Skip to main content

How the Ceteris Paribus Laws of Physics Lie

  • Chapter
Nature’s Principles

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 4))

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Armstrong, D. (1983). What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, R. (1978). A Realist Theory of Science. Hassocks, Sussex, 2 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the Law of Physics Lie. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s Capacities and their Measurement. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1992). Aristotelian natures and the modern experimental method. In Earman, J., editor, Inference, Explanation and Other Philosophical Frustrations, pages 44–71, Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1995a). Ceteris paribus laws and socio-economic machines. The Monist, 78:276–294.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1995b). How laws relate what happens: Against a regularity account. In Stachowiak, H., editor, Pragmatik. Handbuch pragmatischen Denkens, volume V, pages 305–314, Hamburg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The Dappled World. A Study of the Boundaries of Science. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The Nature of Psychological Explanation. Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980a). Essays on Actions and Events, chapter Mental Events, pages 207–225. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980b). Essays on Actions and Events, chapter Actions, Reasons and Causes, pages 3–19. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1993). Replies. In Stoecker, R., editor, Reflecting Davidson, Berlin/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1995). Laws and cause. Dialectica, 49:263–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1977). Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science, 44:248–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducasse, C. J. (1968). On the analysis of causality [1957]. In his Truth, Knowledge and Causation, pages 15–20. London/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. and Roberts, J. (1999). Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese, 118:439–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., Glymour, C. and Mitchell, S. (2002). Editorial. Erkenntnis, 57:277–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., Roberts, J. and Smith, S. (2002). Ceteris paribus lost. Erkenntnis, 57:281–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1991). You can fool some of the people all of the time, everything else being equal. Hedged laws and psychological explanations. Mind, 100:19–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1973). Aquinas. In: G. E. M. Anscombe and P. T. Geach Three Philosophers. Oxford, pages 64–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Laws, theories, and generalizations. In Grünbaum, A. and Salmon, W., editors, The Limitations of Deductivism, pages 37–46, Berkeley/London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (2002). A semantics and methodology for ceteris paribus hypotheses. Erkenntnis, 57:395–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1954). Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guarini, M. (2000). Horgan and Tienson on ceteris paribus laws. Philosophy of Science, 67:301–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman, D. M. (1992). The Inexact and Separate Science of Economics. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1988). Provisos: A problem concerning the inferential function of scientific theories. In Grünbaum, A. and Salmon, W. C., editors, The Limitations of Deductivism, pp. 19–36, Berkeley/London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T. and Tienson, J. (1996). Connectionism and the Philosophy of Psychology. Cambridge, Mass./London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hüttemann, A. (1998). Laws and dispositions. Philosophy of Science, 65:121–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson, I. (1980). Ceteris paribus clauses, closure clauses and falsifi-ability. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 11:16–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, G. (1980). The many sciences and the one world. Journal of Philosophy, 77:773–791.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, G. (2000). Handeln und Verursachen. Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kincaid, H. (1996). Philosophical Foundations of the Social Sciences. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klee, R. (1992). Anomalous monism, ceteris paribus and psychological explanation. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 43:389–403.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurtzman, D. R. (1973). Ceteris paribus clauses: Their illumination and elimination. American Philosophical Quarterly, 10:35–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1978). Philosophical Papers, volume I, chapter Fallibilism and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes, pages 8–101. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1993). Natural laws and the problem of provisos. Erkenntnis, 38:133–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical Papers. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1999). All else being equal. Philosophy, 74:155–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J. L. (1980). The Cement of the Universe. A Study of Causation [1974]. Oxford, 2 edition.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1973). A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive [1843]. Toronto, 4 edition. (Collected Works, Vol. VII/VIII).

    Google Scholar 

  • Morreau, M. (1999). Other things being equal. Philosophical Studies, 96:163–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science. London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Persky, J. (1990). Ceteris paribus. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 4:187–193.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. and Rey, G. (1995). When other thing’s aren’t equal: Saving ceteris paribus laws from vacuity. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 46:81–110.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1974). Replies to my critics. In Schilpp, P. A., editor, The Philosophy of Karl Popper, Bk. II, pages 961–1197, La Salle, Ill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, Mass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, L. (1984). The nature and significance of economic science [1935]. In Hausman, D. M., editor, The Philosophy of Economics, pages 83–110, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human Knowledge. Its Scope and Limits. New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1986). On the notion of cause [1912]. In his Mysticism and Logic, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1991). Ceteris paribus laws. Mind, 100:1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2001a). Pietroski and Rey on ceteris paribus laws. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52:359–370.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G. (2001b). What is ‘normal’? An evolution-theoretic foundation of normic laws and their relation to statistical normality. Philosophy of Science, 68:476–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1959). Truisms as the grounds for historical explanations. In Gardiner, P., editor, Theories of History, pages 443–475, New York/London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriven, M. (1961). The key property of physical laws inaccuracy. In Feigl, H. and Maxwell, G., editors, Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science, pages 91–101, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silverberg, A. (1996). Psychological laws and non-monotonic logic. Erkenntnis, 44:199–224.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, S. (2002). Violated laws, ceteris paribus clauses, and capacities. Synthese, 130:235–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, M. (1986). Events and causality. Journal of Philosophy, 83:249–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swartz, N. (1985). The Concept of Physical Law. Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1992). Naturalism and the mental. Mind, 101:421–441.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and Symmetry. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warfield, T. (1993). Folk psychological ceteris paribus laws? Philosophical Studies, 71:99–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2000). Explanation and invariance in the special sciences. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51:197–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2005 Springer

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Keil, G. (2005). How the Ceteris Paribus Laws of Physics Lie. In: Faye, J., Needham, P., Scheffler, U., Urchs, M. (eds) Nature’s Principles. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/1-4020-3258-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics