Skip to main content

Where Brain, Body and World Collide

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Material Agency

Introduction

The brain fascinates because it is the biological organ of mindfulness itself. It is the inner engine that drives intelligent behaviour. Such a depiction provides a worthy antidote to the once-popular vision of the mind as somehow lying outside the natural order. But it is a vision with a price. For it has concentrated much theoretical attention on an uncomfortably restricted space; the space of the inner neural machine, divorced from the wider world which then enters the story only via the hygienic gateways of perception and action. Recent work in neuroscience, robotics and psychology casts doubt on the effectiveness of such a shrunken perspective. Instead, it stresses the unexpected intimacy of brain, body and world and invites us to attend to the structure and dynamics of extended adaptive systems – ones involving a much wider variety of factors and forces. Whilst it needs to be handled with some caution, I believe there is much to be learnt from this broader vision. The mind itself, if such a vision is correct, is best understood as the activity of an essentially situated brain: a brain at home in its proper bodily, cultural and environmental niche.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See B.C. Smith (1996), p. 148. Note that Smith’s worry, at root, concerns the gap between physiological and semantic or intentional questions.

  2. 2.

    Thus we read, for example, that computational approaches make possible “a science of structure and function divorced from material substance [that] ... can answer questions traditionally posed by psychologists” (Pylyshyn (1986, p. 68).

  3. 3.

    See, for example, David Marr’s (1982) distinction between the levels of computation, algorithm and implementation.

  4. 4.

    See, for example, Simon (1982), Dawkins (1982), Clark (1997) Chapter 4.

  5. 5.

    For a review, see Clark (1997) Chapter 5.

  6. 6.

    Schieber & Hibbard (1993).

  7. 7.

    The notion of synergy aims to capture the idea of links that constrain the collective unfolding of a system comprising many parts. For example, the front wheels of a car exhibit a built-in synergy which allows a single driver ‘command’ (at the steering wheel) to affect them both at once. Synergetic links may also be learnt, as when we acquire an automated skill, and may be neurally as well as brute-physiologically grounded. See Kelso (1995), pp. 38, 52.

  8. 8.

    For a survey of such experiments, see Welch (1978).

  9. 9.

    In this case, without any perceived shift in the visual scene.

  10. 10.

    In a somewhat related vein, Caminiti et al. (1990) show that the directional preference of individual cells encoding reaching movement commands varies according to initial arm position. See also discussion in Jeannerod (1997), Chapter 1.

  11. 11.

    Though much of the connectivity is reciprocal. See Van Essen & Anderson (1990), Churchland et al. (1991), p. 40.

  12. 12.

    The exception is if subjects are told in advance to watch out for changes to a certain feature. See McConkie (1990), Churchland et al. (1994).

  13. 13.

    Thanks to David Clark for pointing this out.

  14. 14.

    See Churchland et al. (1994), p. 44, Wurz & Mohler (1976).

  15. 15.

    For an accessible introduction, see P.M. Churchland (1995).

  16. 16.

    This is known as a ‘subsumption’ architecture, because the layers each constitute a complete behaviour-producing system and interact only in simple ways such as by one layers subsuming (turning off) the activity of another or by one layer’s co-opting and hence ‘building-in’ the activity of another (see Brooks (1991)).

  17. 17.

    By a process of spreading activation amongst landmark encoding nodes – see Mataric (1991).

  18. 18.

    Such representations bear some resemblance to what the ecological psychologist J.J. Gibson called “affordances,” although Gibson himself would reject our emphasis on inner states and encodings. For an affordance is the potential of use and activity that the local environment offers to a specific kind of being: chairs afford sitting (to humans) and so on. See Gibson (1979). The philosopher Ruth Millikan has developed a nice account of action-oriented representation under the label ‘pushmipullyu representation’ – see Millikan (1995).

  19. 19.

    This example is borrowed from Clark (1995).

  20. 20.

    The story is detailed in Triantafyllou & Triantafyllou (1995) and further discussed in Clark (1997). A 49 inch eight-segment anodised aluminum and lycra robot tuna is being used at MIT (Massachusetts Institute of Technology) to test the details of the theory.

  21. 21.

    See Edwards, Baum & Morrow-Howell (1994), Baum (1991).

  22. 22.

    Some of this additional structure is maintained and provided by family and friends. (But similarly, much of our own wideware is provided by language, culture and institutions which we do not ourselves create.)

  23. 23.

    Such counterbalancing is, as Marcel Kinsbourne has usefully reminded me, a somewhat delicate and complex matter. The mere provision of the various props and aids is useless unless the patient remains located in a stable, familiar environment. And the ability of different patients to make use of such added environmental structure itself varies according to the nature and extent of the neurally based deficit.

  24. 24.

    See Dawkins (1982).

  25. 25.

    See Kutsch et al. (1993). Thanks to Joe Faith for drawing this example to my attention.

  26. 26.

    See, for example,, Thelen & Smith (1994), Port and Van Gelder (1995).

  27. 27.

    See, for example,, Hutchins (1995).

  28. 28.

    See Clark (1997), Crutchfield & Mitchell (1995), Mitchell et al. (1994), van Gelder (1995).

  29. 29.

    For example,, Fodor (1975), Fodor & Pylyshyn (1988).

References

  • Ballard, D. (1991). Animate vision. Artificial Intelligence, 48, 57–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ballard, D., Hayhoe, M., Pook, P. & Rao, R. (1997). Deictic codes for the embodiment of cognition. Behavioral & Brain Sciences 20, 723–767.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum, C. (1991). Addressing the needs of the cognitively impaired elderly from a family policy perspective. American Journal of Occupational Therapy, 45(7), 594–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caminiti, R., Johnson, P., Burnod, Y., Galli, C., & Ferrina, S. (1990). Shift of preferred directions of premotor cortical cells with arm movements performed across the workspace. Experimental Brain Research, 82, 228–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P., Ramachandran, V., & Sejnowski, T. (1994). A critique of pure vision. In C. Koch & J. Davis (Eds.), Large-Scale Neuronal Theories of the Brain . Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). The Neurocomputational Perspective. Cambridge: MIT/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1995). The Engine of Reason, the feat of the soul. MIT press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1995). I am John's brain. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2(2), 144–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being There: Putting Brain, Body and World Together Again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1998). Twisted tales: Cansal Complexity and cognitive scientific explanation. Minds & Machines. 8, 79–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connell, J. (1989). A Colony Architecture for an Artificial Creature. MIT AI Lab Tech Report II, 5, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crutchfield, J. & Mitchell, M. (1995). The evolution of emergent computation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 92, 10742–10746.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (1982). The Extended Phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1995). Darwin's Dangerous Idea. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • DiPelligrino, J., Klatzky, R., & McCloskey, B. (1992). Time course of preshaping for functional responses to objects. Journal of Motor Behavior, 21, 307–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, D., Baum, C., & Morrow-Howell, N. (1994). Home environments of inner city elderly: Do they facilitate or inhibit function? The Gerontologist: Program Abstracts of 47th Annual Scientific Meeting, 34(1), 64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Felleman, D., & VanEssen, D. (1991). Distributed hierarchial processing in primate visual cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 1, 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The Language of Thought. New York: Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J., & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: A critical analysis. Cognition, 28, 3–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, F. (1977). Evolution and Tinkering. Science, 196, 1161–1166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod (1997). The Cognitive Neuroscience of Action. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, S. (1995). Dynamic Patterns. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knierim, J., & Van Essen, D. (1992). Visual cortex: Cartography, connectivity and concurrent processing. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 2, 150–155. 31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kutsch, W., Schaarz, G., Fischer, H., & Kautz, H. (1993). Wireless transmission of muscle potentials during free flight of a locust. Journal of Experimental Biology, 185, 367–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mataric, M. (1991). Navigating with a Rat Brain: A neurobiologically inspired model for robot spatial representation. In J.A. Meyer & S. Wilson (eds) From Animals to Animats I. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McConkie, G. W. (1990). Where vision and cognition meet. Paper presented at the H.F.S.P. Workshop on Object and Scene Perception, Leuven, Belgium.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNaughton, B., & Nadel, L. (1990). Hebb-Marr networks and the neurobiological representation of action in space. In M. Gluck & D. Rumelhart (Eds.), Neuroscience and Connectionist Theory (pp. 1–64). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1995). Pushmi-Pullyu representations. In J. Tomberline (ed) Philosophical Perspectives 9: Connectionism and Philosophical Psychology. Ridgeview, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, M. Crutchfield, J., & Hraber, P. (1994). Evolving cellular automata to perform computations. Physica D, 75, 361–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchie, D., & Johnson, R. (1984). The Creative Computer. U.K.: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (Ed.). (1987). The Robots Dilemma: The Frame Problem in Artificial Intelligence . Norwood: Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reeke, G., & Edelman, G. (1988). Real brains and artificial intelligence. Daedalus, Winter, 143–173.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolatti, G., Fadiga, L., & Fogassi, L. (1996). Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions. Cognitive Brain Research, 3, 131–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schieber, M. (1990). How might the motor cortex individuate movements? Trends in Neuroscience, 13(11), 440–444. 32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schieber, M., & Hibbard, L. (1993). How somatotopic is the motor cortex hand area? Science, 261, 489–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1982). Models of Bounded Rationality (Vol. I and II). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. C. (1996). On the Origin of Objects. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thach, W., Goodkin, H., & Keating, J. (1992). The cerebellum and the adaptive coordination of movement. Animal Review of Neuroscience, 15, 403–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. (1994). A Dynamic Systems Approach to the Development of Cognition and Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Triantafyllou, M., & Triantafyllou, G. (1995). An efficient swimming machine. Scientific American, 272(3), 64–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Essen, D., & Anderson, C. (1990). Information processing strategies and pathways in the primate retina and visual cortex. In S. Zornetzer, J. Davis, & C. Lau (eds) An Introduction to Neural and Electronic Networks (p. 43–72). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Essen, D., & Gallant, J. (1994). Neural mechanisms of form and motion processing in the primate visual system. Neuron, 13, 1–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T., & Port, R. (1995). It's about time: An overview of the dynamical approach to cognition. In R. Port & T. v. Gelder (Eds.), Mind as Motion: Explorations in the Dynamics of Cognition (pp. 1–44). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Welch, R. (1978). Perceptual Modification: Adapting to Altered Sensory Environments. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wurz, R., & Mohler, C. (1976). Enhancement of visual response in monkey striate cortex and frontal eye fields. Journal of Neurophysiology, 39, 766–772.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yarbus, A. (1967). Eye movements and vision. New York: Plenum Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Stephen Graubard and the participants at the Daedalus Authors Meeting (Paris, October 1997) for a wealth of useful advice, good criticism and wise counsel. Special thanks to Jean Pierre Changeux, Marcel Kinsbourne, Vernon Mountcastle, Guilio Tonini, Steven Quartz and Semir Zeki. As usual, any remaining errors are all my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andy Clark .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2008 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Clark, A. (2008). Where Brain, Body and World Collide . In: Knappett, C., Malafouris, L. (eds) Material Agency. Springer, Boston, MA. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-74711-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics