Skip to main content

The Methodology of Institutional Economics: A Pragmatic Instrumentalist Perspective

  • Chapter
Institutional Economics: Theory, Method, Policy

Part of the book series: Recent Economic Thought ((RETH,volume 31))

Abstract

Institutionalists engage in a very active, ongoing dialogue about methodological issues. Their preoccupation with methodology is motivated in part by their critique of mainstream economics. Since institutionalists attempt to steer economic inquiry in a direction quite different from that followed by mainstream economists, the institutionalist critique of neoclassical thought requires that institutionalists be concerned with methodological issues. But there is a more profound reason for the institutionalist emphasis on methodological discourse. It arises out of the influence of the philosophy of pragmatism on institutionalist methodology. A fundamental tenet of pragmatism is that all propositions are subject to revision as theoretical and empirical inquiry moves forward. In order to remain alert to the possibility that such revisions may be required at any given stage of inquiry, methodology must be under constant scrutiny. Consequently, institutionalists are as interested in methodological issues arising in their own work as they are in those arising in their critique of orthodoxy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The term pragmatic instrumentalist is taken from Dewey’s use of the term in The Quest for Certainty in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–1953, Vol. 4: 1929 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1984, footnote, p. 30. It is hoped that by using “pragmatic” to modify “instrumentalist” one can clearly differentiate between Dewey’s use of “instrumental” and Karl Popper’s use of the term in his philosophy of science. See Karl Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York: Basic Books, 1959), footnote, p. 59. Alas, the failure to make this differentiation between the Deweyan and Popperian uses of the term has led to considerable intellectual mischief, a matter that will be taken up later in a comment on Friedman’s “instrumentalism.” One must also differentiate between Dewey’s use of the term from that of Jurgen Habermas. Habermas confines the term instrumental to the technical cognitive interest which he distinguishes from “practical” and “emancipatory” human interests. In contrast, Dewey’s use of instrumentalism spans the three realms of human interests identified by Habermas. See Jurgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests, trans. Jeremy J. Shapiro (Boston: Beacon Press, 1971), pp. 308–311. For a discussion the Habermasian usage, see Jon D. Wisman, “Toward a Humanist Reconstruction of Economic Science,” Journal of Economic Issues 13 (March 1979): 19–48; and “Economic Knowledge, Evolutionary Epistemology, and Human Interests,” Journal of Economic Issues 23 (June 1989): 647–656.

    Google Scholar 

  2. There is no intention here to diminish the importance of Peirce’s philosophical influence on institutionalist methodology. Philip Mirowski, for one, suggests that while Dewey has, indeed, had a greater influence than Peirce on institutionalist methodology, Dewey’ s dominance must be regarded as a basic weakness in the institutionalist literature. He argues that the viability of institutionalism will depend on whether the “hermeneutical” perspective of Peirce can be substituted for the views of Dewey in guiding the methodology of institutional thought in the future. See Philip Mirowski, “The Philosophical Basis of Institutional Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (September 1987): 1001–1038; and the author’s critical comment on this piece, Paul D. Bush, “Institutionalist Methodology and Hermeneutics: A Comment on Mirowski,” Journal of Economic Issues 23 (December 1989): 1159–1172. For two views of Peirce’s influence on institutionalist methodology that are quite different than Mirowski’s, see Alan W. Dyer, “Veblen on Scientific Creativity: The Influence of Charles S. Peirce,” Journal of Economic Issues 20 (March 1986): 21–41; and H.H. Liebhafsky, “Peirce on the Summum Bonnum and the Unlimited Community,” Journal of Economic Issues 20 (March 1986): 5–20.

    Google Scholar 

  3. John R. Commons, Institutional Economics, Vol. I and II (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1961 [1934]), p. 150.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Both studied at Johns Hopkins as graduate students under Peirce. They both taught at the University of Chicago from the late 1890s until 1904 (Veblen, 1892–1904, and Dewey, 1894–1904) and at the New School for Social Research, where Veblen held his last academic post. See Joseph Dorfman, Thorstein Veblen and His America, 7th ed. (Clifton: Augustus M. Kelly, 1972), p. 449; and H.H. Liebhafsky, “An Institutionalist Evaluation of the Recent Apparently, But Only Apparently Fatal Attack on Institutionalism,” Journal of Economics Issues 22 (September 1988): 837–851. The Liebhafsky article contains a discussion of the relationship of Veblen and Dewey to Peirce and Ayres.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Dorfman, Thorstein Veblen and His America, p. 450.

    Google Scholar 

  6. C.E. Ayres, Toward a Reasonable Society (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1961), pp. 29–32. Rick Tilman documents in some detail the strong intellectual ties between Dewey and Ayres as expressed in their correspondence. See Rick Tilman, “New Light on John Dewey, Clarence Ayres, and the Development of Evolutionary Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 24 (December 1990): 963–979. Dewey made direct reference to Ayres’s Theory of Economic Progress (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press, 1944) as a study that incorporated an approach to values and valuations which Dewey regarded as pertinent to his own inquiries. See John Dewey, “Some Questions about Value,” in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–53, Vol. 15: 1942–48 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1989), p. 108, footnote 6; and “By Nature and by Art,” ibid., p. 89, footnote 3. Ayres participated in Ray Lepley’s symposium on Dewey’s theory of value in which there is considerable discussion among Dewey, Ayres, and others (e.g., George R. Geiger) concerning the interrelationship between Dewey’s and Ayres’s views on values in culture and on their role in inquiry. See Clarence E. Ayres, “The Value Economy,” in Ray Lepley, ed., Value: A Cooperative Inquiry (New York: Columbia University Press, 1949), pp. 43–63. For the criticisms and rejoinders relevant to Ayres’s contribution, see pages 302–311, 321–333, and 415–423.

    Google Scholar 

  7. An important consequence of reading Veblen from this perspective is that a “normative” Veblen emerges from behind his well-known rhetorical stance of “Olympian detachment.” For a brief characterization of the normative Veblen presented in the context of a commentary on David W. Seckler’s Thorstein Veblen and the Institutionalists (Boulder: Colorado Associated University Press, 1975), see Paul D. Bush, “Radical Individualism vs. Institutionalism, I,” American Journal of Economics and Sociology 40 (April 1981): 139–148; and “Radical Individualism vs. Institutionalism, II,” American Journal of Economics and Sociology 40 (July 1981): 287–298. For Seckler’s rebuttal to this characterization, see Seckler, “Individualism and Institutionalism Revisited: A Response to Professor Bush,” American Journal of Economics and Sociology 40 (October 1981): 415–425. Not all institutionalists who have an affinity for the ideas of Dewey and Ayres acknowledge the existence of a normative Veblen. See, for example, Wendell Gordon, “The Role of Institutional Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 18 (June 1984): 369–381, specifically, pages 378–379.

    Google Scholar 

  8. K. William Kapp, “In Defense of Institutional Economics,” Swedish Journal of Economics 70 (March 1968): 1–18; reprinted in Warren J. Samuels, ed., Institutional Economics, Vol. I (Aldershot: Edward Elgar, 1988), pp. 92–107.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Professor Ranson made this invitation during his presidential address to the Association for Institutional Thought on April 27, 1984, in San Diego, California, at the 26th Annual Conference of the Western Social Science Association. His address was entitled “Activating AFIT: The Problems and a Possible Solution.”

    Google Scholar 

  10. Some of Richard Rorty’s most important works are: Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979); Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982); Objectivity. Relativism, and Truth: Philosophical Papers, Volume One (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991); and Essays on Heidegger and Others: Philosophical Papers, Volume Two (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., p. 163.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 165.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Brice R. Wachterhauser, “Introduction: History and Language in Understanding,” in Brice R. Wachterhauser, ed., Hermeneutics and Modern Philosophy (Albany: State University of New York, 1986), pp. 5–61; the quotation is at page 13. The use of the terms foundationalism and foundationalist in this philosophical context should not be confused with the term philosophical foundations of…. When the latter phraeseology is used, it simply refers to the philosohical underpinnings of a given methodological position; the philosophical foundations may or may not be foundationalist in character.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 233.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 19. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., p. 231.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., p. 229.

    Google Scholar 

  23. John Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–53, Vol. 12:1938 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), p. 111.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty, p. 236.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Thorstein B. Veblen, “Why is Economics Not an Evolutionary Science?” in Thorstein B. Veblen, ed., The Place of Science in Modern Civilisation (New York: Viking Press, 1942 [1919]), pp. 56–81; the quotation is from page 61.

    Google Scholar 

  31. See Wendell Gordon, “The Role of Institutional Economics,” pp. 369–381; and idem, “The Role of Tool’s Social Value Principle,” Journal of Economic Issues 24 (September 1990): 879–886.

    Google Scholar 

  32. A slightly different version of his reply to Wendell Gordon (and also to Anne Mayhew) appears in Marc R. Tool, “Instrumental Value an Eternal Verity? A Reply to Wendell Gordon,” Journal of Economic Issues 24 (December 1990): 1109–1122; and idem, “Culture Versus Social Value? A Response to Mayhew,” Journal of Economic Issues 24 (December 1990): 1122–1133. See Anne Mayhew, “A Critical Analysis of Tool’s Essays in Social Value Theory” a paper read at the Annual Meetings of the Association for Institutional Thought, El Paso, Texas, April 1987; and idem, “Culture: Core Concept Under Attack,” Journal of Economics Issues 21 (June 1987): 587–603.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, p. 161. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., pp. 121–122.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., p. 113.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., p. 136. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Dewey, “Propositions, Warranted Assertability, and Truth,” in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–53, Vol. 14: 1941, (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988), pp. 179–180. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism, p. 86.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid., p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, p. 160.

