Skip to main content

Getting Our Priorities Right: What Does Justice Require That We Do?

  • Chapter
  • 202 Accesses

Abstract

Having decided that technological unemployment is possible, the next thing we must do is determine how pressing a problem technological unemployment currently is or might become so we can decide how much risk to take in trying to eliminate it. For it might be the case that while technological innovation has mostly focused on labor-saving innovation for years, “the era of computers replacing human labour was largely over [by 2004],” and therefore “attention in the past decade has focused not on labour-saving innovation, but rather on a succession of entertainment and communication devices that do the same things as we could do before, but now in smaller and more convenient packages … These innovations were enthusiastically adopted, but they provided new opportunities for consumption on the job and in leisure hours rather than a continuation of the historical tradition of replacing human labour with machines.” If this is indeed the case, continued technological innovation may not pose as great a threat of increasing unemployment rates in the future as it did in the past, but as unemployment rates remain unacceptably high, this still leaves us with the problem of what to do about the technological unemployment we already have. And this is especially true if a significant amount of the technological unemployment we are currently experiencing becomes structural (if it is not structural already), for it will then become extremely hard to get rid of even after the business cycle rebounds. We accordingly still need to do something about the legacy of labor-saving technological innovation even if it is no longer the future threat it once was.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See Donald Van de grift and Joseph A. Bisti, “The Economic Effects of New Jersey’s Self-Service Operations Ban on Retail Gasoline Markets,” Journal of Consumer Policy 24 (2001): 63–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. For many, many more examples of this kind of thing, see Craig Lambert, Shadow Work: The Unpaid, Unseen jobs That Fill Your Day (Berkley, CA: Counterpoint Press, 2015).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See. e.g., Robert Skidelsky and Edward Skidelsky, How Much Is Enough? Money and the Good Life (New York: Other Press, 2012).

    Google Scholar 

  4. See James Tobin, “Economic Growth as an Objective of Government Policy,” American Economic Review 54 (1964): 1–20

    Google Scholar 

  5. For a discussion of how growth and employment roughly track each other, see, Roger E. A. Farmer, Expectations, Employment, and Prices (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), pp. 132–133

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Peter J. Henning, “Financial Crisis Cases Sputter at the End,” The New York Times (April 25, 2015); Gretchen Morgenson, “Ways to Put the Boss’s Skin in the Game,” The New York Times (March 21, 2015); James B. Stewart, “In Corporate Crimes, Individual Accountability Is Elusive,” The New York Times (February 19, 2015); Brandon L. Garrett, Too Big to jail: How Prosecutors Compromise with Corporations (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2014)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. See, e.g., Richard A. Musgrave, “Federal Tax Reform,” in Public Finance and Full Employment (Washington, DC: Federal Reserve, 1945), pp. 22–52

    Google Scholar 

  8. The multiplier effect was first suggested by Keynes in 1929 in Can Lloyd George Do It? but was more fully worked out and defended by Keynes’s disciple, Richard Kahn, in 1931 See Richard Kahn, “The Relation of Home Investment to Unemployment,” The Economic Journal 41 (1931): 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. John Maynard Keynes, Essays in Persuasion (London: Palgrave Macmülan, 2010), pp. 86–123

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. Nicholas Wapshott, Keynes/Hayek: The Clash that Defined Modern Economics (New York: Norton, 2011), pp. 132–135.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Richard J. Kent, “A 1929 Application of Multiplier Analysis by Keynes,” History of Political Economy 39 (2007): 529–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. See Valerie A. Ramey, “Can Government Stimulate the Economy?” Journal of Economic Literature 49 (2011): 673–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Jonathan A. Parker, “On Measuring the Effects of Fiscal Policy in Recessions,” Journal of Economic Literature 49 (2011): 703–718.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. See Carmen M. Reinhart and Kenneth S. Rogoff, The Time Is Different: Eight Centuries of Financial Folly (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2009).

    Google Scholar 

  15. For a discussion of what did and did not work in the $825 billion stimulus plan sponsored by the Obama administration, see Michael Grabell, Money Well Spent? The Truth behind the Trillion-Dollar Stimulus, the Biggest Economic Recovery Plan in History (New York: Public Affairs, 2012).

    Google Scholar 

  16. In fact, Hayek devoted his Nobel acceptance lecture to arguing for this proposition. See F. A. Hayek, “The Pretence of Knowledge,” in Full Employment at Any Price? (London: Institute of Economic Affairs, Occasional Paper 45, 1975), pp. 30–42.

    Google Scholar 

  17. For an example of this argument, see Arthur B. Laffer, “Government Exaction and Revenue Deficiencies,” in The Supply-Side Solution, ed. Bruce Bartlett and Timothy P. Roth (London: MacMillan, 1984), pp. 120–139

    Google Scholar 

  18. Some no doubt also see themselves more as followers of Adam Smith, or perhaps even followers of Smith alone. But this is a mistake. Smith was an anti-mercantilist, and most of what are thought of as his pro—laissez faire remarks are really driven by his anti-mercantilism, and taken in that context do not evidence the embrace of a broader anti-interventionist position. See Reiff, Exploitation and Economic Justice in the Liberal Capitalist State, p. 189 (citing sources); Mark R. Reiff, “Two Theories of Economic Liberalism,” Adam Smith Review (forthcoming). See also Jesse Burkhead, “The Balanced Budget,” The Quarterly journal of Economics 68 (1954): 191–216

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. See, e.g., Ludwig von Mises, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1998 [1949]), pp. 854–857

