein, “Apothecary-Chemists in Eighteenth-Century Germany,” in New Narratives in Eighteenth-Century Chemistry, ed. Lawrence Principe (Dordrecht: 2007), 97–137, esp. 128–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 23.
    Robert G. Frank, Jr., “The Physician as Virtuoso in Seventeenth-Century England,” in English Scientific Virtuosi in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries, eds. Barbara Shapiro and Robert G. Frank, Jr., (Los Angeles: 1979), 57–119, on 92, and see the table in Webster, Instauration, 166–9.Google Scholar
  20. 24.
    Robert G. Frank, Jr., Harvey and the Oxford Physiologists (Berkeley: 1980), Table 3, 63–89.Google Scholar
  21. 25.
    Toby Barnard, “Petty, Sir William (1623–1687),” ODNB (Oxford: 2004) online edn., May 2007 at http://www.oxforddnb.com/view/article/22069.Google Scholar
  22. 26.
    J. R. Partington, A History of Chemistry, vol. 2 (London: 1961), 487. See also Barbara Beguin Kaplan, Divulging of Useful Truths in Physick: The Medical Agenda of Robert Boyle (Baltimore: 1993).Google Scholar
  23. 27.
    Allen G. Debus, “Thomas Sherley’s ‘Philosophical Essay’ (1672): Helmontian Mechanism as the Basis of a New Philosophy,” Ambix (July 1980) 27:124–35; W. R. Newman, “The Corpuscular Transmutational Theory of Eirenaeus Philalethes,” in Rattansi and Clericuzio, Alchemy and Chemistry, 161–82. Philalethes was the pseudonym of the American George Starkey, a member of the Hartlib circle, who worked closely with Boyle and Newton.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. 29.
    The Philosophical Works of the Honorable Robert Boyle … ed. and abridged by Peter Shaw (London: 1725), 3:85.Google Scholar
  25. 30.
    On Willis, see Carl Zimmer, Soul Made Flesh: The Discovery of the Brain and How It Changed the World (New York: 2004). On the interest of members of this circle in a “vital agent,” see Antonio Clericuzio, “The Internal Laboratory. The Chemical Reinterpretation of Medical Spirits in England (1650–1680),” in Rattansi and Clericuzio, Alchemy and Chemistry, 51–83.Google Scholar
  26. 32.
    L. J. Rather, “Pathology at Mid-Century: A Reassessment of Thomas Willis and Thomas Sydenham,” in Medicine in Seventeenth-Century England, ed. Allen Debus (Berkeley: 1974), 71–112, on 83. Fracastoro also likened diseases to ferments, but for him it was a metaphor whereas Willis meant it literally.Google Scholar
  27. 33.
    Thomas Willis, De Fermentatione (1659) trans. as “A Medical-Philosophical Discourse of Fermentation, or, Of the Intestine Motion of Particles in every Body,” in Dr. Willis’s Practice of Physic … trans. S[amuel] P[ordage] (London: 1681), 1. See also Alfred White Franklin, “Clinical Medicine,” in Debus, Medicine in Seventeenth-Century England, 128–9. Franklin comments that Willis “could not escape from that compulsion to search for reasonable explanations, implanted by his Oxford education which still imposed the medical gospels of Aristotle and Galen.”Google Scholar
  28. 35.
    Rather, “Pathology,” 83. Leeuwenhoek had seen yeast but did not realize it was alive. The living nature of yeast was demonstrated by Charles Caignard-Latour, Theodor Schwann, and F. Kuetzing independently in 1837. Maximillian Joseph Herzon, A Text-Book on Disease-Producing Microorganisms (Philadelphia: 1910), 20. See also Ralph Major, “Agostino Bassi and the Parasitic Theory of Disease,” Bulletin of the History of Medicine (1944) 16:99–105.Google Scholar
  29. 36.
    We use specific yeasts for specific purposes, but that was not the case in the seventeenth century. Restoration bakers often used the barm skimmed from brewing to make bread. The Paris Faculty of Medicine recommended banning added leavens in bread-making as unhealthful, thinking that bread should be left to rise from sourdough or by itself (aided, unbeknownst to them, by wild yeasts in the air). Elizabeth David, English Bread and Yeast Cookery (London: 1978), 90–1, 98–100.Google Scholar
  30. 37.
    Stephen Gaukroger, The Collapse of Mechanism and the Rise of Sensibility (Oxford: 2010), 91 and see also 93. See also Anna Marie Roos, The Salt of the Earth: Natural Philosophy, Medicine and Chymistry in England, 1650–1750 (Leiden: 2007), 116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. 38.
    Rather, “Pathology,” 85; Donald G. Bates, “Thomas Willis and the Epidemic Fever of 1661: A Commentary,” Bulletin of the History of Medicine (1965) 39, no. 5:393–414.Google Scholar
  32. 40.
