Advertisement

Conversational Presuppositions. Presupposition as Defeasible (And Non-defeasible) Inference

  • Alessandro Capone
Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 22)

Abstract

Is presupposition a semantic or genuinely pragmatic notion? My answer in this paper is that it is a pragmatic notion and I provide explanantions for this view, mainly related to cancellability. Of course, it is not easy to extract theoretical considerations from data and it is possible that one gives an opnionated interpretation of the data. However, at least I wish to propose that in the case of presuppositions data have to be seen in a different way and new data must also be consulted.

References

  1. Abbott, Barbara (2000). Presuppositions as non-assertions. Journal of Pragmatics 32, 1419-37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Abbott Barbara (2008). Presuppositions as common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy 21, 523-538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Andreasen, N.C., Grove, W.M. (1986). Thought, language and communication in schizophrenia: diagnosis and prognosis. Schizophrenia Bulletin 12/3, 348-359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Asher, Nicholas (2000). Events, facts, propositions and evolutive anaphora. In Higginbotham, James, Pianesi, Fabio, Varzi, Achille. Speaking of events. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  5. Atlas, Jay (2004). Presupposition. In L.R. Horn, G. Ward, eds. The Handbook of Pragmatics. Oxford, Blackwell.Google Scholar
  6. Atlas, Jay, Levinson, Stephen C. (1981). It-clefts, informativeness and logical form. In Cole, Peter, ed. Radical pragmatics. (1–51). New York, Academic Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bach, Kent (1994). Conversational impliciture. Mind and Language 9, 124–162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Bach, Kent (2001). Semantically speaking. In Perspectives on semantics, pragmatics and discourse. A festschrift for Ferenc Kiefer. Istva´n Kenesei and Robert M. Harnish (eds.), 146–170. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  9. Burge, Tyler (2013). Cognition through understanding. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Burton-Roberts, Noel (2005). Robyn Carston on semantics, pragmatics, and ‘encoding’. Journal of Linguistics 41, 389–407.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Burton-Roberts, Noel (2006). Cancellation and intention. Newcastle University, School of English, Manuscript to be published in the Newcastle working papers in linguistics. Esther Romero and Belen Soria (eds.). Explicit communication: Robyn Carston’s pragmatics. London: Palgrave-Macmillan.Google Scholar
  12. Capone, Alessandro (1998). Modality and discourse. PhD dissertation, University of Oxford.Google Scholar
  13. Capone, Alessandro (2000). Dilemmas and excogitations: an essay on modality, clitics and discourse. Messina, Armando Siciliano.Google Scholar
  14. Capone, Alessandro (2003). On Grice’s circle (further considerations on the semantics/pragmatics debate). RASK: International Journal of Language and Communication 19: 3–32.Google Scholar
  15. Capone, Alessandro (2006). On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type). Journal of Pragmatics 38: 645–669.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Capone, Alessandro (2009). Are explicatures cancellable? Towards a theory of the speaker’s intentionality. Intercultural Pragmatics 6/1, 55-88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Capone, Alessandro. 2010. On the social practice of indirect reports. Further advances in the theory of Pragmemes. Journal of Pragmatics 22/2, 377-91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Capone, Alessandro (2011). The attributive/referential distinction, pragmatics, Modularity of mind and modularization. Australian Journal of Linguistics 31/2, 153-186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Capone, Alessandro. 2012. The pragmatics of quotation, explicatures and modularity of mind, Pragmatics and Society 4/3, 259-294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Capone, Alessandro (2013a). The pragmatics of quotation, explicatures and modularity of mind. Pragmatics and Society 4/3, 259-284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Capone Alessandro (2013b). The role of pragmatics in reconstructing the rational law-maker. Pragmatics and Cognition 21/2, 399-414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Capone, Alessandro (2013c). The pragmatics of pronominal clitics and propositional attitudes. Intercultural Pragmatics 10/3, 459-485.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Capone A 2016 The pragmatics of indirect reports. Socio-philosophical considerations. Cham, Springer.Google Scholar
  24. Cappelen, Herman & Lepore, Ernie (1997). Varieties of quotation. Mind 106/423, 429–450.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Carston, Robyn (2002). Thought and utterances. The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford, Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Chierchia, Gennaro and Sally McConnell-Ginet (1990). Meaning and grammar. Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press.Google Scholar
  27. Cutting, J. (1989). Psicologia della schizophrenia. Torino, Bollati Boringhieri.Google Scholar
  28. Elbourne, Paul (2013). Definite descriptions. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Gazdar, Jerald, 1979. Pragmatics. New York, Academic Press.Google Scholar
  30. Geurts, Bart (1994). Presupposing. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Osnabrück.Google Scholar
  31. Goffman, E. (1981). Forms of talk. Pennsylvania University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Goodwin, C. (2007). Interactive Footing. Pp. 16–46 in Reporting Talk: Reported Speech in Interaction, edited by Elizabeth Holt and Rebecca Clift. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Grice. P.H. (1989). Studies in the way of words. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  34. Haugh, Michael (2014). Im/politeness implicatures. Berlin/New York, Mouton De Gruyter.Google Scholar
  35. Heim, Irene (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of semantics 9, 183-221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Huang, Yan (1994). The syntax and pragmatics of anaphora. A study with special reference to Chinese. Cambridge, CUP.Google Scholar
  37. Huang, Yan (2014). Pragmatics. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  38. Jaszczolt, Kasia (1999). Discourse, beliefs and intentions. Oxford, Elsevier.Google Scholar
  39. Jaszczolt, Kasia (2005). Default semantics: Foundations of a compositional theory of acts of communication. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Jaszczolt, Kasia (2016). Meaning in linguistic interaction. Semantics, metasemantics, philosophy of language. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Kecskes, Istvan (2013). Intercultural pragmatics. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Kempson, Ruth (1975). Presupposition and the delimitation of semantics. Cambridge, CUP.Google Scholar
  43. Kennedy, Christopher (2002). Nigger: the strange career of a troublesome word. New York, Vintage.Google Scholar
  44. Levinson, Stephen C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge, CUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Levinson, Stephen C. (2000). Presumptive meanings. The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge Mass., MIT PRESS.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Lewis, David (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8, 339-359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Macagno, Fabrizio, Capone, Alessandro (2016a). Presuppositions as cancellable inferences. In K. Allan, A. Capone, I. Kecskes, eds. Pragmemes and theories of language use. Dordrecht, Springer.Google Scholar
  48. Macagno, Fabrizio, Capone, Alessandro (2016b). Uncommon ground. Intercultural Pragmatics 13/2, 51-180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Saka, Paul (1998). Quotation and the use-mention distinction. Mind 107/425, 113–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Simons, Mandy (2013). On the conversational basis of some presuppositions. In A. Capone, F. Lo Piparo, M. Carapezza, eds. Perspectives on linguistic pragmatics. Dordrecht, Springer, 329-348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Stalnaker, Robert (1974). Pragmatic presuppositions. In K. Muniitz, P. Unger, eds. Semantics and Philosophy. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
  52. Stalnaker, Robert (1999). Context and content. Essays on intentionality if speech and thought. Oxford, OUP.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Stalnaker, R. (2008). A response to Abbott on presuppositions and common ground. Linguistics & Philosophy 31:539–544.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. von Heusinger, Klaus. 2002. Specificity and definiteness in sentence and discourse structure. Journal of Semantics 19. 1–30.Van der Sandt, Rob (1992). Presupposition projection as anaphora resolution. Journal of Semantics 9, 333-77.Google Scholar
  55. Van der Sandt, Rob (2012). Presupposition and accommodation in discourse. In K. Allan, K. Jaszczolt, eds. The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics. Cambridge, CUP.Google Scholar
  56. Williamson, Timothy, 2000. Knowledge and its limits. Oxford, OUP.Google Scholar
  57. Wilson, Deirdre (1975). Presupposition and non-truth-conditional semantics. New York, Academic Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  • Alessandro Capone
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of Cognitive ScienceUniversity of MessinaMessinaItaly

Personalised recommendations