Advertisement

Dimensions of the Bodily Creativity. For an Extended Theory of Performativity

  • Antonino Pennisi
Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 23)

Abstract

In our project the performance is a product of performativity. Performativity is the cognitive ability to produce physical or mental actions. Studying performance and studying performativity sets different scientific activities. Studying how to enhance the perfòrmances belongs to the behavioral science. On the contrary, studying performativity belongs to a general cognitive procedure that must not be confused with the description of behaviors, requiring a specific theorization in the cognitive sciences instead. The aim of this research project is to focus on the hypothesis that performativity is not a property confined to certain specific human skills, or to certain specific acts of language. Instead, the executive and motor component of cognitive behavior should be considered an intrinsic part of the physiological functioning of the mind and as endowed with self-generative power.

Performativity as a physiological tool of cognitive creativity has precise neural correlates and procedural properties. The firsts are summarized briefly in the central part of the essay. The latter are more widely discussed in the following chapters. From the point of view of procedures, instead, it is argued that performativity is a cognitive property that arises from the absence of an algorithm designed to carry out a given performance. Acting in a non-planned way, learning by trial and error, applying familiar behavioral patterns to new situations: these are just a few examples of what is performativity and of how it works. Thus, performativity is intrinsically creative because its nature is to face situations that cannot be solved by the application of already known algorithms. In a nutshell, performative creativity is a procedural system that is somewhere between what Chomsky called “rule governed creativity” and “rule-changing creativity”. Performativity however bears a peculiar kind of creativity, which is different from the one generated by the competence but still shares some features with the latter: in fact, it is a fully embodied and free-from-rules process that is carried out through trial and error, that is to say it depends on the bodily practice (locomotion, language, perception, etc.) made in everyday experience.

It is for this reason that Embodied Cognition (EC) should be the theoretical framework to explain the functioning of the performativity. EC indeed is the answer to all those cerebrocentric theories that consider only the computational function of the brain and ignore the role of the body as the main responsible for all the abilities of humans, animals and machines, describing performance just as an executive function. The EC however addresses the issue of performativity from the point of view of the individual rather than from that of the species. From this perspective it makes difficult to incorporate performativity into a general theory of cognition. Its phenomenological instances come into conflict with the naturalism of cognitive sciences. On the contrary, an extended theory of performativity cannot do without ethological and evolutionist perspectives. These perspectives are addressed in the second part of the essay, both from the point of view of the historical reconstruction and from that of the current debate.

In the light of the considerations made in the last part, the final hypothesis that we support is that performativity is not an attribute belonging to some human abilities only, nor to the faculty of language, nor to uniquely creative intelligence of homo sapiens. On the contrary, it can be defined as a fundamental element for any species’ cognitive process. From an evolutionary point of view, performativity probably developed in parallel with the structural and functional transformations occurred in homo sapiens that led to the species-specificity of language and let embodied simulation be our model of perception. For what concerns other species, performativity had a different development for any of them and led to other kinds of cognitive abilities.

References

  1. Abutalebi, J., Brambati, S.M., Annoni, J.M., Moro, A., Cappa, S.F., & Perani, D. (2007). The neural cost of the auditory perception of language switches: An event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging study in bilinguals. The Journal of Neuroscience, 27(50), 13762–13769.Google Scholar
  2. Aizawa, K. (2010). The coupling-constitution fallacy revisited. Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 332–342.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Aizawa, K. (2014). The enactivist revolution. Avant, 5(2), 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Anderson, M. (2015). The renaissance extended mind. London: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
  5. Aristotle. (PH) Physica. In P. H. Wicksteed & F. M. Cornford (Eds.), The physics: II vol. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (1957)Google Scholar
  6. Austin, J.A. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bergson, H. (1896). Matter and memory (1896) (Trans.: N.M. Paul & W. Scott Palmer). London: George Allen and Unwin (1911).Google Scholar
  8. Bergson, H. (1908). Memory of the present and false recognition. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 134–185). Westport: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  9. Bergson, H. (1911). Life and consciousness. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 3–36). Westport: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  10. Bergson, H. (1912). The soul and the body. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 37–74). Westport: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  11. Bergson, H. (1913). Phantasms of the living” and psychical research. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 75–103). Westport: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  12. Bergson, H. (1919). Mind-energy: Lectures and essays. Westport: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
  13. Berwick, R.C., & Chomsky, N. (2016). Why only us. Language and evolution. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  14. Bolhuis, J., Tattersall, I., Chomsky, N., & Berwick, R. (2014). How could language have evolved? PLoS Biology, 12(8), 1–6.Google Scholar
  15. Brooks, R.A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1), 139–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Brooks, R. (2002). Flesh and machine: How robots will change us. New York: Pantheon.Google Scholar
  17. Calvo, P., & Keijzer, F. (2009). Cognition in plants. In F. Baluska (Ed.), Plant-environment interactions: From sensory plant biology to active plant behavior (pp. 247–266). Berlin: Springer.Google Scholar
  18. Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Chomsky, N. (1959). A review of B.F. Skinner’s verbal behavior. In L.A. Jakobovits, & M.S. Miron (Eds.), Readings in the psychology of the language (pp. 142–143). Prentice-Hall, 1967.Google Scholar
  20. Chomsky, N. (1960). Explanatory models in linguistics. In Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 44, pp. 528–550).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Chomsky, N. (1964). Current issues in the linguistic theory. The Hague/Paris: Mouton.Google Scholar
  22. Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Chomsky, N. (1966). Cartesian linguistics: A chapter in the history of rationalist thought. New York: Harper & Row.Google Scholar
  24. Chomsky, N. (1982). A note on the creative aspect of language use. The Philosophical Review III, 1982, 423–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Clark, A. (2008a). Supersizing the mind. Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Clark, A. (2008b). Surfing uncertainty. Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty. Prediction, action and the embodied mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  28. Clowry, G.J. (2014). Seeking clues in brain development to explain the extraordinary evolution of language in humans. Language Sciences, 46, 220–231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Coello, C.A., Lamont, G.B., & Van Veldhuizen, D.A. (2007). Evolutionary algorithms for solving multi-objective problems. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
  30. Cook, J.Th. (1991). Spinoza’s science of the ‘idea of the body. In J.C. Smith (Ed.), Historical Foundation of Cognitive Science (pp. 81–98). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
  31. Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason and the human brain. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  32. Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. Mariner Books.Google Scholar
  33. Damasio, A. (2004). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, sorrow, and the feeling brain. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
  34. Della Rocca, M. (2008). Spinoza. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  35. Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science.Google Scholar
  36. Gallagher, S. (2017a). Enactivist interventions rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Gallagher, S. (2017b). Theory, practice and performance. Connection Science, 29(I), 106–118.Google Scholar
  38. Gallagher, S. (2018). Mindfulness and mindlessness in performance. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 1, 5–18.Google Scholar
