Advertisement

Maier on the Alleged Transparency of Mixed Quotation

  • Alessandro Capone
Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 22)

Abstract

In this chapter I propose, unlike Maier (Semant Pragmat 7, 2014), that quoted fragments in so called ‘mixed quotations’ (what I prefer to call ‘mixed indirect reports’) are opaque. This view of opacity is required, we propose, to preserve the difference between direct and indirect reports, direct reports involving possibly high levels of literality, accuracy and granularity, even if we concede, in keeping with Maier, that verbatim quotations are also susceptible to contextual standards of ‘verbatimness’, as Maier terms it. Maier’s considerations against opacity and in favour of transparency are based on a shifted interpretation of indexicals, anaphoric reference, morphological adjustments (in Italian) and grammatical adjustments (transformations involving a different word order with respect to the original utterance in Dutch). Claim by claim, we are made aware that we should see regard things differently and that, after all, it makes sense to adhere to the conservative and classical Fregean claim that mixed quotations (and indeed quotations) are cases involving opacity. In fact, where would we be if we abandoned the idea that quotation in mixed quotation requires reference to an utterance understood to be verbatim, rather than through mere paraphrase? Is this not similar to arguing that quotation is also not an opaque context? Yet Frege, as highlighted by Evans (The varieties of reference, OUP, Oxford, 1982), insisted that intensional contexts were contexts providing evidence in favour of opacity and were at a level of meaning which was different from denotation (the other level of meaning which is constituted by senses or modes of presentation).

References

  1. Allan, Keith (2016). Reports, indirect reports and illocutionary force. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Indirect reports and pragmatics. Dordrecht, Springer, 573–592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bonami, Olivier, Godard, Daniele (2008). On the syntax of direct quotation in French. In R. Bauerle, U. Reyle, E. Zimmerman, eds. Presuppositions and discourse: essays offered to Hans Kamp. Oxford, Elsevier, 65–99.Google Scholar
  3. Capone, Alessandro (2008). Belief reports and pragmatic intrusion. The case of null appositives. Journal of Pragmatics.Google Scholar
  4. Capone, Alessandro (2010a). On the social practice of indirect reports. Journal of Pragmatics 42, 377–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Capone, Alessandro (2010b). Between Scylla and Charibdis: The semantics and pragmatics of attitudes ‘de se’. Intercultural Pragmatics 7 (3):471–503 (2010).
  6. Capone, Alessandro (2013). The pragmatics of indirect reports and slurring. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, M. Carapezza, eds. Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics. Dordrecht, Springer, 152–184.Google Scholar
  7. Capone, Alessandro (2016). Indirectly reporting and translating slurring utterances. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Indirect reports and pragmatics. Dordrecht, Springer, 233–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Capone, Alessandro (2016). The pragmatics of indirect reports. Socio-Philosophical considerations. Dordrecht, Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Capone, Alessandro. 2016. The pragmatics of indirect reports. Socio-philosophical considerations. Cham, Springer Verlag.Google Scholar
  10. Capone, Alessandro (2017). On the tension between semantics and pragmatics. In K. Allan, A. Capone, I. Kecskes, eds. Pragmemes and theories of language use. Dordrecht, Springer.Google Scholar
  11. Capone, Alessandro (2018). Indirectly reporting grammatical, lexical, and morphological errors. International journal of Language Studies.12/1, 19–36.Google Scholar
  12. Capone, Alessandro, Mohammad Ali Salmani Nodoushan (2014). On indirect reports and language games: Evidence from Persian. RIFL (Rivista Italiana di Filosofia del Linguaggio) 2, 26–42.Google Scholar
  13. Cappelen, Herman, Lepore, Ernie (2005). Liberating content. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  14. Castañeda, Hector-Neri (1966). “‘He’: A Study in the Logic of Self-Consciousness.” Ratio 8: pp. 130–157.Google Scholar
  15. Cummings, Louise (2016). Reported speech: a clinical pragmatic perspectives. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Indirect reports and pragmatics. Cham, Springer.Google Scholar
  16. Davidson, Donald (1968). On saying that. Synthese 19 (1–2):130–146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Davidson, Donald (1979). Quotation. Theory and decision. 11/1, 27–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Davis, Wayne (2016). A theory of saying reports. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Indirect reports and pragmatics. Interdisciplinary studies. Cham, Springer, 291–333.Google Scholar
  19. Devitt, Michael (1996). Coming to our senses. Cambridge, CUP.Google Scholar
  20. Devitt, Michael (2018). Subsententials: pragmatics or semantics? In A. Capone, M. Carapezza, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Further avances in pragmatics and philosophy. Part 1: From theory to practice. Cham, Springer, 45–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Evans, Gareth (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  22. Gibbs, Raymond (1999). Intentions in the experience of meaning. Cambridge, CUP.Google Scholar
  23. Goffman, E. (1981). Forms of talk. Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press.Google Scholar
  24. Goldberg, Sanford (2015). Assertion. On the philosophical significante of assertoric speech. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  25. Higginbotham, James (2003). “Remembering, Imagining, and the First Person.” In Alex Barber (ed.), Epistemology of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 496–533.Google Scholar
  26. Jaszczolt, Kasia. 1999. Discourse, beliefs and intentions. Oxford, Elsevier.Google Scholar
  27. Jaszczolt, Kasia (2016). Meaning in linguistic interaction. Semantics, metasemantics, philosophy of language. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lepore, Ernie, Ludwig, Kirk (2007). Donald Davidson’s truth-theoretic semantics. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Levinson, S.C. (2000). Presumptive meanings. Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Maier, Emar (2014). Mixed quotation: the grammar of apparently transparent opacity. Semantics & Pragmatics 7, 2014.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Mey Jacob 2001 Pragmatics, Oxford, Blackwell.Google Scholar
  32. Parson, Terence (2014). Articulating medieval logic. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Rosenthal, D. (2003). Unity of consciousness and the self. Meeting of the Aristotelian Society, pp. 325–352.Google Scholar
  34. Salmon, Nathan (2018). Semantically empty gestures. In A. Capone, M. Carapezza, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Further advances in pragmatics and philosophy. From theory to practice. Cham, Springer, 3–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Schlenker, P. (2003). A plea for monsters. Linguistics and Philosophy 26–1, 29–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Stalnaker, Robert (1999). Context and Content. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Voloshinov, V. N. (1971). Reported speech. In L. Matejka & K. Promorska (Eds.), Readings in Russian poetGoogle Scholar
  38. Wettstein, Howard (2016). Speaking for another. In A. Capone, F. Kiefer, F. Lo Piparo, eds. Indirect reports and pragmatics. Cham, Springer, 405–434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Wieland, Nellie (2013). Indirect reports and pragmatics. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, M. Carapezza, eds. Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy. Cham, Springer, 389–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Wong, Jock (2010). The triple articulation of language. In A. Capone, ed. Pragmemes. Journal of Pragmatics 42/11, 2932–2944.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Alessandro Capone
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Cognitive ScienceUniversity of MessinaMessinaItaly

Personalised recommendations