Advertisement

From Aristotle to Consciousness and Intentionality

  • Grant Gillett
Chapter

Abstract

Neo-Aristotelian accounts of the human psyche incorporate our meaningful contact with the world such that complex connectivity within the brain and between brain and world is the basis of consciousness and mental function (a “contact view”). Intelligent contact with things shapes human consciousness and cognition in ways reflecting truth-related thought and talk about the world in a context of communication, judgement, and knowledge. Human intersubjectivity thus allows us to triangulate on the objects we encounter and configure our dealings with them in communicable ways grounded in truth and falsity. Aristotle’s naturalistic view of the soul as an active, self-organising system implies that distinctively human life corresponds to a progressive integration of neural functions, enabling us to tell (in both senses) what is happening and what things really are.

Keywords

Autopoiesis Embodiment Neurophilosophy Discursive psychology 

References and Bibliography

  1. Adams, F., Drebushenko, D., Fuller, G., & Stecker, R. (1990). Narrow content: Fodor’s folly. Mind & Language, 5(3), 214–229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Allport, A. (1993). Visual attention. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 631–682). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. Baars, B. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Science, 6(1), 47–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bartolomeo, P. (2002). The relationship between visual perception and visual mental imagery: A reappraisal of the neuropsychological evidence. Cortex, 38(3), 357–378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Brentano, F. (1874 [1973]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint (L. McAlister, Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  6. Brentano, F. (1929 [1981]). Sensory and noetic consciousness (M. Schattle & L. McAlister, Trans.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  7. Caston, V. (1996). Why Aristotle needs imagination. Phronesis, 41, 20–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  9. Damasio, A. (1996). The somatic marker hypothesis and the possible functions of the prefrontal cortex. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 351, 1413–1429.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  11. Davidson, D. (2001). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition, 79, 1–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  14. Dreyfus, H., & Taylor, C. (2015). Retrieving realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Edelman, G. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire: On the matter if the mind. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  16. Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  17. Freeman, W. J. (2015). Mechanism and significance of global coherence in scalp EEG. Current Opinion in Biology, 23, 199–205.Google Scholar
  18. Frege, G. (1977). Logical investigations (P. Geach, Trans. & Ed.) Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Frege, G. (1980). Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (P. Geach & M. Black, Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  20. Freud, S. (1986). The essentials of psychoanalysis (J. Strachey, Trans.). Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  21. Friston, K. (2010). The free energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews/Neuroscience, 11, 127–134.Google Scholar
  22. Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Gillett, G. (1992). Representation, meaning and thought. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Gillett, G. (1993). Ought and wellbeing. Inquiry, 36, 287–306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Gillett, G. (1997). Husserl, Wittgenstein and the snark. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LVII, 331–350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Gillett, G. (2008). Subjectivity and being somebody: Human identity and neuroethics (St Andrews Series on Philosophy and Public Affairs). Exeter: Imprint Academic.Google Scholar
  27. Gillett, G. (2014). Concepts, consciousness and counting by pigeons. Mind, 123, 1147–1153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Gillett, G., & Liu, S. (2012). Free will and Necker’s cube: Reason, language and top-down control in cognitive neuroscience. Philosophy, 87(1), 29–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Gillett, G., & McMillan, J. (2001). Consciousness and intentionality. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Griffiths, P. (1997). What emotions really are. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Haldane, J. (1992). Aquinas and the active intellect. Philosophy, 67, 199–210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Harre, R., & Gillett, G. (1994). The discursive mind. London: Sage.Google Scholar
  33. Hughlings Jackson, J. (1887). Remarks on the evolution and dissolution of the nervous system. British Journal of Psychiatry, 33, 25–48.Google Scholar
  34. Hume, D. (1740 [1969]). A treatise of human nature (E. Mossner, Ed.). London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  35. Hurford, J. R. (2003). The neural basis of predicate-argument structure. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 261–316.Google Scholar
  36. Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Husserl, E. (1950 [1999]). Cartesian meditations (D. Cairns, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  38. Husserl, E. (1954 [1970]). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (D. Carr, Trans.). Chicago: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy (F. Kersten, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Jacquette, D. (2004). The Cambridge companion to Brentano. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Kim, J. (2010). Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. King, J. R., Jacobo, D., Faugeras, F., et al. (2013). Information sharing in the brain indexes consciousness in noncommunicative patients. Current Biology, 23, 1914–1919.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Knott, A. (2012). Sensorimotor cognition and natural language syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  44. Kozma, R., Davies, J., & Freeman, W. J. (2012). Synchronized minima in ECoG power at frequencies between beta-gamma oscillations disclose cortical singularities in cognition. Journal of Neuroscience and Neuroengineering, 1(1), 11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  46. Luria, A. R. (1973). The working brain. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  47. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  48. McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, value and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 34, 57–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). The phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  51. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1973). Consciousness and the acquisition of language (H. Silverman, Trans.). Chicago: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  52. Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
  53. Neisser, U. (1982). Memory observed. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman & Co.Google Scholar
  54. Nussbaum, M. (1990). Love’s knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Rist, J. (1966). Notes on Aristotle De Anima 3.5. Classical Philology, 61, 8–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Robinson, D. (1989). Aristotle’s psychology. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  58. Sorabji, R. (1974). Body and soul in Aristotle. Philosophy, 49, 63–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Strawson, P. (1974). Freedom and resentment and other essays. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
  60. Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5(10), 416–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  62. Tomasello, M. (2014). The natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Treisman, A. (1996). The binding problem. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 6, 171–178.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Tye, M. (1999). Phenomenal consciousness: The explanatory gap as a cognitive illusion. Mind, 108, 705–726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Winch, P. (1958). The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  66. Wood, A. (2003). Kant and the problem of human nature. In B. Jacobs & P. Kain (Eds.), Essays on Kant’s anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  67. Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  68. Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Grant Gillett
    • 1
  1. 1.Dunedin School of MedicineUniversity of OtagoDunedinNew Zealand

Personalised recommendations