  39. Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind. An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  40. García-Moreno, F., Vasistha, N.A., Trevia, N., Bourne, J.A., & Molnár, Z. (2011). Compartmentalization of cerebral cortical germinal zones in a lissencephalic primate and gyr-encephalic rodent. Cerebral Cortex, bhr312.Google Scholar
  41. Ghazanfar, A.A., & Rendall, D. (2008). Evolution of human vocal production. Current Biology, 18(11), R457–R460.Google Scholar
  42. Gibbs, R.W. (2005). Embodiment and cognitive science. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Gibbs, R.W. (2008). The Cambridge handbook of metaphor and thought. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Gibson, J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  45. Godfrey-Smith, P. (2001). On the status and explanatory structure of developmental systems theory. In P. E. Griffiths & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (pp. 283–298). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  46. Hurley, S. (2001). Perception and action: Alternative views. Synthese, 129, 3–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Hutto, D., Myin, E. (2013). Radicalising enactivism. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  48. Jansen, T. (2013). Analyzing evolutionary algorithms. The computer science perspective. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Jaquet, C. (2004). L’unité du corps et de l’esprit. Affects, actions et passions chez Spinoza. Paris: Puf.Google Scholar
  50. Klein, D., Zatorre, R.J., Milner, B., Meyer, E., & Evans, A.C. (1994). Left putaminal activation when speaking a second language: Evidence from PET. Neuroreport, 5(17), 2295–2297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Ko, J.H., Antonelli, F., Monchi, O., Ray, N., Rusjan, P., Houle, S., et al. (2013). Prefrontal dopaminergic receptor abnormalities and executive functions in Parkinson’s disease. Human Brain Mapping, 34(7), 1591–1604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. London: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  53. Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh. The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  54. LeDoux, J. (1998). The emotional brain. The mysterious underpinnings of emotional life. Touchstone: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
  55. LeDoux, J. (2003). Synaptic self: How our brains become who we are. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  56. Leroi-Gourhan, A. (1964). Le geste et la parole (Vol. 2) (trad: Bostock, A., Gesture and speech. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993). Paris: Albin Michel.Google Scholar
  57. Leroi-Gourhan, A. (1983). Mécaniques vivant. Le crâne des vertébrés du poisson à l’homme. Paris: Fayard.Google Scholar
  58. Libet, B. (2004). Mind time. The temporal factor in consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  59. Lieberman, P. (2013). The unpredictable species. What makes humans unique. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Lieberman, P., & McCarthy, R. (2007). Tracking the evolution of language and speech: Comparing vocal tracts to identify speech capabilities. Expedition: The magazine of the University of Pennsylvania, 49(2), 15–20.Google Scholar
  61. Lucretius, C.T. (DRN). In H.A.J. Munro & J.D. Duff (Eds.), Titi Lucreti Cari De rerum natura libri sex. London: G. Bell and Sons. (1903)Google Scholar
  62. Menary, R. (2006). Radical Enactivism. Intentionality, phenomenology and narrative. Amsterdam: Benjamins.Google Scholar
  63. Menary, R. (2010). The extended mind. New Edition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Monchi, O., Petrides, M., Petre, V., Worsley, K., & Dagher, A. (2001). Wisconsin card sorting revisited: Distinct neural circuits participating in different stages of the task identified by event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging. The Journal of Neuroscience, 21(19), 7733–7741.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Monchi, O., Petrides, M., Strafella, A.P., Worsley, K.J., & Doyon, J. (2006). Functional role of the basal ganglia in the planning and execution of actions. Annals of Neurology, 59(2), 257–264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Nagano-Saito, A., Leyton, M., Monchi, O., Goldberg, Y.K., He, Y., & Dagher, A. (2008). Dopamine depletion impairs frontostriatal functional connectivity during a set-shifting task. The Journal of Neuroscience, 28(14), 3697–3706.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Representation in mind. Cambridge, MA/London: MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  68. Noë, A. (2009). Out of our heads. Why you are not your brain. New York: Farrar-Straus-Giroux.Google Scholar
  69. Noë, A. (2015). Strange tools. Art and human nature. New York: Farrar-Straus-Giroux.Google Scholar
  70. Penfield, W., & Rasmussen, T. (1950). The cerebral cortex of man: A clinical study of localization of function. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  71. Pennisi, A. (2006). Patologie e psicopatologie del linguaggio. In A. Pennisi & P. Perconti (Eds.), Le scienze cognitive del linguaggio. Bologna: Il Mulino.Google Scholar