    Google Scholar 

  20. For further discussion of what it means for a rule to be self-defeating, see my “Terrorism, Retribution, and Collective Responsibility,” Social Theory and Practice 34 (2008): 209–242 at 240–241; and Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984), pp. 3–51

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ludwig von Mises, Interventionism: An Economic Analysis (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1998, 2011 [1940]), p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wesley C. Mitchell, Lecture Notes on Types of Economic Theory (New York: Augustus M. Kelly, 1949), pp. 15–81.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ludwig von Mises, Liberalism (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2010)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ludwig von Mises, A Critique of Interventionism (Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Institute, 2011 [1927]), p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  25. FA. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom (London: Routledge, 1944), pp, 40–41.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, pp. 125–126. See also F. A. Hayek, “Economic Freedom and Representative Government,” in New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economies and the History of Ideas (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978), pp. 105–118

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  27. See Robert Skidelsky, “Hayek versus Keynes: The Road to Reconciliation,” in The Cambridge Companion to Hayek, ed. Edward Feser (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), pp. 82–110

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  28. Joseph A. Schumpeter, “Depressions,” in Essays on Entrepreneurs, Innovations, Business Cycles, and the Evolution of Capitalism (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 1989), pp. 108–117

    Google Scholar 

  29. See, e.g., Ludwig von Mises, “Laissez Faire or Dictatorship” and “Liberty and Its Antithesis,” in Pianning for Freedom: Let the Mark et System Work (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 2008), pp. 15–24

    Google Scholar 

  30. For more on the concept of positive liberty, see Charles Taylor, “What’s Wrong with Negative Liberty?” in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985), pp. 211–229.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  31. See, e.g., Walter Eucken and T. W. Hutchison, “On the Theory of the Centrally Administered Economy: An Analysis of the German Experiment: Part II,” Economica 15 (1948): 173–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. Viktor J. Vanberg, “Constitutionally Cons trained and Safeguarded Competition in Markets and Politics,” in The Constitution of Markets: Essays in Political Economy (London: Routledge, 2001), pp. 1–16

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  33. See, e.g., David J. Gerber, Law and Competition in Twentieth Century Europe: Protecting Prometheus (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), pp. 232–265

    Google Scholar 

  34. David Gerber, “Two Models of Competition Law,” in Comparative Competition Law: Approaching an International System of Antitrust Law, ed. Hanns Ullrich (Baden-Baden: Nomos-Verlagsgesellschaft, 1998), pp. 105–116

    Google Scholar 

  35. Wernhard Möschel, “Competition Policy from an Ordo Point of View,” in German Neo-Liberals and the Social Market Economy, ed. Alan Peacock and Hans Willgerodt (London: Macmillan, 1989), pp. 142–159

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  36. Franz Bohm, Walter Eucken, and Hans Grossmann-Doerth, “The Ordo Manifesto of 1936,” in Germany’s Social Market Economy: Origins and Evolution, ed. Alan Peacock and Hans Willgerodt (London: Macmillan, 1989), pp. 15–26.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  37. For a searing indictment of monopolization and the ways it can undermine both economic and political freedom by one of the major voices in the ordohberal movement, see Wilhelm Röpke, The Social Crisis of Our Time (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1950), pp. 227–235.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Viktor Vanberg, “‘Oduningsthéorie’ as Constitutional Economics— The German Conception of a’ social Market Economy,’” Ordo 39 (1988): 17–31.

    Google Scholar 

  39. For more on or do liberalism and its role in postwar German thinking, see, e.g., Herbert Gersch, Karl-Heinz Paqué, and Holger Schmieding, The Fading Miracle: Four Decades of Market Economy in Germany (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 26–36

    Book  Google Scholar 

  40. Razeen Sally, “Ordoliberalism and the Social Market: Classical Political Economy from Germany,” New Political Economy 1 (1996): 233–257

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Liza Lovdahl Gormsen, A Principled Approach to Abuse of Dominance in European Competition Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010), pp. 39–48

    Book  Google Scholar 

  42. Werner Bonefeld, “Freedom and the Strong State: On German Ordoliberalism,” New Political Economy 17 (2012): 633–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Ralf Ptak, “Neoliberalism in Germany: Revisiting the Or do liberal Foundations of the Social Market Economy,” in The Road from Mont Pèlerin, ed. Philip Mirowski and Dieter Plehwe (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009), pp. 98–138

    Google Scholar 

  44. See Hans Willgerodt and Alan Peacock, “German Liberalism and Economic Revival,” in Germany’s Social Market Economy: Origins and Evolution (London: Macmillan, 1989), pp. 1–14.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  45. See Mark Blythe, Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), pp. 141–142

    Google Scholar 

  46. Volker Berghahn and Brigitte Young, “Reflections on Werner Bonefeld’s ‘Freedom and the Strong State: On German Or do liberalism’ and the Continuing Importance of the Ideas of Or do liberalism to Understand Germany’s Contested Role in Resolving the Eurozone Crisis,” New Political Economy 18 (2013) 768–778

    Article  Google Scholar 

  47. See generally Mark R. Reiff, Punishment, Compensation and Law: A Theory of Enforceability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2005).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  48. See Röpke, The Social Crisis of Our Time, pp. 165–175. See also Wilhelm Röpke, The Moral Foundations of Civil Society (London: W. Hodge, 1948), esp. pp. 204–205

    Google Scholar 

  49. Wilhelm Röpke, Economics of the Free Society (Chicago, IL: Henry Regnery, 1963), esp. pp. 218–219

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2015 Mark R. Reiff

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Reiff, M.R. (2015). Getting Our Priorities Right: What Does Justice Require That We Do?. In: On Unemployment. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-55000-2_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics