Advertisement

Joint Action: Why So Minimal?

  • Cédric Paternotte
Chapter
  • 6 Downloads
Part of the Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality book series (SIPS, volume 11)

Abstract

The repeated attempts to characterise joint action have displayed a common trend towards minimalism – whether they focus on minimal situations, minimal characterisations, cognitively minimal agents or minimal cognitive mechanisms. This trend also appears to lead to pluralism: the idea that joint action may receive multiple, equally valid characterisations. In this paper, I argue for a pluralist stance regarding joint action, although one stemming from maximalism. After describing three cases of “maximal” joint action – demonstrations, deliberations and free collective improvisation – that stretch our conceptual characterisations of joint action, I introduce and defend contextual minimalism, which focuses on joint actions occurring in contexts from which the factors that typically favour successful cooperation are absent. Although maximalist as compared to the other forms of minimalism, contextual minimalism does fit the minimalist trend and its recent emphasis on specific cognitive cooperative mechanisms.

Keywords

Joint action Minimalism Pluralism Contextualism Mass action Improvisation 

References

  1. Bacharach, M. (1999). Interactive team reasoning: A contribution to the theory of cooperation. Research in Economics, 53(2), 117–147.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bacharach, M. (2006). Beyond individual choice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bailey, D. (1993). Improvisation: Its nature and practice in music. New York: Da Capo Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bratman, M. (1992). Shared cooperate activity. The Philosophical Review, 101(2), 327–341.Google Scholar
  5. Bratman, M. (1993). Shared intention. Ethics, 104(1), 97–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bratman, M. (2009). Modest sociality and the distinctiveness of intention. Philosophical Studies, 144(1), 149–165.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Butterfill, S. (2012). Joint action and development. The Philosophical Quarterly, 62(246), 23–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Butterfill, S. (forthcoming). Joint Action: A minimalist approach. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), Routledge handbook on the social mind. Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Butterfill, S., & Sebanz, N. (2011). Joint action: What is shared? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(2), 137–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Canonne, C. (2013). Focal points in collective free improvisation. Perspectives of New Music, 51(1), 40–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Canonne, C., & Aucouturier, J.-J. (2016). Play together, think alike: Shared mental models in expert music improvisers. Psychology of Music, 44(3), 544–558.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Gilbert, M. (1990). Walking together: A paradigmatic social phenomenon. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 15, 1–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Gilbert, M. (2009). Shared intention and personal intentions. Philosophical Studies, 144, 167–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Hakli, R., Miller, K., & Tuomela, R. (2010). Two kinds of we-reasoning. Economics and Philosophy, 26(3), 291–320.Google Scholar
  16. Heinonen, M. (2016). Minimalism and maximalism in the study of shared intentional action. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 46(2), 168–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Keller, P. E. (2008). Joint action in music performance. In F. Morganti, A. Carassa, & G. Riva (Eds.), Enacting intersubjectivity: A cognitive and social perspective to the study of interactions (pp. 205–221). Amsterdam: IOS Press.Google Scholar
  18. Knoblich, G., Butterfill, S., & Sebanz, N. (2010). Psychological research on joint action: Theory and data. In B. Ross (Ed.), Psychology of learning and motivation (Vol. 51, pp. 121–154). Burlington: Academic.Google Scholar
  19. Kutz, C. (2000). Acting together. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 61(1), 1–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Loehr, J. D., Kourtis, D., Vesper, C., Sebanz, N., & Knoblich, G. (2013). Monitoring individual and joint action outcomes in duet music performance. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 25(7), 1049–1061.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Michael, J. (2017). Music performance as joint action. In M. Lesaffre, P.-J. Maes, & M. Leman (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of embodied music interaction (pp. 160–166). Routledge.Google Scholar
  22. Miller, S. (2001). Social action – a teleological account. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Pacherie, E. (2013). Intentional joint agency: Shared intention lite. Synthese, 190(10), 1817–1839.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Paternotte, C. (2014a). Minimal Cooperation. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44(1), 45–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Paternotte, C. (2014b). Constraints on joint action. In M. Gallotti & J. Michael (Eds.), Perspectives on social ontology and social cognition (pp. 103–123). New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  26. Paternotte, C. (2015). The epistemic core of weak joint action. Philosophical Psychology, 28(1), 70–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Peacocke, C. (2005). Joint Attention: its nature, reflexivity and relation to common knowledge. In N. M. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack & J. Roessler (Eds.), Joint attention: Communication and other minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Schweikard, D. & Schmid, H.B. (2013). Collective intentionality. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/collective-intentionality
  29. Searle, J. (1990). Collective intentions and actions. In P. R. Cohen, J. Morgan, & M. Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication (pp. 401–415). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  30. Solomon, M. (2006). Groupthink versus The Wisdom of Crowds: The social epistemology of deliberation and dissent. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 44, 28–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Sunstein, C. R. (2006). Deliberating groups versus prediction markets (or Hayek’s challenge to Habermas). Episteme, 3, 192–213.Google Scholar
  32. Tollefsen, D. (2005). Let’s pretend! Children and joint action. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 35(1), 75–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Tuomela, R. (2000). Cooperation: A philosophical study. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Tuomela, R. (2007). The philosophy of sociality-the shared point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  35. Tuomela, R. (2013). Social ontology: Collective intentionality and group agents. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Tuomela, R., & Miller, K. (1988). We-intentions. Philosophical Studies, 53, 367–389.Google Scholar
  37. Vesper, C., Butterfill, S., Knoblich, G., & Sebanz, N. (2010). A minimal architecture for joint action. Neural Networks, 23(8–9), 998–1003.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Warneken, F., Chen, F., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Cooperative activities in young children and chimpanzees. Child Development, 77, 640–663.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Cédric Paternotte
    • 1
  1. 1.SND Research Team, Department of PhilosophySorbonne UniversitéParisFrance

Personalised recommendations