Skip to main content

Transcendental Idealism and Theistic Commitment in Fichte

  • Chapter
The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism

Part of the book series: The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism ((PHGI))

  • 347 Accesses

Abstract

What does Fichte’s philosophy, especially in writings relating to the “atheism dispute [Atheismusstreit]” (1798–1800), actually say about the intellectual basis and philosophical tenability of theistic belief? Fichte found himself at odds with his own audience on exactly this issue,1 and puzzlement on this point persists to this day. In 1798, he published the chapter “On the Basis of Our Belief in a Divine Governance of the World.” This text’s derivation of pre-philosophical religious conviction from ineluctable acts of ideation, coupled with its identification of God with the moral world order, can give the impression (and prompted the objection) that Fichte philosophically accounts for belief in God in a way that proves to be completely corrosive of any genuinely theistic commitment. And his attempts to rebut that objection, especially in Book III of 1800’s The Vocation of Man (hereafter, “VM III”), depict and defend properly philosophical belief in a supreme being in a way that has perplexed and divided scholars right down to the present, and so seriously as to raise doubts about how well we have understood the essential content of his Jena-era transcendental idealism — from which, according to Fichte himself, The Vocation of Man does not radically depart.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. I will elide the historical details of the atheism dispute here. For a detailed treatment, see Yolanda Estes, “Commentator’s Introduction: J. G. Fichte, Atheismusstreit, Wissenschaftslehre, and Religionslehre,” in J. G. Fichte and the Atheism Dispute (1798–1800), trans. Curtis Bowman, ed. Yolanda Estes (Burlington, Vt.: Ashgate, 2010), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For an overview of this text’s conflicted recent reception, see Daniel Breazeale, introduction to Fichte’s Vocation of Man: New Interpretive and Critical Essays, ed. Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2013), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  3. In this connection I am particularly indebted to Andrew Chignell, “Belief in Kant,” Philosophical Review 116, no. 3 (2007): 323–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. I will be speaking specifically of the philosophy of the Jena era (1794–1801). Fichte’s later work is more markedly metaphysical in tone and replete with religious references. For an overview focused on his theory of religion, see Yolanda Estes, “After Jena: Fichte’s Religionslehre,” in After Jena: New Essays on Fichte’s Later Philosophy, ed. Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 2008), 99–114.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For further discussion, see Daniel Breazeale, “The ‘Standpoint of Life’ and the ‘Standpoint of Philosophy’ in the Context of the Jena Wissenschaftslehre,” in Transzendentalphilosophie als System: Die Auseinandersetzung zwischen 1794 und 1806, ed. Albert Mues (Hamburg: Meiner, 1989), 81–104.

    Google Scholar 

  6. For more on Fichte’s first principles and the associated account of reason, see Frederick Neuhouser, Fichte’s Theory of Subjectivity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. See also Günter Zöller, Fichte’s Transcendental Philosophy: The Original Duplicity of Intelligence and Will (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  8. See Matthew C. Altman and Cynthia D. Coe, The Fractured Self in Freud and German Philosophy (Hampshire, England: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013), 27–52.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For further discussion, see Wayne M. Martin, “‘Without a Striving, No Object is Possible’: Fichte’s Striving Doctrine and the Primacy of Practice,” in New Perspectives on Fichte, ed. Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Prometheus Books, 1996), 19–33.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For more on these issues, see Steven Hoeltzel, “Finite and Absolute Reason in (and beyond) Fichte’s System of Ethics,” Philosophy Today 52, nos. 3–4 (fall–winter 2008): 259–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. For more on transcendental theology in Fichte, see Benjamin D. Crowe, “Fichte’s Transcendental Theology,” Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 92, no. 1 (Jan. 2010): 68–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. For more on Fichte’s notion of certainty, see Günter Zöller, “‘Das Element aller Gewissheit.’ Jacobi, Kant, und Fichte über den Glauben,” Fichte-Studien 14 (1998): 21–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. For further discussion, see Daniel Breazeale, “How to Make an Idealist: Fichte’s ‘Refutation of Dogmatism’ and the Problem of the Starting Point of the Wissenschaftslehre,” Philosophical Forum 19, nos. 2–3 (winter–spring 1987–88): 97–123.

    Google Scholar 

  14. On this vexed question, see Benjamin D. Crowe, “Revisionism and Religion in Fichte’s Jena Wissenschaftslehre,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy 16, no. 2 (May 2008): 371–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel “Allwill”, trans. and ed. George di Giovanni (Montreal and Kingston: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1994), 514. German edition: Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi, Werke, 6 vols., ed. Friedrich Roth and Friedrich Köppen (Leipzig: Fleischer, 1812–25. Reprint: Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1976), 3:33.

    Google Scholar 

  16. For a reading along these lines, according to which Fichte’s position thus “can be neither theistic nor atheistic,” see Wayne M. Martin, “Transcendental Philosophy and Atheism,” European Journal of Philosophy 16, no. 1 (April 2007): 122.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Such a rebuttal is clearly ill-suited to the court of public opinion — in which case, perhaps The Vocation of Man serves to rhetorically drape an ontologically unencumbered idealism in metaphysically respectable guise. For a detailed reading to this effect, see Ives Radrizzani, “The Place of The Vocation of Man in Fichte’s work,” in New Essays on Fichte’s Later Jena Wissenschaftslehre, ed. Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 2002), 317–44.

    Google Scholar 

  18. VM III is often read as a radical reversal of Fichte’s prior position. For a detailed example of that sort of interpretation, see Martial Guéroult, “La destination de l’homme,” in Études sur Fichte (Paris: Aubier-Montaigne, 1974), 72–96.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2014 Steven Hoeltzel

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hoeltzel, S. (2014). Transcendental Idealism and Theistic Commitment in Fichte. In: Altman, M.C. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism. The Palgrave Handbook of German Idealism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-33475-6_19

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics