Advertisement

A New System of the World

  • Francesco G. Sacco
Chapter
  • 3 Downloads
Part of the International Archives of the History of Ideas Archives internationales d'histoire des idées book series (ARCH, volume 231)

Abstract

In his inaugural speech for the chair of astronomy of Gresham College in 1657, the young Christopher Wren expressed confidence that, thanks to “the industry of some writers of our age,” the foundation of Copernican astronomy, laid by Galileo and Kepler, would soon be completed and perfected. A few years later, in 1670, another Gresham professor delivered a lecture which attempted to provide an unquestionable proof of Copernican astronomy. Although unsuccessful in this respect, Hooke’s Attempt to Prove the Motion of the Earth by Observations, published in 1674, did present three new principles of the Copernican “system of the world.” The first principle introduced the idea “that all celestial bodies whatsoever, have an attraction or gravitating power towards their own centres.” This attraction is not limited to the constituents of each body, rather it extends “to all the other celestial bodies that are within the sphere of their activity.” Terrestrial gravity is part of a wider physical system, since the sun, the moon and all the other planets “have an influence” over the earth, as this latter does on them.

Bibliography

  1. Aiton, Eric. 1972. The vortex theory of planetary motion. London: Mcdonald.Google Scholar
  2. Applebaum, Wilbur. 1996. Keplerian astronomy after Kepler. History of Science 34: 451–504.Google Scholar
  3. Armitage, Angus. 1950. “Borell’s hypothesis” and the rise of celestial mechanics. Annals of Science 6: 268–282.Google Scholar
  4. Auzout, Adrien. 1665. L’éphéméride du comète. Paris.Google Scholar
  5. Bacon, Francis. 1857–74. Works, 7 vols., ed. Robert L. Ellis, James Spedding, Douglas D. Heath. London: Longman.Google Scholar
  6. Bennett, Jim. 1975. Hooke and Wren and the system of the world: Some point toward an historical account. British Journal for the History of Science 8: 32–61.Google Scholar
  7. ———. 1980. Robert Hooke as mechanic and natural philosopher. Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 35: 33–48.Google Scholar
  8. ———. 1981. Cosmology and the magnetical philosophy, 1640–1680. Journal for the History of Astronomy 12: 165–177.Google Scholar
  9. ———. 1982. The mathematical science of Christopher Wren. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. ———. 1989. Magnetical philosophy and astronomy from Wilkins to Hooke. In Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise of astrophysics, Part A: Tycho Brahe to Newton, ed. R. Taton and C. Wilson, 222–230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Bertoloni Meli, Domenico. 2006. Thinking with objects: The transformation of mechanics in the seventeenth century. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Birch, Thomas. 1756–57. The history of the Royal Society of London, 4 vols. London.Google Scholar
  13. Boantza, Victor. 2011. From cohesion to pesanteur: the origins of the 1669 debate on the causes of gravity. In Controversies within the Scientific Revolution, eds. Marcelo Dascal and Victor Boantza, 77–100. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  14. Boantza, Victor D., and Anna Marie Ross. 2015. Mineral Waters across the channel: Matter theory and natural history from Samuel Duclos’ minerallogenesis to Martin Lister’s chymical magnetism, ca. 1666–86. Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London 69: 373–394.Google Scholar
  15. Boner, Patrick. 2006. Kepler on the origin of comets: Applying earthly knowledge to celestial bodies. Nuncius 21: 31–47.Google Scholar
  16. ———. 2013. Kepler’s cosmological synthesis: Astrology, mechanism and the soul. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  17. Borelli, Giovanni Alfonso. 1666. Theoricae mediceorum planetarum. Florence.Google Scholar
  18. Boyle, Robert. 1999. The works of Robert Boyle, 14 vols., ed. Michael Hunter and Edward Davies. London: Pickering and Chatto.Google Scholar
  19. ———. 2001. The correspondence of Robert Boyle, 6 vols., ed. Michael Hunter, Antonio Clericuzio and Laurence Principe. London: Pickering and Chatto.Google Scholar
  20. Bucciantini, Massimo. 2003. Galileo e Keplero: filosofia, cosmologia e teologia nell’eta’ della controriforma. Turin: Einaudi.Google Scholar
  21. Charleton, Walter. 1654. Physiologia epicuro-gassendo-charletoniana. London.Google Scholar
  22. Descartes, René. 1964–74. Oeuvres, 12 vols., ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  23. ———. 1983. Principles of philosophy. Trans. Valentine Rodger Miller and Rees P. Miller. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  24. ———. 1984–91. The philosophical writings, 3 vols., Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Douglas Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Ducheyne, Steffen. 2012. The main business of natural philosophy: Isaac Newton’s natural philosophical methodology. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  26. Freudenthal, Gideon. 1993. Clandestine Stoic concepts in mechanical philosophy: The problem of electrical attraction. In Renaissance and revolution: Humanists, scholars, craftsmen and natural philosophers in early modern Europe, ed. J.V. Field and Frank A. James, 161–172. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Gal, Ofer. 2002. Meanest foundations and nobler superstructures: Hooke, Newton and the “Compounding of the Celestial Motions of the Planetts”. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  28. Gal, Ofer, and Raz Chen-Morris. 2005. The archaeology of the inverse square law: (1) Metaphysical images and mathematical practices. History of Science 43: 391–414.Google Scholar
  29. Galilei, Galileo. 1890–1909. Opere, 20 vols, ed. Antonio Favaro. Florence: Barbera.Google Scholar
  30. ———. 1974. Two new sciences, including Centres of gravity and Force of percussion. Trans. Stillman Drake. Madison/London: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  31. Gassendi, Pierre. 1658. Opera omnia, 6 vols. Leiden.Google Scholar
  32. Gaukroger, Stephen. 2002. Descartes’ system of natural philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Giglioni, Guido. 2013. How Bacon Became Baconian. In The mechanization of natural philosophy, ed. Daniel Garber and Sophie Roux, 27–54. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  34. Gilbert, William. 1600. De magnete. London.Google Scholar
  35. ———. 1900. On the magnet. Trans. Sylvanus Thompson. London: Chiswick Press.Google Scholar
  36. Gouk, Penelope. 1980. The role of acoustic and music theory in the scientific work of Robert Hooke. Annals of Science 37: 573–605.Google Scholar
  37. Granada, Miguel Angel. 2010. A quo movetur planetae? Kepler et la question de l’agent du mouvement planétaire après la disparition des orbes solides. Galilaeana 7: 111–141.Google Scholar
  38. Guicciardini, Niccolò. 1998. Newton: un filosofo della natura e il sistema del mondo. Milan: Le Scienze.Google Scholar
  39. Guicciardini, Niccoló. 2011. Newton. Rome: Carocci.Google Scholar
  40. Heilbron, John. 1979. Electricity in the 17th and 18th centuries. Berkeley/Los Angeles/London: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  41. Henry, John. 2011. Gravity and De gravitatione: The development of Newton’s ideas on action at a distance. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 42: 11–27.Google Scholar
  42. Hooke, Robert. 1661. An attempt for the explication of the phaenomena. London.Google Scholar
  43. ———. 1665. Micrographia. London.Google Scholar
  44. ———. 1674a. An attempt to prove the motion of the Earth by observations. London.Google Scholar
  45. ———. 1674b. Animadversions on the first part of the Machina coelestis. London.Google Scholar
  46. ———. 1677. Lampas. London.Google Scholar
  47. ———. 1678. Lectures and collections. London.Google Scholar
  48. ———. 1705. Posthumous works, ed. Richard Waller. London.Google Scholar
  49. ———. 1726. Philosophical experiments and observations, ed. William Derham. London.Google Scholar
  50. Horrocks, Jeremiah. 1673. Opera posthuma, ed. John Wallis. London.Google Scholar
  51. Huygens, Christiaan. 1888–1950. Oeuvres completes, 22 vols., ed. Société hollandaise des sciences. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.Google Scholar
  52. Johnston, Stephen. 2010. Wren, Hooke, and graphical practice. Journal for the History of Astronomy 41: 381–392.Google Scholar
  53. Jullien, Vincent. 2006. Philosophie naturelle et géométrie au XVIIe siècle. Paris: Honoré Champion.Google Scholar
  54. Kepler, Johannes. 1937–98. Gesammelte Werke, 20 vols., ed. Kepler-Kommission der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Munich: Beck.Google Scholar
  55. ———. 1992. New astronomy. Trans. William Donahue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  56. ———. 1995. Epitome of Copernican astronomy and harmonies of the world. Amherst: Prometheus Books.Google Scholar
  57. Koyré, Alexandre. 1968. Newtonian studies. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  58. ———. 1973. The astronomical revolution: Copernicus, Kepler, Borelli. Trans. R. E. W. Maddison. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
  59. Kuhn, Thomas. 1957. The Copernican revolution: Planetary astronomy in the development of Western thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Lombardi, Anna Maria. 2008. Keplero: una biografia scientifica. Turin: Codice.Google Scholar
  61. Mach, Ernst. 1919. The science of mechanics: a critical and historical account of its development. Trans. Thomas J. McCormack. Chicago/London: Open Court Publishing.Google Scholar
  62. Manzo, Silvia. 2006. Entre el atomismo y la alquimia: la teoria de la materia de Francis Bacon. Buenos Aires: Editorial Biblos.Google Scholar