    Google Scholar 

  44. J.E. Tiles, Dewey (New York: Routledge, 1988), p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Abraham Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry (San Francisco: Chandler Publishing Company, 1964), p. 333.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Pierre Duhem, “Physical Theory and Experiment,” in Herbert Feigl and May Brodbeck, eds., Readings in the Philosophy of Science (New York: Appelton-Century-Crofts, Inc., 1953), pp. 235–252.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Willard V.O. Quine, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” in Willard V.O. Quine, ed., From a Logical Point of View, 2nd ed., rev. (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980 [1953]), pp. 20–46.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Allan G. Gruchy was the first to use the term holism in describing the methodology of institutional economics. See his Modern Economic Thought: The American Contribution (Now York: Prentice-Hall, 1947). An extensive discussion of holistic methodology in institutional economics is found in Charles K. Wilber and Robert S. Harrison, “The Methodological Basis of Institutional Economics: Pattern Model, Storytelling, and Holism,” Journal of Economic Issues 12 (March 1978): 61–89. Discussions of holism and pattern models in the social sciences are undertaken by Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry, pp. 327–328; and Paul Diesing, Patterns of Discovery in the Social Sciences (New York: Aldine, 1971), pp. 157–167. For a sophisticated treatment of holism in general, and with respect to John R. Commons’s thought in particular, see Yngve Ramstad, “A Pragmatist’s Quest for Holistic Knowledge: The Scientific Methodology of John R. Commons,” Journal of Economic Issues 20 (December 1986): 1067–1105.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ramstad, “A Pragmatist’s Quest for Holistic Knowledge …,” p. 1097.

    Google Scholar 

  51. For a discussion of the preoccupation with “induction” in institutional economics and the failure to develop formal models “to guide observation and experience,” see James I. Sturgeon, “Induction and Instrumentalism in Institutional Thought,” Journal of Economic Issues 18 (June 1984): 599–608, especially, page 604.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry, pp. 335–338.

    Google Scholar 

  53. An exmple of the use of a hypothetico-deductively formulated model in institutional economics is found in Paul D. Bush, “An Exploration of the Structural Characteristics of a Veblen-Ayres-Foster Defined Institutional Domain,” Journal of Economic Issues 17 (March 1983): 35–66. Ramstad has criticized the approach taken in that article as being incompatible with a holistic methodology. See Ramstad, “A Pragmatist’s Quest for Holistic Knowledge …,” p. 1097 and footnotes 12 and 51. “It is my suspicion,” he says, “that Bush’s ingenious effort to formalize such qualitative and evolving concepts as’ social values,’ and then to combine them into concepts such as ‘ceremonial encapsulation’ or into quantitative indexes such as the ‘index of ceremonial dominance,’ will ultimately prove sterile” [footnote 15]. While the author is sympathetic to Ramstad’s concerns with respect to the perils of both “formalism” and “quantification,” he does not believe that the model he set forth in the 1983 article is incompatible with holistic methodology. Indeed, every effort was made to indicate that the “hypothetical” portion of the model was derived from the rich theoretical and empirical insights found in the pattern models of Veblen, Dewey, Ayres, and Foster. In regard to the question of sterility, that is a matter that can only be settled through further inquiry.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Diesing, Patterns of Discovery …, pp. 156–67.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Wilbur and Harrison, “The Methodological Basis of Institutional Economics,” p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Mirowski, “The Philosophical Basis of Institutional Economics.”

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid., p. 1016.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Joseph Ratner, ed., Intelligence in the Modern World: John Dewey’s Philosophy (New York: The Modern Library, 1939), p. 308.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty, p. 235.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., p. 236.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  62. George R. Geiger, John Dewey in Perspective (New York: Oxford University Press, 1958), p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Tiles, Dewey, p. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, pp. 30–47.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ibid., p. 109. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ibid., p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Mirowski, “The Philosophical Basis of Institutional Economics,” p. 1163.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Ibid., p. 1034, footnote 7. See John Dewey, “Theory of Valuation,” in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–53, Vol. 13:1938–39 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1988), pp. 191–251. The author has commented on Mirowski’s use of Thayer’s observation about Dewey’s “alliance with the logical positivists” in Bush, “Institutionalist Methodology and Hermeneutics: A Comment on Mirowski,” p. 1163.

