Advertisement

The Temporality of Violence: Destruction, Dissolution and the Construction of Sense

  • Felix Ó MurchadhaEmail author
Chapter

Abstract

Violence tends to the destruction of meaningful entities and of that through which such entities are meaningful. Not all violence is annihilating in its effects, but violence aims towards a nothingness which discloses a certain fragility of meaning. The obliteration of the singular, the reduction of organic and structural unity to charred flesh and rubble, is not simply an event within a world, but an event that threatens worldly sense. The constitution of such worldly sense is dependent on time, on the interweaving of temporal tendencies, or orientations, in Husserlian terms: retention and protention. But this interweaving of temporal orientations requires a minimal order of continuity whereby retention, both near and far, and near and far protention allow for a sense of temporal stretch which has a unity and a sense. This is true even though every now may be new, temporal relations being of self-differentiation. Annihilating violence—whether of the individual raped and tortured or the community left bereft through war, colonization or natural disaster—has a traumatizing effect which results in a disconnection from the past and derealization of that which profoundly modifies the retentional and protentional orientations. The vulnerability of temporal constitution, which violence discloses, reveals a fundamental absence at the core of time itself and a nothingness threatening the stability of normalized meaningful entities and spaces while revealing a groundless space of the emergence of meaning.

Bibliography

  1. Amery, J. (2009). At the Mind’s Limits: Contemplations by a Survivor on Auschwitz and Its Realities. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Arendt, H. (1970). On Violence. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
  3. Aristotle. (1984). The Physics. In J. Barnes (Ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Barthes, R. (2002). A Lover’s Discourse: Fragments. London: Vintage Classics.Google Scholar
  5. Benjamin, W. (1968). Theses on the Philosophy of History. In H. Arendt (Ed.), Illuminations (pp. 253–265). New York: Schocken Books.Google Scholar
  6. Benjamin, W. (1986). The Critique of Violence. In Reflections: Essays, Aphorisms, Autobiographical Writings (E. Jephcott, Trans.) (pp. 277–300). New York: Schocken Books.Google Scholar
  7. Bergson, H. (1991). Matter and Memory (N. M. Paul & W. S. Palmer, Trans.). New York: Zone Books.Google Scholar
  8. Blanchot, M. (2015). The Writing the Disaster (A. Smock, Trans.). London: University of Nebraska Press.Google Scholar
  9. Brison, S. (2011). Aftermath: Violence and the Remaking of the Self. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Caruth, C. (1996). Unclaimed Experience: Trauma, Narrative, and History. Baltimore: John Hopkins Press.Google Scholar
  11. Cavarero, A. (2009). Horrorism: Naming Contemporary Violence (W. McCuaig, Trans.) New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Dastur, F. (2000). Phenomenology of the Event: Waiting and Surprise. Hypatia, 15(4), 178–189.Google Scholar
  13. Derrida, J. (1992). The Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundations of Authority”. In D. Connell, M. Rosenfeld, & D. Carlson (Eds.), Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice (pp. 3–67). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  14. Husserl, E. (2001). In R. Bernet & D. Lohmar (Eds.), Die Bernauer Manuskripte über das Zeitbewusstsein (1917/18). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  15. Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority (A. Lingis, Trans.). Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1965). The Structure of Behavior. London: Metheun.Google Scholar
  17. Merleau-Ponty, M. (1968). The Visible and the invisible (A. Lingis, Trans.). Pittsburg: Duquesne University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Merleau-Ponty, M. (2013). The Phenomenology of Perception (D. Landes, Trans.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  19. Ó Murchadha, F. (2002). Being and Ruination. Simmel and Heidegger on the Phenomenology of Ruins. Philosophy Today, 46(SPEP Supplement), 10–18.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Ó Murchadha, F. (2017). Speaking After the Phenomenon: The Promise of Things and the Future of Phenomenology. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology, 48(1), 99–115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Plato. (1961a). Parmenides. In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), The Complete Dialogues of Plato. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Plato. (1961b). Timaeus. In E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (Eds.), The Complete Dialogues of Plato. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Ratcliffe, M. (2017). Grief and the Unity of Emotions. Mid-West Studies in Philosophy, XLI, 154–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Ravaisson, F. (2009) Of Habit (C. Carlisle & M. Sinclaire, Trans.). London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  25. Ricoeur, P. (1994). Time and Narrative vol. 1 (K. McLaughlin, Trans.) Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Simmel, G. (1996). “Die Ruine” in Philosophische Kultur. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  27. Staudigl, M. (2015). Phänomenologie der Gewalt. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Tengelyi, L. (2004). The Wild Region in Life-History. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.NUI GalwayGalwayIreland

Personalised recommendations