Advertisement

Objectivity

  • Paul Needham
Chapter
  • 18 Downloads
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 423)

Abstract

Objective justification requires the recognition and accommodation of sources of experimental error. Examples illustrating perceptual error, the import of appropriate and inappropriate expectations, taking systematic error into account and the articulation of random error are discussed. The notions of experimental precision and accuracy are distinguished, and the approximation associated with the articulation of degree of precision is contrasted with vagueness. The interpretation of experiment is compared with the interpretation of human action and its cultural products. The need for precautions when relying on epistemic authority is discussed in the light of the need to rely on the judgements of others. Acquiring confidence in arriving at inductive conclusions cautiously emphasises their fallibility. Finally, the interplay of epistemic and ethical value judgements is illustrated and discussed in the assessment of inductive risk.

References

  1. Boring, E. G. (1957). A history of experimental psychology (2nd ed.). New York: Appleton-Century Crofts.Google Scholar
  2. Chang, H. (2012b). Joseph Priestley (1722–1804). In R. F. Hendry, P. Needham, & A. J. Woody (Eds.), Handbook of the philosophy of science (Vol. 6, Philosophy of chemistry, pp. 55–62). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  3. Chomsky, N. (1959), Review of B. F. Skinner. Verbal Behavior, Language, 35, 26–58.Google Scholar
  4. Cranor, C. F. (1993). Regulating toxic substances: A philosophy of science and the law. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 559–579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Douglas, H. (2004). Prediction, explanation, and dioxin biochemistry: Science in public policy. Foundations of Chemistry, 6, 49–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Drake, S. (1978). Galileo at work: His scientific biography. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  8. Drake, S., & Kowal, C. T. (1980). Galileo’s sighting of Neptune. Scientific American, 243, 52–59.Google Scholar
  9. Duhem, P. (1906b). La théorie physique: Son objet – sa structure. Paris: Chevalier et Rivière; 2nd ed. (text unchanged, two appendices added) 1914; Reprinted Vrin, Paris, 1981. Translated in Duhem (1954).Google Scholar
  10. Frank, S. T. (1973). Aural sign of coronary-artery disease. New England Journal of Medicine, 289, 327–328.Google Scholar
  11. Franklin. A. (1986). The neglect of experiment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Galileo, G. (1613 [1957]). Letters on sunspots, trans.: Drake, S., and C. D. O’Malley, Ed., The Controversy on the Comets of 1618. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1960. Extracts in Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo, Ed. and trans. S. Drake. New York: Doubleday Anchor Books.Google Scholar
  13. Hempel, C. G. (1965). Science and human values. In Aspects of scientific explanation (pp. 81–96). Toronto: Free Press, Collier-Macmillan.Google Scholar
  14. Hughes, I., & Hase, T. (2010). Measurements and their uncertainties: A practical guide to modern error analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Kant, I. (1783 [1966]). Prolegomena. Riga: Hartknoch; Eng. trans. by Peter G. Lucas, Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Klotz, I. M. (1980). The N-ray affair. Scientific American, 242, 122–131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Kociba, R., Keyes, D. G., Beyer, J. E., Carreon, R. M., Wade, C. E., Dittenber, D. A., Kalnins, R. P., Frauson, L. E., Park, C. N., Barnard, S. D., Hummel, R. A., & Humiston, C. G. (1978). Results of a two-year chronic toxicity and oncogenicity study of 2,3,7,8-tetracholorodibenzo-p-dioxin in rats. Toxicology and Applied Pharmacology, 46, 279–303.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. McMullin, E. (1983). Values in science. In P. D. Asquith & T. Nickles (Eds.), Proceedings of the 1982 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 2, pp. 3–28). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  19. Naylor, R. (1974). Galileo’s simple pendulum. Physis, 16(1974), 32–46.Google Scholar
  20. Quine, W. V. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.Google Scholar
  21. Quine, W. V., & Ullian, J. S. (1978). The web of belief (2nd ed.). New York: Random House.Google Scholar
  22. Sobel, D. (1995). Longitude: The true story of a lone genius who solved the greatest scientific problem of his time. New York: Walker & Company.Google Scholar
  23. Wood, R. W. (1904). The n-rays. Nature, 70, 530–531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Paul Needham
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of StockholmStockholmSweden

Personalised recommendations