    Google Scholar 

  70. James A. Swaney and Robert Premus, “Modern Empiricism and Quantum-Leap Theorizing in Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 16 (June 1982): 713–730; reprinted in Alfred S. Eichner, ed., Why Economics is Not Yet a Science (Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 1983), pp. 41–60; the words quoted are on pp. 47–48. See Crossland’s and Weinel’s critique of Swaney and Premus [Philip P. Crossland and Ivan Weinel, “Modern Empiricism and Quantum Leap in Economics: A Comment,” Journal of Economic Issues 17 (December 1983): 1129–1138] and Swaney’s and Premus’s reply [James A. Swaney and Robert Premus, “Practice, Logic and Problem Solving: A Reply to Crossland and Weinel,” Journal of Economic Issues 17 (December 1983): 1138–1142.]. Although this is an interesting exchange of views, the alleged association of Dewey with logical positivism is not mentioned.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, pp. 512. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Gladys Parker Foster offers a very clear discussion of the role of prediction in pragmatic instrumentalist thought in “Cultural Relativism and the Theory of Value: The Educational Implications,” American Journal of Economics and Sociology 50 (July 1991): 257–267; see especially pages 262–265.

    Google Scholar 

  73. James A. Swaney, “A Coevolutionary Model of Structural Change,” Journal of Economic Issues 20 (June 1986): 393–401; idem, “Building Instrumental Environmental Control Institutions,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (March 1987): 295–308; and James A. Swaney and Paulett I. Olson, “The Economics of Biodiversity: Lives and Lifestyles,” Journal of Economic Issues 26 (March 1992): 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Marc R. Tool, The Discretionary Economy (Santa Monica: Goodyear Publishing Company, 1979) and idem, Essays in Social Value Theory (Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  75. Milton Friedman, “The Methodology of Positive Economics,” in Milton Friedman, ed., Essays in Positive Economics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953), pp. 3–43.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See Lawrence A. Boland, “A Critique of Friedman’s Critics,” Journal of Economic Literature 17 (June 1979): 503–522; and Lawrence A. Boland and William J. Frazer, Jr., “An Essay on the Foundations of Friedman’s Methodology,” American Economic Review 74 (September 1983): 782–788.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 59.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ken Dennis, “Boland on Friedman: A Rebuttal,” Journal of Economic Issues 20 (September 1986): 633–660; and idem, “Boland on Boland: A Further Rebuttal,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (March 1987): 388–393.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Lawrence A. Boland, “Boland on Friedman’s Methodology: A Summation,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (March 1987): 380–388.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Lawrence A. Boland, The Foundations of Economic Methodology (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1982), p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ibid., p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  82. John Dewey, Reconstruction in Philosophy, in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Middle Works of John Dewey, 1899–1924, Vol. 12: 1920 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1982), pp. 169–170. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Boland, “A Critique of Friedman’s Critics,” and Boland and Frazer, Jr., “An Essay on the Foundations of Friedman’s Methodology.”

    Google Scholar 

  84. Abraham Hirsch and Neil di Marchi, Milton Friedman: Economics in Theory and Practice (Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1990), p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  86. James R. Wible, “The Instrumentalisms of Dewey and Friedman,” Journal of Economic Issues 18 (December 1984): 1049–1070; the words quoted are on page 1065.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ibid., p. 1060.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  89. See H.H. Liebhafsky and E.E. Liebhafsky, “Comment on ‘The Instrumentalisms of Dewey and Friedman,” Journal of Economic Issues 19 (December 1985): 974–983; and James Webb, “Is Friedman’s Methodological Instrumentalism A Special Case of Dewey’s Instrumental Philosophy? A Comment on Wible,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (March 1987): 393–329.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Abraham Hirsch and Neil de Marchi, “Methodology: A Comment on Frazer and Boland, I,” American Economic Review 74 (September 1984): 782–788; and idem, Milton Friedman: Economics in Theory and Practice, pp. 92–93.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Friedman, “The Methodology of Positive Economics,” pp. 14–15.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Friedman, “The Methodology of Positive Economics,” p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  94. See Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, pp. 113, 314, 485, and elsewhere.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Dewey, “The Theory of Valuation,” p. 248.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, pp. 16, 105–122.

    Google Scholar 

  97. The author originally offered this criticism in his “The Normative Implications of Positive Analysis,” A paper presented to the Western Economics Association, Corvallis, Oregon, August 23, 1968; abstracted in the Western Economic Journal 6 (September 1968): 309.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Hirsch and de Marchi, Milton Friedman, p. 273.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Bruce Caldwell’s critique of Friedman’s methodology, while not focused on the specific issues raised here, lends general support to the arguments set forth in this section. See Bruce Caldwell, Beyond Positivism (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1982), pp. 173–188. See also the Geoffrey M. Hodgson’s discussion of the inadequacies of Friedman’s methodology in Geoffrey M. Hodgson, Economics and Institutions: A Manifesto for a Modern Institutional Economics (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1988), pp. 28–35.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism, p. 164. However, K. Kolenda warns that Rorty may be giving too much credit to Dewey on this point. See K. Kolenda, “Rorty’s Dewey,” Journal of Value Inquiry 20 (1986): 57–62, especially page 61.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Dewey, “Valuation Judgments and Immediate Quality,” in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–1953, Vol. 15:1942–48 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1989), pp. 70–71. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, p. 163.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Ibid., p. 176.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  106. John Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic, in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Middle Works of John Dewey, 1899–1924, Vol. 8:1915 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1979), p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Ibid., pp. 26–28. See also Dewey, “Theory of Valuation,” pp. 194–195.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Dewey, Essays in Experimental Logic, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Dewey, “Theory of Valuation,” p. 249.

    Google Scholar 

  110. James Gouinlock, John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value (New York: Humanities Press, 1972), pp. 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  111. John Dewey, Democracy and Education, in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Middle Works of John Dewey, 1899–1924, Vol. 9:1916 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1980), p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Dewey, “Theory of Valuation,” pp. 248–249.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Dewey, Democracy and Education, p. 306.

    Google Scholar 

  114. John Dewey, “Existence, Value, and Criticism,” in Jo Ann Boydston, ed., The Later Works of John Dewey, 1925–1953, Vol. 11: 1925 (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1986), p. 321.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Dewey, The Quest for Certainty, pp. 211–212. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, pp. 489–490. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Ibid., pp. 496–497. Italics as indicated in quotation.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Ibid., p. 491. Italics in the original.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Ibid., p. 484, footnote 3.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ibid., p. 484.

    Google Scholar 

  121. The notion that values function as standards by which behavior is correlated has been widely discussed in the institutionalist literature by J. Fagg Foster and his students. For a summary of this discussion, see Paul D. Bush, “The Theory of Institutional Change,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (September 1987): 1075–1116, reprinted in Marc R. Tool, ed., Evolutionary Economics: Foundation of Institutional Thought, Vol. I (Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 1988), pp. 125–166.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Charles S. Peirce, “The Scientific Attitude and Fallibalism,” in Justus Buchler, ed., Philosophical Writings of Peirce (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), p. 54.

    Google Scholar 

  123. Jacob Bronowski, Science and Human Values, rev. ed. (New York: Harper & Row, 1965), p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  124. Ibid., p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  125. Dewey, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, p. 496.

    Google Scholar 

  126. See, for example, George R. Geiger, John Dewey in Perspective, pp. 124–135; and Michael F. Sheehan and Rick Tilman, “A Clarification of the Concept of ‘Instrumental Valuation’ in Institutional Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 26 (March 1992): 197–208.

    Google Scholar 

  127. The meaning of the term neoinstitutional, like the term instrumental, has been obscured by usages that are incompatible with the meaning assigned to the term in the American institutionalist literature. The term neoinstitutional has been coopted by the so-called new institutionalists whose neoclassical methodology is fundamentally incompatible with what they call the old institutionalists (i.e., contributors to the standard American institutionalist literature). For a well-known specimen of the new institutional economics, see Richard N. Langlois, ed., Economics as Process: Essays in the New Institutional Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986). The use of the term neoinstitutional as a synonym for the new institutional economics apparently enjoys wide currency in Europe. For example, one European neoclassical economist working in the new institutional economics mode who refers to his research program as neoinstitutional economics is Thrainn Eggertsson; see his Economic Behavior and Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Neoinstitutionalists of the old institutional economics variety, and those sympathetic to their exclusive claim on the neoinstitutionalist rubric, are highly critical of the new institutional economics and its cooption of the term institutional, neo, or otherwise. For a sample of this critical literature, see John Adams, “Reinventing the Mos: Neoclassical Ignorance of Institutionalism as a Source of Fame and Employment,” a paper presented to the Fourth Colloquium of the Charles Gide Association, Marseilles, France, September 19 and 20, 1991; Geoffrey M. Hodgson, “Institutional Economic Theory: The Old versus the New,” Review of Political Economy 1 (November 1989): 249–269, reprinted in Geoffrey M. Hodgson, After Marx and Sraffra (London: MacMillan, 1991), pp. 194–213; and Anne Mayhew and Walter Neale, “The Implicit Theory and Method of the Old (and Real) American Institutionalists,” a paper presented to the Fourth Colloquium of the Charles Gide Association, Marseilles, France, September 19 and 20, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  128. H.P. Rickman states that according to Wilhelm Dilthey, “the use of understanding [verstehen] provides the human studies with a method distinct from those of the physical sciences and thus frees them from subservience to the latter.” See Wilhelm Dilthey, Pattern and Meaning in History, edited and introduced by H.R. Rickman (New York: Harper Torchbook, 1962), pp. 17–18.

    Google Scholar 

  129. Examples of the use of this distinction between “value judgment” and “valuation” are to be found in Paul D. Bush, “The Theory of Institutional Change,” Edythe S. Miller, “Review of Wendell Gordon and John Adams, Economics as a Social Science: An Evolutionary Approach,” Journal of Economics Issues 24 (March 1990): 275–278; and Baldwin Ranson, “Review of Laurence H. Tribe, Corrine S. Schelling, and John Voss, editors, When Values Conflict,” Journal of Economic Issues 12 (March 1978): 195–196.

    Google Scholar 

  130. It appears that Liebhafsky first used the term self-correcting value judgments in The Nature of Price Theory, rev. ed. (Homewood: Dorsey Press, 1968), p. 523. His elaboration on this idea is discussed by Warren Samuels in “Technology vis-a-vis Institutions in the JEI: A Suggested Interpretation,” Journal of Economic Issues 11 (December 1977): 867–895; the discussion is found on pages 887–891. See also Anne Mayhew’s use of Liebhafsky’s notion in “Ayresian Technology, Technological Reasoning, and Doomsday,” Journal of Economic Issues 15 (June 1981); 513–520.

    Google Scholar 

  131. C.E. Ayres, The Industrial Economy (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company, 1952), p. 310.

    Google Scholar 

  132. A number of important issues arise in connection with the pragmatic instrumentalist view of the role of values in inquiry. Space does not permit their discussion here, but the author has attempted to address some of them in previous publications, two of which are: Paul D. Bush, “The Normative Implications of Positive Analysis”; and idem, “Reflections on the 25th Anniversary of AFEE: Current Philosophical and Methodological Issues in Institutional Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 25 (June 1991): 321–346. For a highly competent review of the pragmatic instrumentalist approach to the theory of valuation and its application in the institutionalist literature, see Steven R. Hickerson, “Instrumental Valuation: The Normative Compass of Institutional Economics,” Journal of Economic Issues 21 (September 1987): 1117–1143; reprinted in Marc R. Tool, ed., Evolutionary Economics: Foundation of Institutional Thought, Vol. I (Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 1988), pp. 167–193. The most extensive development and application of the pragmatic instrumentalist value theory to institutional economics is to be found in the works of Marc R. Tool. See Tool, The Discretionary Economy, and idem, Essays in Social Value Theory. The pragmatic instrumentalist position acknowledges the possibility of an infinite regress in the means-ends relationship that exits between “value judgments” and “valuations.” Contrary to the view held by many philosophers, pragmatic instrumentalists do not regard the possibility of an infinite regress as a deficiency of the theory. It is their view that, properly understood, all empirical and normative propositions are embedded in infinite regresses. On this issue, see Sidney S. Alexander, “Human Values and Economists’ Values,” in Sidney Hook, ed., Human Values and Economic Policy (New York: New York University Press. 1967), pp. 101–116; Paul D. Bush, “Reflections on the 25th Anniversary of AFEE: Current Philosophical and Methodological Issues in Institutional Economics,” especially pp. 329–340; and Larry Dwyer, “The Alleged Value Neutrality of Economics,” Journal of Economics Issues 16 (March 1982): 75–106.

    Google Scholar 

  133. For a discussion of the methodological significance of this definition of the term “institution,” see Paul D. Bush, “On the Concept of Ceremonial Encapsulation,” Review of Institutional Thought 3 (December 1986): 25–45. See also J. Fagg Foster’s use of this conception of institutions in “The Effect of Technology on Institutions,” Journal of Economic Issues 15 (December 1981): 907–913.

    Google Scholar 

  134. Gunnar Myrdal, Objectivity in Social Research (New York: Pantheon Books, 1969), p. 9. Myrdal’s use of the term “a priori” should not be read to mean in some metaphysical sense “beyond inquiry.” His use of the term is consistent with the pragmatic instrumentalist view that valuations are logically prior to the determination of the “facts.”

