Advertisement

At the Potter’s Wheel : An Argument for Material Agency

  • Lambros Malafouris
Chapter

1

Consider a potter throwing a vessel on the wheel (Fig. 2.1). Think of the complex ways brain, body, wheel and clay relate and interact with one another throughout the different stages of this activity and try to imagine some of the resources (physical, mental or biological) needed for the enaction of this creative process. Focus, for instance, on the first minutes of action when the potter attempts to centre the lump of clay on the wheel. The hands are grasping the clay. The fingers, bent slightly following the surface curvature, sense the clay and exchange vital tactile information necessary for a number of crucial decisions that are about to follow in the next few seconds. What is it that guides the dextrous positioning of the potter’s hands and decides upon the precise amount of forward or downward pressure necessary for centring a lump of clay on the wheel? How do the potter’s fingers come to know the precise force of the appropriate grip? What makes these questions even more...

Keywords

Agency Problem Intentional State Material Engagement Mental Causation Technical Choice 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Bateson, G., 1973. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. London: Granada.Google Scholar
  2. Brooks, R. A., 1991. Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence 47: 39–59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Callon, M. and Latour, B., 1981. Unscrewing the Big Leviathan. In Advances in Social Theory and Methodology: Towards an Integration of Micro and Macro-Sociology, edited by K. Knorr-Cetina and A. V. Cicouvel, pp. 277–303. Routledge, Boston, MA.Google Scholar
  4. Gazzaniga, M. S., 1998. The Mind’s Past. University of California Press, Berkeley.Google Scholar
  5. Clark, A., 1997. Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  6. Clark, A. and Chalmers, D., 1998. The Extended Mind. Analysis 58(1): 10–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Dennet, D. C., 1987. The Intentional Stance. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  8. Gallagher, S., 2005. How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Gallagher, S., 2000. Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 4(1): 14–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Gell, A., 1998. Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford.Google Scholar
  11. Gibbs, R. W., 2001. Intentions as emergent products of social interactions. In Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition, edited by F. Bertram, L. J. Moses and D. A. Baldwin. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  12. Gibson, J. J., 1979. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston, MA.Google Scholar
  13. Howhy, J. and Frith, C., 2004. Can Neuroscience explain consciousness? Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 180–198.Google Scholar
  14. Hutchins, E., 1995. Cognition in the Wild. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  15. Knappett, C., 2005. Thinking Through Material Culture: An Interdisciplinary Perspective. University of Pennsylvania Press, Philadelphia.Google Scholar
  16. Knappett, C., 2004. The affordances of things: A post-Gibsonian perspective on the relationality of mind and matter. In Rethinking Materiality: The Engagement of Mind with the Material World, edited by E. DeMarrais, C. Gosden and C. Renfrew, pp. 43–51. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  17. Knappett, C., 2006. Beyond Skin: Layering and Networking in Art and Archaeology. Cambridge Archaeological Journal 16(2): 239–251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kirsh, D., 1995. The intelligent use of space, Artificial Intelligence 73(1–2): 31–68.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Kirsh, D., 1996. Adapting the environment instead of oneself. Adaptive Behavior 4(3–4): 415–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Libet, B., 1985. Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8: 529–566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Libet, B., 1999. Do we have free will? Journal of Consciousness Studies 6: 47–58.Google Scholar
  22. Libet, B., Gleason, C. A., Wright, E. W. and Pearl, D. K., 1983. Time of conscious intention to act in relation to onset of cerebral activity (readiness potential). The unconscious initiation of a freely voluntary act. Brain 102: 623–642.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Malafouris, L., 2004. The cognitive basis of material engagement: Where brain, body and culture conflate. In Rethinking Materiality: The Engagement of Mind with the Material World, edited by E. DeMarrais, C. Gosden and C. Renfrew, pp. 53–62. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  24. Malafouris, L., in press. Linear B as distributed cognition: Excavating a mind not limited by the skin. In material culture. In Excavating the Mind: Cross-sections Through Culture, Cognition and Materiality, edited by M. Jessen, N. Johanssen and H. J. Jensen. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus.Google Scholar
  25. Malafouris, L. and C. Renfrew, editors, in press. The Cognitive Life of Things: Recasting the Boundaries of the Mind. McDonald Institute Monographs, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  26. Merleau-Ponty, M., 1962. Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge, London.Google Scholar
  27. Schiffer, B. and Skibo, J. M., 1997. The explanation of artifact variability. American Antiquity 62: 27–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Searle, J. R., 1983. Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  29. Tsakiris, M. and Haggard, P., 2005. Experimenting with the acting self. Cognitive Neuropsychology 22(3/4): 387–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Van der Leeuw, S. E., 1993. Giving the potter a choice: Conceptual aspects of pottery techniques. In Technological Choices: Transformations in Material Cultures since the Neolithic, edited by P. Lemonnier, pp. 238–288. Routledge, London.Google Scholar
  31. Van der Leeuw, S. E., 1994. Cognitive aspects of technique. In The Ancient Mind, edited by C. Renfrew and E. Zubrow, pp. 135–142. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Van Gelder, T., 1995. What might cognition be, if not computation? Journal of Philosophy 91: 345–381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Walter, W. G., 1953. The Living Brain. Duckworth, London.Google Scholar
  34. Wegner, D. M., 2002. The Illusion of Conscious Will. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.Google Scholar
  35. Wegner, D. M., 2003. The mind’s best trick: How we experience conscious will. Trends in Cognitive Science 7: 65–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Wegner, D. M., 2004. Precis of the illusion of conscious will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27: 649–692.Google Scholar
  37. Wertsch, J. V., 1998. Mind as Action. Oxford University Press, New York, NY.Google Scholar
  38. Wittgenstein, L., 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Basil Blackwell, Oxford.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.McDonald Institute for Archaeological ResearchCambridge UniversityUK

Personalised recommendations