Advertisement

Paradigms and Self-reference: What Is the Point of Asserting Paradoxical Sentences?

  • Jakub MáchaEmail author
Chapter
Part of the The Frontiers Collection book series (FRONTCOLL)

Abstract

A paradox, according to Wittgenstein, is something surprising that is taken out of its context. Thus, one way of dealing with paradoxical sentences is to imagine the missing context of use. Wittgenstein formulates what I call the paradigm paradox: ‘one sentence can never describe the paradigm in another, unless it ceases to be a paradigm.’ (PG, p. 346) There are several instances of this paradox scattered throughout Wittgenstein’s writings. I argue that this paradox is structurally equivalent to Russell’s paradox. The above quotation is Wittgenstein’s version of the vicious circle principle which counteracts the paradox. The prohibition Wittgenstein describes is, however, limited to a certain language-game. Finally, I argue that there is a structural analogy between a noun being employed as a self-membered set and a paradigmatic sample being included in or excluded from the set it generates. Paradoxical sentences are not prohibited forever; they can indicate a change in our praxis with a given paradigm.

Keywords

Paradox Self-reference Paradigm Yardstick Rule Ludwig Wittgenstein Gottlob Frege 

References

  1. Agamben, G. (1993) The Coming Community: Theory of Bounds, University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  2. Ahmed, A. (2017) ‘Triangulation and the Private Language Argument', Belgrade Philosophical Annual 30, 35–52.Google Scholar
  3. Diamond, C. (1995) The Realistic Spirit, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Diamond, C. (2001) ‘How Long Is the Standard Meter in Paris?’, in: T. McCarthy and S. C. Stidd (eds) Wittgenstein in America, Oxford University Press, 104–139.Google Scholar
  5. Frege, G. (1892) ‘Über Begriff und Gegenstand’, Vierteljahresschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie 16, 192–205.Google Scholar
  6. Gramsci, A. (1971) ‘Wave of Materialism’ and ‘Crisis of Authority’, in: Q. Hoare and G. Nowell-Smith (eds) Selections from the Prison Notebooks, International Publishers.Google Scholar
  7. Irvine, A. D., and Deutsch, H. (2016) ‘Russell’s Paradox’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/russell-paradox/>.
  8. Keel, O. (1994) The Song of Songs: A Continental Commentary, Fortress Press.Google Scholar
  9. Kutschera, F. von (1989) ‘Paradox’, in: K. Gründer (ed.) Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, vol. 7, Schwabe Verlag, 81–97.Google Scholar
  10. Kuusela, O. (2019) Wittgenstein on Logic as the Method of Philosophy, Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Lessing, E. G. (1759/1825) Fables and Epigrams; with Essays on Fable and Epigram, John and H. L. Hunt.Google Scholar
  12. McGinn, M. (1997) Wittgenstein and the Philosophical Investigations, Routledge.Google Scholar
  13. Stroud, B. (2001) ‘Private objects, physical objects and ostension’, in: D. Charles and W. Child (eds) Wittgensteinian Themes: Essays in Honour of David Pears, Oxford University Press, 143–162.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Masaryk UniversityBrnoCzech Republic

Personalised recommendations