    Google Scholar 

  135. Jerry L. Petr, “Fundamentals of an Institutionalist Perspective on Economic Policy,” Journal of Economic Issues 18 (March 1984): 1–17; reprinted in Marc R. Tool, ed., An Institutionalist Guide to Economics and Public Policy (Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 1984), pp. 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  136. See, for example, Mark Blaug, The Methodology of Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1980), pp. 1–51; Bruce Caldwell, Beyond Positivism, pp. 221–230; Paul Feyerabend, Against Method, rev. ed. (London: Verso, 1988); Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2d ed. enl. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970), and idem “Reflections on My Critics,” in Imre Lakatos and Alan Musgrave, eds., Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge (London: Cambridge University Press, 1970), pp. 231–278; Imre Lakatos, “Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes,” in Imre Lakatos, The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes: Philosophical Papers, Volume I, ed. John Worrall and Gregory Currie (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), pp. 8–101; and Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery.

    Google Scholar 

  137. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.

    Google Scholar 

  138. Kuhn, “Reflections on My Critics,” pp. 266–277.

    Google Scholar 

  139. See, for example, John M. Connolly and Thomas Keutner, “Introduction: Interpretation, Decidability, and Meaning,” in John M. Connolly and Thomas Keutner, trans, and eds., Hermeneutics Versus Science? Three German Views: Essays by H.-G. Gadamer, E.K. Specht. W. Stegmuller (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1988), pp. 1–67; Kurt Mueller-Vollmer, “Introduction: Language, Mind, and Artifact: An Outline of Hermeneutic Theory Since the Enlightenment,” in Kurt Mueller-Vollmer, ed., The Hermeneutics Reader (New York: Continuum Publishing Company, 1985), pp. 1–53; and Wachterhauser, “Introduction: History and Language in Understanding,” pp. 5–61.

    Google Scholar 

  140. Mirowski, “The Philosophical Basis of Institutional Economics,” p. 1010.

    Google Scholar 

  141. Wachterhauser, “Introduction: History and Language in Understanding,” pp. 7–10.

    Google Scholar 

  142. Ibid., p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  143. Ibid., p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  144. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  145. Ibid., p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  146. Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, pp. 12–13.

    Google Scholar 

  147. William Waller explores some related problems in William Waller, “Avoiding the Cartesian Vice in Radical Institutionalism: A Reply to Mayhew,” Journal of Economic Issues 24 (September 1990): 897–901.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Fritz Machlup, “The Problem of Verification in Economics,” Southern Economic Journal 22 (July 1955): 1–21; see especially pages 7–11.

    Google Scholar 

  149. Lionel Robbins, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, 2nd ed. (London: MacMillan and Co., Ltd., 1952 [1935]), p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  150. See Ludwig von Mises, Human Action (New Haven: Yale University Press 1949); and idem, The Ultimate Foundations of Economic Science (New York: D. Van Norstrand, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  151. For an excellent sample of critical commentaries of Rorty’s work, see Alan Malachowski, ed., Reading Rorty (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990). See also K. Kolenda, “Rorty’s Dewey”; and idem, Rorty’s Humanistic Pragmatism (Tampa: University of Southern Florida Press, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

  152. Unfortunately, the limits of space have not permitted a review of and response to the substantial body of literature critical of pragmatic philosophy. That task must remain for a later undertaking. Such an undertaking should include a discussion of some of the more interesting and relevant commentaries, such as: Roy Bhaskar, “Rorty, Realism and the Idea of Freedom,” in Alan Malachowski, ed., Reading Rorty (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990), pp. 198–232; Martin Hollis and Edward J. Nell, Rational Economic Man (London: Cambridge University Press, 1975), pp. 152–169; and Max Horkheimer, Critical Theory, trans. Matthew J. O’Connell et al. (New York: Herder and Herder 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  153. Hodgson, Economics and Institutions.

    Google Scholar 

References

  • Aronson, J. A Realist Philosophy of Science (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateman, Bradley W. “‘Human Logic’ and Keynes’s Economics: A Comment,” Eastern Economic Journal 15 (January–March 1989): 63–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beed, Clive. “Philosophy of Science and Contemporary Economics: An Overview,” Journal of Post Keynesian Economics 13 (Summer 1991): 459–494.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, Roy. A Realist Theory of Science, 2nd ed. (Leeds: Leeds Books), 1978 [1975]. Brighton, Harvester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, Roy. The Possibility of Naturalism: A Philosophic Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences (Brighton: Harvester), 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, Roy. Scientific Realism and Human Emancipation (London: Verso), 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, Roy. Philosophy and the Idea of Freedom (Oxford: Basil Blackwell), 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boler, J.F. Charles Peirce and Scholastic Realism: A Study of Peirce’s Relation to John Duns Scotus (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown-Collier, E.K. “Keynes’ View of an Organic Universe: The Implications,” Review of Social Economy 43 (1985): 14–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown-Collier, E.K. and Bausor, R. “The Epistemological Foundations of the General Theory,” Scottish Journal of Political Economy 35 (August 1988): 227–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carabelli, Anna M. “Keynes on Cause, Chance and Probability,” in A. Lawson and H. Pesaran, eds., Keynes’ Economics: Methodological Issues (London: Croom Helm, 1985), pp. 151–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, Alan F. What is This Thing Called Science? (Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  • Commons, John R. Institutional Economics—Its Place in Political Economy (New York: Macmillan, 1934). Reprinted 1990 with a new introduction by M. Rutherford (New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, John B. “Keynes on Atomism and Organicism,” The Economic Journal 99 (December 1989): 1159–1172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis, John B. “Keynes and Organicism,” Journal of Post Keynesian Economics 12(2) (Winter 1989–90): 308–315.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow, Shiela C. Macroeconomic Thought: A Methodological Approach (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1985).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow, Shiela C. “Beyond Dualism,” Cambridge Journal of Economics 14 (June 1990): 143–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgibbons, Athol. Keynes’s Vision: A New Political Economy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Georgescu-Roegen, Nicholas. The Entropy Law and the Economic Process (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruchy, Allan G. “The Philosophical Basis of the New Keynesian Economics,” Ethics 58 (July 1948): 235–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamouda, Omar F. and Smithin, John N. “Some Remarks on ‘Uncertainty and Economic Analysis,” The Economic Journal 98(1) (March 1988): 159–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, Rom. Varieties of Realism (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, John A. Wealth and Life: A Study in Values (London: Macmillan, 1929).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, Geoffrey M. Economics and Institutions: A Manifesto for a Modern Institutonal Economics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, Geoffrey M. “The Reconstruction of Economics: Is There a Place for Neoclassical Theory?” Journal of Economic Issues 26 (September 1992): 749–767.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodgson, Geoffrey M. Economics and Evolution: Bringing Life Back into Economics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanth, Rajani K. “Economic Theory and Realism: Outlines of a Reconstruction,” Methodus 3 (December 1991): 37–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, Antony. “Uncertainty and Economic Analysis,” The Economic Journal 95 (December 1985): 909–927.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, Antony. “The Relative/Absolute Nature of Knowledge and Economic Analysis,” The Economic Journal 97 (December 1987): 951–970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, Antony. “Abstrction, Tendencies and Stylised Facts: A Realist Approach to Economic Analysis,” Cambridge Journal of Economics 13 (March 1989): 59–78. Reprinted in A. Lawson, J.G. Palma, and J. Sender, eds., Kaldor’s Political Economy (London: Acdemic Press, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, Jarrett ed. Scientific Realism (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Maki, Uskali. “On the Problem of Realism in Economics,” Ricerche Economiche 43 (gennaio–giugno 1989): 176–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maki, Uskali. “Practical Syllogism, Entrepreneurship, and the Invisible Hand,” in D. Lavoie, ed., Economics and Hermeneutics (London: Routledge, 1991, pp. 149–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manicas, P.T. A History and Philosophy of the Social Sciences (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987).

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, James G. Living Systems (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  • Myrdal, Gunnar. in P. Streeten, ed., Value in Social Theory: A Selection of Essays on Methodology (New York: Harper, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Donnell, Rodney M. Keynes: Philosophy, Economics and Politics (London: Macmillan, 1989).

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, Charles Sanders, in C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss, eds., Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume VI, Scientific Metaphysics (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1935).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotheim, Roy J. “Organicism and the Role of the Individual in Keynes’ Thought,” Journal of Post Keynesian Economics 12 (Winter 1989–90): 317–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sayer, Andrew. Method in Social Science: A Realist Approach (London: Hutchinson, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  • Veblen, Thorstein B. in L. Ardzrooni, ed., Essays in Our Changing Order (New York: Viking Press, 1934).

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, Alfred N. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1929).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilber, Charles K. and Harrison, Robert S. “The Methodological Basis of Institutional Economics: Pattern Model, Storytelling, and Holism,” Journal of Economic Issues 12 (March 1978): 61–89. Reprinted in W.J. Samuels Institutional Economics, vol. 2. (Aldershot: Edward Elgar 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  • Winslow, Edward A. “‘Human Logic’ and Keynes’s Economics,” Eastern Economic Journal 12 (October–December 1986): 413–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winslow, Edward A. “Organic Interdependence, Uncertainty and Economic Analysis,” The Economic Journal 99 (December 1989): 1173–1182.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1993 Kluwer Academic Publsihers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bush, P.D. (1993). The Methodology of Institutional Economics: A Pragmatic Instrumentalist Perspective. In: Tool, M.R. (eds) Institutional Economics: Theory, Method, Policy. Recent Economic Thought, vol 31. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-585-29604-3_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-585-29604-3_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-9346-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-0-585-29604-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics