Advertisement

Wide Content Explanations

  • Ljudevit Hanžek
Chapter
Part of the Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action book series (HSNA, volume 6)

Abstract

In this paper, the author argues that ascriptions of wide mental content form a part of successful explanations of action. Ascriptions of wide mental content result in wide explanations; ascriptions of narrow mental content result in narrow explanations; descriptions of an agent’s mental states in terms of their physical properties result in physical explanations. In Sect. 2.1, he outlines the central problem of the paper. In Sect. 2.2, he explicates the criteria for evaluating competing explanations, which will be used in resolving the issue. Section 2.3 defines an action-context, a set of elements that are present in every situation in which explanation of action is sought for. Section 2.4 shows, very roughly, what a wide explanation looks like. In Sect. 2.5, the author presents some familiar objections to the very idea of content explanations, whether wide or narrow. He also responds to these objections. Section 2.6 provides reasons for thinking that physical explanations of action are inadequate. Section 2.7 shows that narrow explanations are also not appropriate.

Keywords

Action Explanation Narrow mental content Physical explanation Wide mental content 

References

  1. Achinstein, P. (1984). The pragmatic character of explanation. PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 275–292.Google Scholar
  2. Aizawa, K., & Gillet, C. (2009). The (multiple) realization of psychological and other properties in the sciences. Mind and Language, 24(2), 181–208.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Alvarez, M. (2007). The causalism/anti-causalism debate in the theory of action: What it is and why it matters. In A. Leist (Ed.), Action in context (pp. 103–123). Berlin: De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  4. Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brown, C. (2016). Narrow mental content. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/content-narrow/. Accessed: 27 May 2016.
  6. Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4(1), 73–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review, 95(1), 3–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chalmers, D. (2002). The components of content. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 608–633). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Davidson, D. (1963). Actions, reasons and causes. The Journal of Philosophy, 60(23), 685–700.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association (Vol. 61, pp. 441–58).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Egan, F. (2009). Wide content. In A. Beckermann, B. McLaughlin, & S. Walter (Eds.), Oxford handbook of the philosophy of mind (pp. 351–366). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences: Or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis. Synthese, 28(2), 97–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Kandel, E., Schwartz, J., Jessell, T., Siegelbaum, S., & Hudspeth, A. J. (2013). Principles of neural science. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  15. Kriegel, U. (2008). Real narrow content. Mind and Language, 23(3), 304–328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Maguire, E., & Woollett, K. (2011). Acquiring ‘the knowledge’ of London’s layout drives structural brain changes. Current Biology, 21(24–2), 2109–2114.Google Scholar
  17. McDermott, M. (1986). Narrow content. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 64(3), 277–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. McKitrick, J. (2005). Are dispositions causally relevant? Synthese, 144(3), 357–371.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Owens, D. (1989). Levels of explanation. Mind, 98(389), 59–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Potochnik, A. (2010). Levels of explanation reconceived. Philosophy of Science, 77(1), 59–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. H. Capitan & D. D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
  22. Putnam, H. (1975a). The meaning of ‘meaning’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 7, 131–193.Google Scholar
  23. Putnam, H. (1975b). Mind, language, and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Schiffer, S. (2016). An introduction to content and its role in explanation. http://www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/courses/content/papers/schiffer.html. Accessed 26 May 2016.
  26. Segal, G. (1989). Seeing what is not there. The Philosophical Review, 98(2), 189–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Vanderbeeken, R., & Weber, E. (2002). Dispositional explanations of behavior. Behavior and Philosophy, 30, 43–59.Google Scholar
  28. Van Fraassen, B. (2013). The pragmatic theory of explanation. In A. Bird & J. Ladyman (Eds.), Arguing about science (pp. 366–408). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  29. Wall, J. T., Xu, J., & Wang, X. (2002). Human brain plasticity: An emerging view of the multiple substrates and mechanisms that cause cortical changes and related sensory dysfunctions after injuries of sensory inputs from the body. Brain Research Reviews, 39, 181–215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. White, S. L. (1982). Partial character and the language of thought. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 347–365.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Ljudevit Hanžek
    • 1
  1. 1.Faculty of Humanities and Social Sciences, University of SplitSplitCroatia

Personalised recommendations