Advertisement

Deconstructing The Opining Verbs

  • Melanie Bervoets
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy book series (SLAP, volume 102)

Abstract

To account for the characteristics of future-directed opining verbs observed in Chap.  2—including the kinds of eventualities the verbs can be used to describe, and the types of subjects and objects they can combine with—the most promising semantic analysis attributes to each verb both an episodic attestation element and a modal opinion term. Combining this with the desideratum from Chap.  3 for EXH to be able to combine directly with the modal, as well as independent evidence from the potential attachment sites of adverbials like again, entries inspired by Kratzer (Decomposing attitude verbs. In: Talk in honor of A. Mittwoch. The Hebrew University, Jerusalem, 2006) and Hacquard (Nat Lang Semant 18:79–114, 2010) can be fleshed out in such a way that each of the two elements is exposed within the semantic structure. The modal details will vary from verb to verb, both in terms of force and modal background. The attestation element will make the verbs episodic, and so combination with a dispositional operator, HAB, is required to get the attitude-like manifestations of the verbs. The establishment of such dispositional opinions will align the future-directed opining verbs with other opining verbs, but contrast them with other submission verbs, a situation that can be tied to the presence of lexically encoded opinion. Finally, clearly laying out the semantic details attributed to the verbs highlights an additional advantages of adopting the analysis outlined in Chap.  2, one that stems from the verbs’ modality.

Keywords

Opinion verbs Propositional attitude verbs Intensionality Habituality Free choice Semantic decomposition Dispositions Speech reporting verbs Proffering verbs 

References

  1. Anand, Pranav, and Valentine Hacquard. 2008. Epistemics with attitude. In SALT XVIII, ed. T. Friedman and S. Ito. Ithaca: Cornell University.Google Scholar
  2. Beck, S., and K. Johnson. 2004. Double objects again. Linguistic Inquiry 35(1): 97–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Boneh, Nora, and Edit Doron. 2013. Hab and Gen in the expression of habituality. Genericity 43: 176–191.Google Scholar
  4. Boyd, Julian, and J.P. Thorne. 1969. The semantics of modal verbs. Journal of Linguistics 5(1): 57–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Dahl, Östen. 1975. On generics. In Formal semantics of natural language, ed. Ed Keenan, 99–112. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Fodor, J., and E. Lepore. 2001. Morphemes matter: The continuing case against lexical decomposition. Manuscript, Rutgers University.Google Scholar
  7. Hacquard, Valentine. 2010. On the event relativity of modal auxiliaries. Natural Language Semantics 18: 79–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Kratzer, Angelika. 2006. Decomposing attitude verbs. In Talk in honor of A. Mittwoch. Jerusalem: The Hebrew University.Google Scholar
  9. Lawler, John M. 1973. Studies in English generics: University of Michigan, Ann Arbor dissertation.Google Scholar
  10. Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice theoretical approach. In Meaning, use and interpretation of language, ed. Rayner Bauerle, Christoph Schwarze, and Arnim von Stechow, 209–250. Boston: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
  11. Menendez-Benito, Paula. 2012. On dispositional sentences. Genericity 43: 276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. von Stechow, A. 1995. Lexical decomposition in syntax. In The lexicon in the organization of language, ed. Egli et al. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  13. Vendler, Zeno. 1957. Verbs and times. Philosophical Review LXVI: 143–160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature B.V. 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Melanie Bervoets
    • 1
  1. 1.TorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations