Advertisement

Autonomy and the Birth of Authenticity

  • Tim Black
Chapter

Abstract

Authenticity has become one of the defining ideals of the modern world. It is the quality we are meant to demand in that which we consume; a value to be opposed to all that is ‘fake’ or ‘phoney’ or ‘artificial’. Above all, it is what an individual is meant to aspire to be: true to one’s self, self-actualising and self-expressing. Authenticity today has an almost ethical force. It underpins identity politics, legitimises transgenderism and informs the ubiquitous demand for often legal recognition and informal respect. But what does its elevation say about the condition of modernity? What is its historical and conceptual relationship to ideas of freedom and autonomy? And to what extent is it really possible or even desirable, as Shakespeare’s Polonius insisted it was, to be true to thine own self?

References

  1. Berman, M. (1971). The politics of authenticity. New York and London: George Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
  2. Cranston, M. (1991). Jean-Jacques: The early life and work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, 1712–1754. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  3. Diderot, D. (1976). Rameau’s nephew and D’Alembert’s dream (L. Tancock, Trans.). London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  4. Durant, W., & Durant, A. (1967). Rousseau and revolution. New York: Fine Communications.Google Scholar
  5. Ellingson, T. (2001). The myth of the noble savage. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Ferrara, A. (1992). Modernity and authenticity: A study of the social and ethical thought of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
  7. Goethe, J. W. (1962). The sorrows of young Werther, and selected writings (C. Hutter, Trans.). New York: The New American Library.Google Scholar
  8. Gutmann, A., & Taylor, C. (1994). Multiculturalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Hartman, A. (2015). A history of the culture wars: A war for the soul of America. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hegel, G. W. F. (1896). Lectures on the history of philosophy (E. S. Haldane & F. Simpson, Trans., vol. 3). London: Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  11. Heidegger, M. (2000). Being and time (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Marcuse, H. (2002). One-dimensional man: Studies in the ideology of advanced industrial society. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  13. Marx, K. (1961). Economic and philosophic manuscripts of 1844 (M. Milligan, Trans.). New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
  14. Rousseau, J. J. (1979). Emile, or on education (A. Bloom, Trans.). New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  15. Rousseau, J. J. (1987). The basic political writings (D. A. Cress, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.Google Scholar
  16. Rousseau, J. J. (1997). Julie, or the new Heloise (J. Vache, Trans.). New Hampshire: Dartmouth College Press.Google Scholar
  17. Rousseau, J. J. (2008). Confessions (A. Scholar, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Sartre, J.-P. (2003). Being and nothingness: An essay in phenomenological ontology (H. E. Barnes, Trans.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  19. Taylor, C. (2007). A secular age. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Trilling, L. (1972). Sincerity and authenticity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Varga, S. (2013). Authenticity as an ethical ideal. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  22. Williams, R. (1958). Culture and society. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Tim Black
    • 1
  1. 1.LondonUK

Personalised recommendations