Advertisement

Introduction

  • Jamie Carlin Watson
  • Laura K. Guidry-Grimes
Chapter
Part of the Philosophy and Medicine book series (PHME, volume 129)

Abstract

Philosophers and other specialists are increasingly called upon to offer insight and guidance for complex moral decisions, whether as ethics committee members or as ethics consultants. The practice of ethics consultation is especially prominent in health care facilities, and there is growing professional interest in academic programs and fellowships designed to develop skills in assisting with moral decision-making. This phenomenon has raised questions among both academics and medical professionals about the nature and plausibility of anyone’s possessing such a skill, particularly, whether ethics professionals should be regarded as other specialists, as experts who can offer authoritative advice. In this introduction, we explain some of the basic concepts related to moral expertise and review the central debates over its nature, plausibility, scope, and implications, for both theoretical bioethics and clinical practice.

References and Further Reading

  1. Agich, George J. 1995. Authority in ethics consultation. Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 23: 273–283.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. 1998. Core competences for health care ethics consultation. 1st ed. IL: Glenview.Google Scholar
  3. ———. 2011. Core competences for health care ethics consultation. 2nd ed. IL: Glenview.Google Scholar
  4. ———. 2014. Code of ethics and professional responsibilities for healthcare ethics consultants. IL: Glenview http://www.asbh.org/publications/content/asbh-reader.html.Google Scholar
  5. Anscombe, Elizabeth. 1981. Authority in morals. In Faith in a hard ground, ed. Mary Geach and Luke Gormally, 92–100. Charlottesville: Imprint Academic, 2008.Google Scholar
  6. Archard, David. 2011. Why moral philosophers are not and should not be considered moral experts. Bioethics 25 (3): 119–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Arendt, Hannah. 1961. What is authority? In Between past and future: Six exercises in political thought, 91–142. New York: Viking Press.Google Scholar
  8. Aulisio, Mark P. 2003. Meeting the need: Ethics consultation in health care today. In Ethics consultation: From theory to practice, ed. Mark P. Aulisio, Robert M. Arnold, and Stuart J. Younger, 3–22. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Ayer, Alfred J. 1954. Philosophical essays. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  10. Beachamp, Tom, and James Childress. 2013. Principles of biomedical ethics. 7th ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Bergman, Edward J., and Autumn Fiester. 2014. The future of clinical ethics education: Value pluralism, Communication, and mediation. In The future of bioethics, International dialogues, ed. A. Akabayaski, 703–711. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Broad, C.D. 1952. Ethics and the history of philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  13. Brummett, Abram, and Christopher J. Ostertag. 2017. Two troubling trends in the coversation over whether clinical ethics consultants have ethics expertise, HEC Forum. Springer.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10730-017-9321-8.
  14. Burch, Robert W. 1974. Are there moral experts? The Monist 58 (4): 646–658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Caplan, Arthur. 1989. Moral experts and moral expertise: Do either exist? In Clinical ethics: Theory and practice, ed. Barry Hoffmaster, Benjamin Freedman, and Gwen Fraser, 59–87. Clifton: Humana Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Cholbi, Michael. 2007. Moral expertise and the credentials problem. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10: 323–334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Civan, Andrea, and Wanda Pratt. 2007. Threading together patient expertise. AMIA Symposium Proceedings: 140–144.Google Scholar
  18. Coady, David. 2012. What to believe now: Applying epistemology to contemporary issues. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Collins, Harry, and Robert Evans. 2007. Rethinking expertise. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Cowley, Christopher. 2005. A new rejection of moral expertise. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 8: 273–279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. ———. 2012. Expertise, Wisdom, and moral philosophers: A response to Gesang. Bioethics 26 (6): 337–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Cross, Ben. 2016. Moral philosophy, Moral expertise, and the argument from disagreement. Bioethics 30 (3): 188–194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Crosthwaite, Jan. 1995. Moral expertise: A problem in the professional ethics of professional ethicists. Bioethics 9 (5): 361–379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. DeRenzo, Evan. 1994. Providing clinical ethics consultation. HEC Forum 6 (6): 384–389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Döries, A., and K. Hespe-Jungesblut. 2007. Bundesweite Umfrage zur Implementierung Klinischer Ethikberatung in Krankenhäusern. Ethik in der Medizin 19: 148–156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Dreyfus, Hubert and Stuart Dreyfus. 1980. A five-stage model of the mental activities involved in directed skill acquisition. Operations research center report.Google Scholar
  27. ———. 1986. Mind over machine: The power of human intuitive expertise in the era of the computer. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
  28. Driver, Julia. 2006. Autonomy and the asymmetry problem for moral expertise. Philosophical Studies 128 (3): 619–644.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. ———. 2013. Moral expertise: Judgment, Practice, and analysis. Social Philosophy and Policy 30 (1–2): 280–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Dubler, Nancy Neveloff, and Carol B. Liebman. 2011. Bioethics mediation: A guide to shaping shared solutions, revised and expanded. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Fiester, Autumn. 2015. Teaching Nonauthoritarian clinical ethics: Using an inventory of bioethical positions. Hastings Center Report 45 (2): 20–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Fox, E., S. Myers, and R.A. Pearlman. 2007. Ethics consultation in United States Hospitals: A National Survey. American Journal of Bioethics 7 (2): 13–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Frey, R.G. 1978. Moral experts. Personalist 59: 47–52.Google Scholar
  34. Fricker, Elizabeth. 2006. Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In The epistemology of testimony, ed. Jennifer Lackey and Ernest Sosa, 225–250. Oxford.Google Scholar
  35. Gesang, Bernward. 2010. Are moral philosophers moral experts? Bioethics 24 (4): 153–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Goldman, Alvin I. 2001. Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXIII (1): 85–110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Gordon, John-Stewart. 2014. Moral philosophers are moral experts! A reply to David Archard. Bioethics 28 (4): 203–206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Hartzler, Andrea, and Wanda Pratt. 2011. Managing the personal side of health: How patient expertise differs from the expertise of clinicians. Journal of Medical Internet Research 13 (3).  https://doi.org/10.2196/jmir.1728.
  39. Heldal, Frode, and Aksel Tjora. 2009. Making sense of patient expertise. Social Theory and Health 7: 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Hendel, Charles. 1958. The absurdity of Christianity, and other essays. New York: Liberal Arts Press.Google Scholar
  41. Herrmann, Beate. 2010. What does the ethical expertise of a moral philosopher involve in clinical ethics consultancy. In Clinical ethics consultation: Theories and methods, Implementation, Evaluation, ed. Jan Schildmann, John-Steward Gordon, and Jochen Vollmann, 107–117. Abingdon: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  42. Hester, Micah D., and Toby Shonfeld. 2012. Guidance for healthcare ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Ho, Dien. 2016. Keeping it ethically real. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 41 (4): 369–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Hoffman, Martin. 2012. How to identify moral experts? An application of Goldman’s criteria for expert identification to the domain of morality. Analyse & Kritik 34 (2): 299–313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Hooker, Brad. 1998. Moral expertise. In Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E. Craig, 509–511. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  46. Hopkins, Robert. 2007. What is wrong with moral testimony. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXXIV (3): 611–634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Hulsey, Timothy L., and Peter J. Hamson. 2014. Moral expertise. New Ideas in Psychology. 34 (1): 1–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Iltis, Ana S., and Lisa Rasmussen. 2016. The ‘Ethics’ expertise in clinical ethics consultation. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 41 (4): 363–368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Iltis, Ana S., and Mark Sheehan. 2016. Expertise, ethics expertise, and clinical ethics consultation: Achieving terminological clarity. Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 41 (4): 416–433.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Jones, Karen. 1999. Second-hand moral knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy XCVI (2): 55–78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Jones, Karen, and François Schroeter. 2012. Moral Expertise. Analyse & Kritik 34 (2): 217–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Jonsen, Albert R., Mark Siegler, and William J. Winslade. 2010. Clinical ethics: A practical approach to ethical decisions in clinical medicine. 7th ed. New York: McGraw Hill.Google Scholar
  53. Kahn, Carrie-Ann Biondi. 2005. Aristotle’s moral expert: The Phronimos. In Ethics expertise: History contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa Rasmussen, 39–53. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. LaBarge, Scott. 2005. Socrates and moral expertise. In Ethics expertise: History, Contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa Rasmussen, 15–38. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Lackey, Jennifer. 2018. Experts and peer disagreement. In Knowledge, Belief, and God: New insights in religious epistemology, ed. Mathew Benton, John Hawthorne, and Dani Rabinowitz, 228–245.Google Scholar
  56. Licon, Jimmy Alfonso. 2012. Skeptical thoughts on philosophical expertise. Logos & Episteme III (3): 449–458.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Locke, John. 1979. An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  58. MacIntyre, Alisdair. 1988. Whose justice? Which rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  59. Matheson, Jonathan. 2015. The epistemology of disagreement. New York: Palgrave.Google Scholar
  60. McGrath, Sarah. 2009. The puzzle of pure moral deference. Philosophical Perspectives 23 (1): 321–344.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. ———. 2011. Skepticism about moral expertise as a puzzle for moral realism. Journal of Philosophy 108 (3): 111–137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Meyers, Christopher. 2007. A practical guide to clinical ethics consulting. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  63. Mill, J.S. 2002. On liberty. In The basic writings of John Stuart Mill, ed. J.B. Schneewind, 1–119. New York: The Modern Library.Google Scholar
  64. Miller, Dale. 2005. Moral expertise: A Millian perspective. In Ethics expertise: History, Contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa Rasmussen, 73–87. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Mlodinow, Leonard. 2008. The drunkard’s walk: How randomness rules our lives. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
  66. Noble, Cheryl. 1982. Ethics and experts. Hastings Center Report 12 (3): 7–9.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Plato. 1997a. Meno. In Plato: Complete works (John M. Cooper, ed., Trans. G.M.A. Grube, 870–897). Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  68. ———. 1997b. Protagoras. In Plato: Complete works (John M. Cooper, ed., Trans. Stanley Lombardo and Karen Bell, 746–790) Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  69. Priaulx, Nicky, Martin Weinel, and Anthony Wrigley. 2014. Rethinking moral expertise. Health Care Analysis 22 (3): 1–14.Google Scholar
  70. Puma, La, David Schiedermayer John, and Mark Siegler. 1995. How ethics consultation can help resolve Dilemmas about dying patients. Western Journal of Medicine 163 (03): 263–267.Google Scholar
  71. Quast, Christian. 2018. Expertise: A practical explication. Topoi 37 (1): 11–27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Rasmussen, Lisa, ed. 2005. Ethics expertise: History, Contemporary perspectives, and applications. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  73. ———. 2011. An ethics expertise for clinical ethics consultation. Journal of Law Medicine and Ethics 39 (4): 649–661.Google Scholar
  74. ———. 2016. Clinical ethics eonsultants are not ‘ethics’ experts—But they do have expertise. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy: A Forum for Bioethics and Philosophy of Medicine 41 (4): 384–400.Google Scholar
  75. Raz, Joseph. 1986. The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  76. Ryle, Gilbert. 1958. On forgetting the difference between right and wrong. In Essays in moral philosophy, ed. A.I. Melden. University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
  77. Schmitt, Frederick F. 2006. Testimonial justification and transindividual reasons. In The epistemology of testimony, ed. Jennifer Lackey and Ernest Sosa, 193–224. Oxford: UK.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Scofield, Giles R. 1993. Ethics consultation: The least dangerous profession? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2: 417–448.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. ———. 1994. Is the medical ethicist an ‘Expert’? Bioethics Bulletin 3 (1): 1–2 9–10, 28.Google Scholar
  80. ———. 2008. What is medical ethics consultation? Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 36 (1): 95–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Shuster, Evelyne. 2014. The VA crisis is fundamentally an ethics crisis. Bioethics Forum at The HastingsCenter.org. http://www.thehastingscenter.org/Bioethicsforum/Post.aspx?id=6993&blogid=140. Accessed 02 Aug 2015.
  82. Singer, Peter. 1972. Moral experts. Analysis 32: 115–117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Stolper, Margreet, Sandra van der Dam, Guy Widdershoven, and Bert Molewijk. 2010. Clinical ethics in the Netherlands: Moral case deliberation in health care organizations. In Clinical ethics consultation: Theories and methods, Implementation, Evaluation, ed. Jan Schildmann, John-Steward Gordon, and Jochen Vollmann, 149–160. Abingdon: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  84. The Joint Commission. 1992. Accreditation Guide for Hospitals.Google Scholar
  85. Vogelstein, Eric. 2015. The nature and value of bioethics expertise. Bioethics 29 (5): 324–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Watson, Jamie Carlin. 2018. The shoulders of giants: A case for non-veritism about expert authority. Topoi.  https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-016-9421-0.
  87. Wear, Stephen. 2005. Ethical expertise in the clinical setting. In Ethics expertise: History contemporary perspectives, and applications, ed. Lisa Rasmussen, 243–258. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Weinstein, Bruce. 1994. The possibility of ethical expertise. Theoretical Medicine 15 (1): 61–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Widdershoven, Guy, and Bert Molewijk. 2010. Philosophical foundations of clinical ethics: A hermeneutic perspective. In Clinical ethics consultation: Theories and methods, Implementation, Evaluation, ed. Jan Schildmann, John-Steward Gordon, and Jochen Vollmann, 37–52. Abingdon: Ashgate.Google Scholar
  90. Williams, Bernard. 1993. Who needs ethical knowlede? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 35: 213–222.Google Scholar
  91. ———. 1995. Truth in ethics. Ratio 8 (3): 227–236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. Wolff, Robert Paul. 1970. In Defense of Anarchism. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
  93. Yoder, Scott D. 1998. The Nature of Ethical Expertise. Hastings Center Report 28: 12–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Zagzebski, Linda Trinkaus. 2012. Epistemic Authority: A Theory of Trust, Authority, and Autonomy in Belief. Oxford: New York.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Zaner, Richard M. 1988. Ethics and the Clinical Encounter. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  • Jamie Carlin Watson
    • 1
  • Laura K. Guidry-Grimes
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Medical Humanities and BioethicsUniversity of Arkansas for Medical SciencesLittle RockUSA

Personalised recommendations