    The entry for Sydenham in Wikipedia quotes word for word an unsigned article in the eleventh edition of the Encyclopedia Britannica (1911) retained from the 1887 edition: “Sydenham’s nosological method is essentially the modern one.” Even if “modern” refers to the dawn of the twentieth century, this is mistaken, but it has been repeated often. See also Knud Faber, Nosography: The Evolution of Clinical Medicine in Modern Times (New York: 1930); Arthur M Silverstein, A History of Immunology (Oxford: 1989), 89; William Bynum, “Nosology,” in Companion Encyclopedia of the History of Medicine, eds. William F. Bynum and Roy Porter (London: 2004), 1:335–6; and Lennart Nordenfelt, “Identification and Classification of Diseases: Fundamental Problems in Medical Ontology and Epistemology,” Studia Philosophica Estonica (2013) 6, no. 2:6–21, published online May 2013.Google Scholar
  33. 41.
    Thomas Sydenham, preface to the third edition of Medical Observations concerning the History and the Cure of Acute Diseases in The Works of Thomas Sydenham, M.D., ed. R. G. Latham, trans. from the Latin ed. of Dr. Greenhill (London: 1848, rpt. 1979, 2 vols. in 1), 1:16. For problems with this edition, see G. G. Meynell, “John Locke and the Preface to Thomas Sydenham’s Observationes Medicae,” Medical History (2006) 50, no. 1:93–110.Google Scholar
  34. 47.
    Charles-Edward-Amory Winslow, The Conquest of Epidemic Disease (Madison: 1980), 173.Google Scholar
  35. 49.
    Kenneth D. Keele, “The Sydenham-Boyle Theory of Morbific Particles,” Medical History (1974) 18:240–8, on 246. Cf. the comment of Charles Goodall in a letter of 1680 that fevers “derive their original not from any vitious humors contained in the blood, but from a seminium febrile conveyed into it from the Monos-sphere”; Audrey Davis, “Some Implications of the Circulation Theory for Disease Theory and Treatment in the Seventeenth Century,” Journal of the History of Medicine (1971) 26, no. 1:28–39, on 37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. 50.
    See L. J. Rather, “Towards a Philosophical Study of the Idea of Disease,” in The Historical Development of Physiological Thought, eds. C. M. Brooks and P. F. Cranefield (New York: 1959), 351–73, esp. 356–8.Google Scholar
  37. 52.
    Lester S. King, The Medical World of the Eighteenth Century (Chicago: 1958), 195; and see A. J. Cain, “Logic and Memory in Linnaeus’s System of Taxonomy,” Proc. Linnean Society of London, Session 1956–7 (April 1958), 169 pts. 1 and 2:144–63, esp. 145–6, “the differentia is not extraneously attached to the genus; it is a particular mode in which the genus may exist.”Google Scholar
  38. 55.
    Sydenham, Medical Observations, in Works, 1:38–9. Many historians have expressed confusion or frustration about Sydenham’s theory of smallpox. Lise Wilkinson, “The Development of the Virus Concept … 5. Smallpox and the Evolution of Ideas on Acute (Viral) Infections,” Medical History (1979) 3:1–28, comments on 1–2 that “Sydenham’s … still valid directions for the treatment of smallpox patients were not matched by clarity of thought on the subject of the aetiology of the disease.”CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. 57.
    See Andreas-Holger Maehle, Drugs on Trial: Experimental Pharmacology and Therapeutic Innovation in the Eighteenth Century (Amsterdam: 1999), 237. He discusses the later transformation of cinchona from a specific to a general medicine on 258 and 286–7.Google Scholar
  40. 58.
    Locke obtained an MB from Oxford, where he had studied with Willis and Boyle. He became Sydenham’s pupil in 1667. Cunningham writes that Locke’s influence led Sydenham to conclude by 1676 that “in medicine there can be no useful discussion at all about cause.” Cunningham, “Sydenham,” 184. Niebyl comments: “Locke, like the Helmontians, believed in an unbridgeable gap between the artificial and the natural,” “Science and Metaphor,” 371. See also James Herbert Dempster, “John Locke, Physician and Philosopher,” Annals of Medical History (1932) n. s. 4:12–59. Kenneth Dewhurst, John Locke (1632–1704): Physician and Philosopher: A Medical Biography with an Edition of the Medical Notes in His Journals (London: 1963), 27, noted that Locke’s early manuscripts include references to the work of Gideon Harvey.Google Scholar
  41. 59.
    J. R. Milton, “Locke, Medicine and the Mechanical Philosophy,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy (2001) 9:221–43. For an opposing view, see Joseph Frank Payne, Thomas Sydenham (London: 1900), 244–9, but this appeared before many of Locke’s manuscript works became available.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. 60.
    Kenneth Dewhurst, Dr. Thomas Sydenham (1624–1689): His Life and Original Writings (Berkeley: 1966), 62.Google Scholar
  43. 62.
    Patrick Romanell discusses “Morbus” in his John Locke and Medicine (New York: 1984) but spreads this quotation, interspersed with comments, over 58–64. I’ve used the quotation as it appears in Milton, “Locke,” 237. For further discussion of the relationship between Locke and Sydenham, see D. L. Cowen, “Comments on Dr. Romanell’s article on Locke and Sydenham,” Bulletin of the History of Medicine (1959) 33, no. 2:173–80. For Locke’s unacknowledged debt to Spinoza, see Wim Klever, “Locke’s Disguised Spinozism,” Revista Conatus—Filosofia de Spinoza, part 1 (July 2012) 6, no. 11:61–82; part 2 (December 2012) 6, no. 12:53–64.Google Scholar
  44. 66.
    This entry and the attribution of authorship have generated much discussion. See Jonathan Walmsley, “Morbus—Locke’s Early Essay on Disease,” Early Science and Medicine (2000) 5, no. 4:367–93; Peter R. Anstey, “Robert Boyle and Locke’s ‘Morbus’ Entry: A Reply to J. C. Walmsley,” Early Science and Medicine (2002) 7, no. 4:357–77; Jonathan Walmsley, “‘Morbus,’ Locke and Boyle: A Response to Peter Anstey,” Early Science and Medicine (2002) 7, no. 4:378–97; and Peter Anstey, “John Locke and Helmontian Medicine,” in The Body as Object and Instrument of Knowledge: Embodied Empiricism in Early Modern Science, eds. Charles T. Wolf and Ofer Gal (Dordrecht: 2010), 93–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. 69.
    Stephen Gaukroger, Collapse of Mechanism, esp. chapter 4, 150–86, discusses Locke’s “wholesale rejection of matter theory” (163). Peter Anstey, John Locke and Natural Philosophy (Oxford: 2013) refers to Locke’s position as “corpuscular pessimism.” Gaukroger writes that Locke’s position evolved; Anstey sees continuity. Both agree that Locke believed in corpuscularism but did not think it could be observed directly.Google Scholar
  46. 71.
    Marjorie Nicholson, “The Microscope and English Imagination,” Smith College Studies in Modern Languages (1935) 16, no. 4:1–92, on 16; and Alan Chapman, England’s Leonardo: Robert Hooke and the Seventeenth-Century Scientific Revolution (Bristol and Philadelphia: 2004), 109. The letter came to light in the mid-eighteenth century in Thomas Birch’s edition of Boyle’s Works (London: 1744) and his History of the Royal Society, vol. 2 (London: 1756), which quotes the letter on 63.Google Scholar
  47. 72.
    Howard Gest, “The Discovery of Microorganisms by Robert Hooke and Antoni van Leeuwenhoek, Fellows of the Royal Society,” N&R (2004) 58:187–201, doi: 10.1098/rsnr.2004.0055.Google Scholar
  48. 73.
    John Henry, “Charleton, Walter (1620–1707)” (Oxford: 2004), online edn. September 2010 at http://www.oxforddnb.com/veiw/article/5157.Google Scholar
  49. 78.
    Grandson of a moderate Puritan divine, Wilkins graduated from Magdalen Hall, Oxford, and became the Warden of Wadham College, Oxford. He married the younger sister of Oliver Cromwell in 1656. He conformed in 1662. A leader of the Latitudinarian party in the Church, he became Bishop of Chester in 1668. John Henry, “Wilkins, John (1614–1672,” ODNB (Oxford: 2004), online edn. October 2009 at http://www.oxfordnb.com/view/article/29421. See also John S. Wilkins, Species, A History of the Idea (Berkeley: 2009), 62. Supporters of a universal language included Descartes, Kircher, Franciscus Mercurius Van Helmont, and Theodore Haak and fellow members of the Hartlib circle.Google Scholar
  50. 79.
    R. Lewis, “The Publication of John Wilkins’s Essay (1668): Some Contextual Considerations,” N&R (2002) 56:133–46, on 137, doi: 10.1098/rsnr.2002.0174.Google Scholar
  51. 82.
    John Wilkins, An Essay towards a Real Character, and a Philosophical Language (London: 1668), online from Google.Google Scholar
  52. 92.
    William Petty, “Observations upon the Dublin Bills of Mortality, and the State of that City,” in Several Essays in Political Arithmetick … To Which are Prefix’d Memoirs of the Author’s Life, 4th ed. (London: 1755), 35–50. This document is exhibited and discussed in the section on “Theories of Contagion” in the online exhibit, “Infectious Diseases at the Edward Worth Library,” online at http://infectiousdiseases.edwardworthlibrary.ie/Theory-of-Contagion, retrieved April 1, 2012. See also Andrea A. Rusnock, Vital Accounts: Quantifying Health and Population in Eighteenth-Century England and France (Cambridge: 2002), 29–33.Google Scholar
  53. 96.
    Barbara Shapiro, John Wilkins, 1614–1673: An Intellectual Biography (Berkeley: 1969), 238.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Margaret DeLacy 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  • Margaret DeLacy

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations