Advertisement

Objections to the Benefits to Inquiry Argument

  • Kirk LougheedEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics book series (SAPERE, volume 51)

Abstract

In this chapter I outline and respond to a number of objections to the Benefits to Inquiry Argument. I begin with what I take to be the weakest objections and conclude with the strongest objections. The most promising objection to the Benefits to Inquiry Argument is that it conflates practical reasons with epistemic reasons. I respond to this by arguing that future epistemic benefits should indeed be considered benefits of epistemic reasoning. But the objection succeeds only if synchronic epistemic reasons are the only type of epistemic reasons included in one’s account of epistemic rationality. But an all-things-considered epistemic rationality will include both synchronic and diachronic epistemic reasons.

Bibliography

  1. Barnett, Zach. 2019. Philosophy Without Belief. Mind 128 (509): 109–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Berker, Selim. 2013. Epistemic Teleology and Separateness of Propositions. Philosophical Review 122 (3): 337–393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Chalmers, David J. 2015. Why Isn’t There More Progress in Philosophy? Philosophy 90 (1): 3–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Christensen, David. 2007. Epistemology of Disagreement: The Good News. Philosophical Review 116 (2): 187–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cohen, L.Jonathan. 1992. An Essay on Belief and Acceptance. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. David, Marian. 2001. Truth as the Epistemic Goal. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, ed. M. Steup, 151–169. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Elgin, Catherine. 2010. Persistent Disagreement. In Disagreement, ed. Richard Feldman Disagreement, and Ted A. Warfield, 53–68. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Engel, 2000. Believing and Accepting. USA: Kluwer Academic.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Feldman, Richard. 2011. Reasonable Religious Disagreements. In Social Epistemology: Essential Readings, ed. Alvin Goldman and Dennis Whitcomb, 137–157. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Feyerabend, Paul. 1988. Against Method. New York: Verso Publishing.Google Scholar
  11. Firth, Roderick. 1998a [1978]. The Schneck Lectures, Lecture 1: Epistemic Utility. First delivered as a lecture at the University of Arizona, 1978.Google Scholar
  12. Firth, Roderick. 1998b [1981]. Epistemic Merit, Intrinsic and Instrumental. In Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 55, 5–23. Reprinted in Firth 1998, 259–271.Google Scholar
  13. Frances, Bryan. 2001. Epistemic Justification and Normativity. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, ed. M. Steup, 49–60. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Fumerton, Richard. 2001. Epistemic Justification and Normativity. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty, ed. M. Steup, 49–60. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Holley, David M. 2013. Religious Disagreements and Epistemic Rationality. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 (1): 33–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hughes, Nick. (forthcoming). Dilemmic Epistemology. Synthese.Google Scholar
  17. Kelly, Thomas. 2003. Epistemic Rational as Instrumental Rationality: A Critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research LXVI (3): 612–640.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. King-Fai, L., K. Pahlevan, J. Kirschvink, and Y. Yung. 2009. Atmospheric Pressure as a Natural Climate Regulator for a Terrestrial Planet with a Biosphere. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 24: 9576–9579.Google Scholar
  19. Lougheed, Kirk. (forthcoming). Catherine Elgin on Peerhood and the Epistemic Benefits of Disagreement. Synthese.Google Scholar
  20. Lougheed, Kirk, and Robert Mark Simpson. 2017. Indirect Epistemic Reasons and Religious Belief. Religious Studies 53 (2): 151–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Matheson, Jonathan. 2015a. The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Matheson, Jonathan. 2015b. Disagreement and the Ethics of Belief. In The Future of Social Epistemology: A Collective Vision, ed. James H. Collier, 139–148. USA: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  23. McGinn, Colin. (1993). Problems in Philosophy: The Limits of Inquiry. Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  24. Pettit, Philip. 2006. No Testimonial Route to Consensus. Episteme 3 (3): 156–165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Schellenberg, John L. (2013). Evolutionary Religion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Schroeder, K.P., and R.C. Smith. 2008. Distance Future of the Sun and Earth Revisited. Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 1: 155–163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Talbot, Brian. 2014. Truth Promoting Non-Evidential Reasons for Belief. Philosophical Studies 168 (3): 599–618.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. van Inwagen, Peter. 1996. It Is Wrong, Everywhere, Always, and for Anyone, to Believe Anything Upon Insufficient Evidence. In Faith, Freedom, and Rationality: Philosophy of Religion Today, ed. J. Jordan and D. Howard-Snyder. London: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  29. Wolterstorf, Nicholas. 2014. The Significance of Inexplicable Disagreement. In Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue, ed. L.F. Callahan and T. O’Connor, 317–330. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Wright, Crispin. (2014). Welfare State Epistemology (Entitlement II). In Contemporary Perspectives on Scepticism and Perceptual Justification, ed. Dylan Dodd and Elia Zardini, 213–247. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Concordia University of EdmontonEdmontonCanada

Personalised recommendations