  72. Pennisi, A. (2016). Prospettive evoluzioniste nell’embodied cognition: il cervello “inquilino” del corpo. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 1(2016), 179–202.Google Scholar
  73. Pennisi, A. (2017). Cosa può un corpo. Spinoza e l’Embodied Cognition, Bollettino del centro di studi filologici e linguistici siciliani, 28/2017, Special Issue In ricordo di Tullio De Mauro, F L. Piparo (Ed.) (pp. 237–264).Google Scholar
  74. Pennisi, G. (2017). What space for performativity in cognitive science? Insights from CODISCO 2017. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 2(2017), 381–386.Google Scholar
  75. Pennisi, A. (2018a). Performative dimensions in cognitive sciences. Reti, saperi, linguaggi Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 1(2018), 25–30.Google Scholar
  76. Pennisi, A. (2018b). Laicità e diritti, Scritti in onore di Demetrio Neri. In F. A. e. L. Formigari (Ed.), Spinoza, Darwin e Nietzsche. L’etica come etologia dei corpi o biopolitica (pp. 61–87). Roma: Aracne.Google Scholar
  77. Pennisi, G. (2018). Towards a deeply embodied Enactivism. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 2(2018), 271–280.Google Scholar
  78. Pennisi, A. (2019). Spinoza e l’Embodied Cognition, in Atti del Convegno internazionale di studi del CISPELS. Storia del pensiero linguistico e semiotico (Roma 17–19 Settembre 2018), In print Roma: Sapienza University Press.Google Scholar
  79. Pennisi, A., & Falzone, A. (2016). Darwinian biolinguistics. Theory and history of naturalistic philosophy on language. Berlin/Heidelberg/New York/Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
  80. Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Rakic, P. (2009). Evolution of the neocortex: A perspective from developmental biology. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(10), 724–735.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Ramachandran, V.S. (2003). The emerging mind: The Reith lectures 2003. London: Profile.Google Scholar
  83. Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
  84. Rowlands, M. (2006). Body language: Representation in action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Sangiacomo, A. (2010a). Saggio introduttivo a Spinoza (Op.), pp. 7–100.Google Scholar
  87. Sangiacomo, A. (2010b). Gli strani confini della coscienza: Spinoza e gli animali. Giornale Critico di Storia delle Idee, A.2, n.4, 2010, pp. 145–162.Google Scholar
  88. Sangiacomo, A. (2011). Adequate knowledge and bodily complexity in Spinoza’s account of consciousness, Methodus, 6(2011), 77–104.Google Scholar
  89. Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning. Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Shapiro, L.A. (2004). The mind incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  91. Shapiro, L.A. (2011). Embodied cognition London/New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  92. Shapiro, L.A. (2014). The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition London/New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  93. Simard, F., Joanette, Y., Petrides, M., Jubault, T., Madjar, C., & Monchi, O. (2010). Fronto-striatal contribution to lexical set-shifting. Cerebral Cortex, 21, 1084–1093.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Skoyles, J.R., & Sagan, D. (2002). Up from dragons: The evolution of human intelligence. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  95. Spinoza, B. (1656-TIE). Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione. In Spinoza CW, pp. 1–30.Google Scholar
  96. Spinoza, B. (1661-KV). Korte Verhandeling van God, de Mensch, en dezself Welstand. In Spinoza CW, pp. 31–107.Google Scholar
  97. Spinoza, B. (1663-CM). Cogitata Metaphysica. In Spinoza CW, pp. 177–212.Google Scholar
  98. Spinoza, B. (2002). (CW) Complete works. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by Michael L. Morgan, Translations by Samuel Shirley, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  99. Spinoza, B. (1663-DCPP). Renati Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiæ. In Spinoza CW, pp. 108–177.Google Scholar
  100. Spinoza, B. (1677-EOGD). Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata. In Spinoza CW, pp. 213–382.Google Scholar
  101. Stewart, J. (2010). Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: From the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 1–31). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  102. Thivierge, J.P., Rivest, F., & Monchi, O. (2007). Spiking neurons, dopamine, and plasticity: Timing is everything, but concentration also matters. Synapse/New York, 61(6), 375.Google Scholar
  103. Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  104. Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge MA/London: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  105. Ventura, S., & Luna, J.M. (2016). Pattern mining with evolutionary algorithms. Cham: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  106. Vico, G.B. (1710). De antiquissima Italorum Sapientia ex linguae latinae originibus eruenda. In N. Badaloni & P. Cristofolini (Eds.), GB Vico, Opere filosofiche, G. Firenze: Sansoni. (1971).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2020

Authors and Affiliations

  • Antonino Pennisi
    • 1
  1. 1.University of MessinaMessinaItaly

Personalised recommendations