  63. Milani, Nausicaa Elena. 2013. The Prodromus cometicum in the Académie des sciences and the Royal Society: The Hevelius-Azout controversy. In Johannes Hevelius and his Gdańsk, ed. Marian Turek, 195–208. Gdańsk: Societas Scientiarum Gedanensis.Google Scholar
  64. Mormino, Gianfranco. 1993. Penetralia motus: la fondazione relativistica della meccanica in Christiaan Huygens. Florence: La Nuova Italia.Google Scholar
  65. Nauenberg, Michael. 1994. Hooke, orbital motion and Newton’s Principia. American Journal of Physics 62: 331–350.Google Scholar
  66. Oldenburg, Henry. 1965–86. The correspondence of Henry Oldenburg, 13 vols., ed. Alfred Rupert Hall and Marie Boas Hall. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  67. Palmerino, Carla Rita. 2007. Bodies in water like planets in the skies: Uses and abuses of analogical reasoning in the study of planetary motion. In Mechanic and cosmology in the medieval and early modern period, ed. Massimo Bucciantini, Michele Camerota, and Sophie Roux, 145–168. Florence: Olschki.Google Scholar
  68. ———. 2008. Une force invisible à l’œuvre: le rôle de la vis attrahens dans la physique de Gassendi. In Gassendi et la modernité, ed. Sylvie Taussig, 141–176. Turnhout: Brepols.Google Scholar
  69. Patterson, Louise Diehl. 1949. Hooke’s gravitation theory and its influence on Newton I: Hooke’s gravitation theory. Isis 40: 327–341.Google Scholar
  70. ———. 1952. Pendulums of Hooke and Wren. Osiris 10: 277–321.Google Scholar
  71. Pepys, Samuel. 1995. The diary of Samuel Pepys, 11 vols., ed. Robert Latham and William Matthwes. London: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
  72. Pugliese, Patri. 2004. Robert Hooke. In Oxford dictionary of national biography, ed. H.C.G. Matthew and Brian Harrison, vol. 27, 951–958. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  73. Pumfrey, Stephen. 1987. Mechanizing magnetism in restoration England: The decline of magnetic philosophy. Annals of Science 44: 1–22.Google Scholar
  74. ———. 1989. Magnetical philosophy and astronomy 1600–1650. In Planetary astronomy from the Renaissance to the rise of astrophysics, Part A: Tycho Brahe to Newton, ed. R. Taton and C. Wilson, 222–230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  75. ———. 1994. ‘These 2 hundred years not the like published as Gellibrand has done de Magnete’: The Hartlib circle and magnetic philosophy. In Samuel Hartlib and universal reformation: Studies in intellectual communication, ed. Mark Greengrass, Michael Leslie, and Timothy Raylor, 247–267. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  76. Purrington, Robert. 2009. The first professional scientist: Robert Hooke and the Royal Society of London. Berlin/Basel: Birkhäuser.Google Scholar
  77. Rees, Graham. 1975. Francis Bacon’s semi-paracelsian cosmology. Ambix 22: 81–101.Google Scholar
  78. ———. 1977. The fate of Bacon’s cosmology in the seventeenth century. Ambix 24: 27–38.Google Scholar
  79. Roberval, Gilles. 1644. Aristarchi Samii de mundi systemate. Paris.Google Scholar
  80. Roux, Sophie. 2004. Cartesian mechanics. In The reception of the Galileian science of motion in seventeenth-century Europe, ed. Carla Rita Palmerino and J. M. M. H Thijssen, 25–66. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  81. Ruffner, James. 1971. The curved and the straight: Cometary theory from Kepler to Hevelius. Journal for the History of Astronomy 2: 178–194.Google Scholar
  82. Shapin, Steven. 1994. A social history of truth: Civility and science in seventeenth-century England. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  83. Sprat, Thomas. 1667. History of the Royal Society. London.Google Scholar
  84. Vickers, Brian. 2007. Francis Bacon mirror of each age. In Advancement of learning: Essays in honour of Paolo Rossi, ed. John Heilbron, 15–57. Florence: Olschki.Google Scholar
  85. Wallis, John. 1666. An essay of Dr. John Wallis exhibiting his hypothesis about the flux and reflux of the sea. Philosophical Transactions 263–289.Google Scholar
  86. Wang, Xiaona. 2016. Francis Bacon and magnetical cosmology. Isis 107: 707–721.Google Scholar
  87. Ward, Seth. 1653. De cometis. Oxford.Google Scholar
  88. Ward, John. 1740. The lives of the professors of Gresham College. London.Google Scholar
  89. Westfall, Richard. 1971. Force in Newton’s physics: The science of dynamics in the seventeenth century. New York: American Elsevier.Google Scholar
  90. ———. 1972. Robert Hooke (1635–1703). In Dictionary of scientific biography, ed. Charles Gillispie, vol. VI, 481–488. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
  91. Wilkins, John. 1802. The mathematical and philosophical works , 2 vols. London.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Francesco G. Sacco
    • 1
  1. 1.Humanities DepartmentCATS CollegeCanterburyUK

Personalised recommendations