Advertisement

The Pragmatics of Referential and Attributive Expressions

  • Alessandro Capone
Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 22)

Abstract

In this chapter I deal with the attributive/referential distinction. After reviewing the literature on the issue, I adopt Jaszczolt’s view based on default semantics. I relate her view to Sperber & Wilson’s Principle of Relevance. I argue in favour of the modularity hypothesis in connection with pragmatic interpretations. I also discuss the issue of modularization à la Karmiloff-Smith in connection with default inferences and, in particular, the referential readings of NPs. I then reply to some considerations by Cummings and use data from the referential/attributive uses of NPs to show that the modularity hypothesis is defensible.

References

  1. Allan, Keith (2010). Referring as a pragmatic act. In Capone, A. (Ed.). Pragmemes. Journal of Pragmatics 42, 2919–2931.Google Scholar
  2. Bach, Kent (1981). Referential/attributive. Synthese 49, 219–244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bach, Kent (2004). Descriptions: points of reference. In Reimer, M. & Bezuidenhout, A. (Eds). Descriptions and beyond, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 189–229.Google Scholar
  4. Barrett, Clark H. (2005). Enzymatic computation and cognitive modularity. Mind and Language 20/3, 259–287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bezuidenhout, Ann (1997). Pragmatics, semantic underdetermination and the referential/attributive distinction. Mind 106/423, 375–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Blakemore, Diane (2000). Indicators and procedures: nevertheless and but. Journal of Linguistics 36, 463–486.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bontly, Thomas (2005). Conversational implicature and the referential use of descriptions. Philosophical Studies 125, 1–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Burton-Roberts, Noel (2005). Robyn Carston on semantics, pragmatics, and ‘encoding’. Journal of Linguistics 41: 389–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Capone, Alessandro (2005). Pragmemes. Journal of Pragmatics 42/11, 2861–3162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Capone, Alessandro (2006). On Grice’s circle. Journal of Pragmatics 38, 645–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Capone, Alessandro (2009). Are explicatures cancellable? Intercultural Pragmatics 6/1, 55–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Capone, Alessandro (2010a). “Between Scylla and Charybdis”: The semantics and pragmatics of attitudes “de se”. Intercultural Pragmatics 7/3 (2010), 471–503.Google Scholar
  13. Capone, Alessandro (2010b). What can modularity of mind tell us about the semantics/pragmatics debate. Australian Journal of Linguistics 30/4, 497–522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Capone, Alessandro. (Ed.) (2010c). Pragmemes. Special issue, Journal of Pragmatics 42.Google Scholar
  15. Capone, A. (2011). Default semantics and the architecture of the mind. Accepted by the Journal of Pragmatics 43, 1741–1754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Carston, Robyn. 2002. Thoughts and utterances: the pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford, Wiley.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Carruthers, Peter (2006). The architecture of the mind. OUP, Oxford.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Cram, D. & Hedley, P. (2005). Pronouns and procedural meaning: the relevance of spaghetti code and paranoid delusion. Oxford working papers in linguistics, Philology and Phonetics, 10, 187–210.Google Scholar
  19. Cummings, Louise (2009). Clinical Pragmatics. Cambridge, CUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Davis, W. A. (1998). Implicature: Intention, Convention, and Principle in the Failure of Gricean Theory. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Devitt, Michael (2003). The case for referential descriptions. In: Bezuidenhout, A., Reimer, M. (Eds.). Descriptions: semantic and pragmatic perspectives. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  22. Devitt, Michael (2007). Referential descriptions and conversational implicatures. EUJAP 3/2, 7–32.Google Scholar
  23. Donnellan, Keith (1966). Reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Review 75, 281–304. Reprinted in: Davis, S. (Ed.). Pragmatics. A reader. Oxford, OUP, 52–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Fodor Jerry (1981). RePresentations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  25. Fodor, Jerry A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Fodor, Jerry A. (2000). The mind doesn’t work that way: the scope and limits of computational psychology. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Griffiths, Paul, Stotz, Karola (2000). How the mind grows: a developmental perspective on the biology of cognition. Synthese 122, 29–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Higginbotham, James (2009). Tense, aspect and indexicality. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Hirschberg, Julia (1985). A Theory of Scalar Implicature. University of Pennsylvania dissertation.Google Scholar
  30. Huang, Yan (2000). Anaphora. A crosslinguistic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  31. Jaszczolt, Katarzyna (1999). Discourse, Beliefs and Intentions. Elsevier, Oxford.Google Scholar
  32. Jaszczolt, Katarzyna (2005). Default semantics. Foundations of a compositional theory of acts of communication. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kasher, Asa (1991). On the pragmatic modules. Journal of Pragmatics 16, 381–397.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Karmiloff-Smith, Annette (1992). Beyond modularity. A developmental perspective on cognitive science. Cambridge, MA, MIT.Google Scholar
  35. Kripke, Saul (1977). Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. In: Fench, P., Uehling, T., Wettstein, H. (Eds.). Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 6–27.Google Scholar
  36. Levinson, Stephen (2000). Presumptive meanings. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Linsky, Leonard (1971). Reference and referents. In: Steinberg, D., Jakobovits, L. (Eds.). Semantics. An interdisciplinary reader in philosophy, linguistics and psychology. Cambridge, CUP., 76–84.Google Scholar
  38. Mey, Jacob (2001). Pragmatics. Oxford, Blackwell.Google Scholar
  39. Neale, Stephen (1990). Descriptions. Cambridge, MIT Press.Google Scholar
  40. Perconti, Pietro (2008). L’autocoscienza. Cosa è, come funziona, a cosa serve. Bari: Laterza.Google Scholar
  41. Powell, George (2001). The referential-attributive distinction – a cognitive account. Pragmatics & Cognition 9/1, 69–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Predelli, Stefano (2003). Russellian description and Smith’s suicide. Acta Analytica 18/31, 1–17.Google Scholar
  43. Price, H.H. (1932). Perception. London, Methuen.Google Scholar
  44. Recanati, Francois (1989). Referential/attributive: a contextualist proposal. Philosophical Studies 56, 217–249.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Rouchota, Villy. 1992. On the referential/attributive distinction. Lingua 87, 137–167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Salmon, Nathan (1982). Assertion and incomplete definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies 42, 37–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Searle, John (1979). Referential and attributive. In Searle, John. Expression and meaning. Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge, CUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Segal, G. (1996). The modularity of theory of mind. In P. Carruthers, P.K. Smith eds Theories of theories of mind, Cambridge, CUP, 141–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Simon, H. (1986). Rationality in psychology and economics. The Journal of Business 59/4, Part 2, 209–224.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Soames, Scott (1994). Donnellan’s referential/attributive distinction. Philosophical Studies 73, 149–168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Strawson, P. (1951). On referring. In: Logico-Linguistic papers, London, Methuen.Google Scholar
  52. Wettstein, Howard (1981). Demonstrative reference and definite descriptions. Philosophical Studies 40/2, 241–257.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Wettstein, Howard (1983). The semantic significance of the referential-attributive distinction. Philosophical Studies 44, 187–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Wettstein, Howard (2012). Having in mind. In J. Almog & P. Leonardi, 93–107.Google Scholar
  55. Wilson, Deirdre and Dan Sperber (2002). Truthfulness and relevance. Mind 111: 583–632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Zielinska, Dorota (2010). Prepositions and explicature from the perspective of the selective mode of language use in the quantized c-field (SMLU) approach. In Capone, A. (Ed.). Perspectives on language use and pragmatics. Muenchen, Lincom, 181–210.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Alessandro Capone
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Cognitive ScienceUniversity of MessinaMessinaItaly

Personalised recommendations