Advertisement

Realizing Epistemic Democracy

  • Marcus PivatoEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Economic Design book series (DESI)

Abstract

Many collective decisions depend upon questions about objective facts or probabilities. Several theories in social choice and political philosophy suggest that democratic institutions can obtain accurate answers to such questions. But these theories are founded on assumptions and modelling paradigms that are both implausible and incompatible with one another. I will propose a roadmap for a more realistic and unified approach to this problem.

Notes

Acknowledgements

I thank Gabriel Carroll, Franz Dietrich, Umberto Grandi, Justin Leroux, Christian List, Arianna Novaro, Kai Spiekermann, and Bill Zwicker for their very helpful comments. None of them are responsible for any errors.

References

  1. Acemoğlu, D., & Ozdaglar, A. (2011). Opinion dynamics and learning in social networks. Dynamic Games and Applications, 1(1), 3–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Ahn, D. S., & Oliveros, S. (2014). The Condorcet jur(ies) theorem. Journal of Economic Theory, 150, 841–851.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Austen-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. (2005). Deliberation and voting rules. In Austen-Smith, D. & Duggan, J. (Eds.), Social Choice and Strategic Decisions: Essays in honour of Jeffrey S. Banks (pp. 269–316). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.Google Scholar
  4. Austen-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2006). Deliberation, preference uncertainty, and voting rules. American Political Science Review, 100(2), 209–217.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Austen-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2009). Information aggregation and communication in committees. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 364(1518), 763–769.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Bächtiger, A., Dryzek, J., Mansbridge, J., & Warren, M. (eds.). (2018). Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Bednar, J., Bramson, A., Jones-Rooy, A., & Page, S. E. (2010). Emergent cultural signatures and persistent diversity: A model of conformity and consistency. Rationality and Society, 22(4), 407–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Berg, S. (1993). Condorcet’s jury theorem, dependency among jurors. Social Choice and Welfare, 10(1), 87–95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bovens, L., & Rabinowicz, W. (2006). Democratic answers to complex questions–an epistemic perspective. Synthese, 150(1), 131–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Bozbay, I., Dietrich, F., & Peters, H. (2014). Judgment aggregation in search for the truth. Games and Economic Behavior, 87, 571–590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Castellano, C., Fortunato, S., & Loreto, V. (2009). Statistical physics of social dynamics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 81, 591.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Castellano, C. (2012). Social influence and the dynamics of opinions: The approach of statistical physics. Managerial and Decision Economics, 33(5–6), 311–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Clemen, R. T., & Winkler, R. L. (1999). Combining probability distributions from experts in risk analysis. Risk analysis, 19(2), 187–203.Google Scholar
  14. Cohen, J. (1986). An epistemic conception of democracy. Ethics, 97(1), 26–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. de Condorcet, M. (1785). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix, Paris.Google Scholar
  16. D’Alfonso, S. (2016). Belief merging with the aim of truthlikeness. Synthese, 193(7), 2013–2034.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Danan, Eric, Gajdos, Thibault, Hill, Brian, & Tallon, Jean-Marc. (2016). Robust social decisions. American Economic Review, 106(9), 2407–2425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. de Finetti, B. (1970) [2017]. Theory of probability. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Translated from Italian by Antonio Machi and Adrian Smith.Google Scholar
  19. Deimen, I., Ketelaar, F., & Le Quement, M. T. (2015). Consistency and communication in committees. Journal of Economic Theory, 160, 24–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Dietrich, Franz. (2010). Bayesian group belief. Social Choice and Welfare, 35(4), 595–626.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Dietrich, Franz, & List, Christian. (2004). A model of jury decisions where all jurors have the same evidence. Synthese, 142(2), 175–202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Dietrich, Franz, & Spiekermann, Kai. (2013a). Epistemic democracy with defensible premises. Economics and Philosophy, 29(1), 87–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Dietrich, Franz, & Spiekermann, Kai. (2013b). Independent opinions? On the causal foundations of belief formation and jury theorems. Mind, 122(487), 655–685.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Dietrich, F., & Spiekermann, K. (2017). “Jury Theorems”. (in press).Google Scholar
  25. Elster, J. (Ed.). (1998). Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge UP.Google Scholar
  26. Everaere, P., Konieczny, S., & Marquis, P. (2010). August. The Epistemic View of Belief Merging: Can We Track the Truth? In The 19th European Conference on Artificial Intelligence (ECAI’10) (pp. 621–626).Google Scholar
  27. Fishkin, J. S., & Laslett, P. (Eds.). (2003). Debating deliberative democracy. Blackwell.Google Scholar
  28. Galton, F. (1907). Vox populi. Nature, 75, 450–451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Genest, C., & Zidek, J. V. (1986). Combining probability distributions: a critique and an annotated bibliography. Statistical Science, 1, 114–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Gilboa, I., Schmeidler, D., & Samet, D. (2004). Utilitarian aggregation of beliefs and tastes. Journal of Political Economy, 112, 932–938.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Gilboa, I. (2009). Theory of decision under uncertainty. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Harsanyi, J. C. (1955). Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy, 63, 309–321. Reprinted in Essays on Ethics, Social Behavior, and Scientific Explanation. Dordrecht: P. Reidel.Google Scholar
  33. Hartmann, S., Pigozzi, G., & Sprenger, J. (2010). Reliable methods of judgement aggregation. Journal of Logic and Computation, 20(2), 603–617.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Hartmann, S., & Sprenger, J. (2012). Judgment aggregation and the problem of tracking the truth. Synthese, 187(1), 209–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Hylland, A., & Zeckhauser, R. (1979). The impossibility of bayesian group decision making with separate aggregation of beliefs and values. Econometrica, 47, 1321–1336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Jost, J. T., Hennes, E. P.& Lavine, H. (2013). Hot political cognition: Its self-, group-, and system- serving purposes. In Carlson, D.E. (Ed.), Oxford handbook of social cognition 851–875. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Kahan, D. M. (2016). The politically motivated reasoning paradigm, part 1: What politically motivated reasoning is and how to measure it. Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences: An Interdisciplinary, Searchable, and Linkable Resource.Google Scholar
  38. Ladha, K. K. (1992). The Condorcet Jury Theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36, 617–634.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Ladha, K. K. (1993). Condorcet’s jury theorem in light of de Finetti’s theorem. Majority-rule voting with correlated votes. Social Choice and Welfare, 10(1), 69–85.Google Scholar
  40. Ladha, K. K. (1995). Information pooling through majority-rule voting: Condorcet’s jury theorem with correlated votes. Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization, 26, 353–372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Landemore, H. (2013). Democratic reason: Politics, collective intelligence, and the rule of the many. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Landemore, H., & Elster, J. (2012). Collective wisdom: Principles and mechanisms. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  43. List, C. (2005). Group knowledge and group rationality: A judgment aggregation perspective. Episteme, 2(1), 25–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Le Quement, M., & Yokeeswaran, V. (2015). Subgroup deliberation and voting. Social Choice and Welfare, 45(1), 155–186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Lodge, Milton, & Taber, Charles. (2013). The rationalizing voter. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Lorenz, Jan. (2007). Continuous opinion dynamics under bounded confidence: A survey. International Journal of Modern Physics C, 18(12), 1819–1838.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Meirowitz, A. (2006). Designing institutions to aggregate preferences and information. Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 1(4), 373–392.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Meirowitz, A. (2007a). Communication and bargaining in the spatial model. International Journal of Game Theory, 35(2), 251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Meirowitz, A. (2007b). In defense of exclusionary deliberation: communication and voting with private beliefs and values. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 19(3), 301–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Mongin, P. (1995). Consistent Bayesian aggregation. Journal of Economic Theory, 66(2), 313–351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Mongin, P., & Pivato, M. (2015). Ranking Multidimensional Alternatives and Uncertain Prospects. Journal of Economic Theory, 157, 146–171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Mongin, P., & Pivato, M. (2017). Social preference under twofold uncertainty (preprint).Google Scholar
  53. Mossel, E., & Tamuz, O. (2017). Opinion exchange dynamics. Probability Surveys, 14, 155–204.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1984). The significance of independent decisions in uncertain dichotomous choice situations. Theory and Decision, 17(1), 47–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Page, S. E., Sander, L., & Schneider-Mizell, C. (2007). Conformity and dissonance in generalized voter models. Journal of Statistical Physics, 128, 1279–1297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Peleg, B., & Zamir, S. (2012). Extending the Condorcet jury theorem to a general dependent jury.Google Scholar
  57. Pivato, M. (2012). A statistical approach to epistemic democracy. Episteme, 9, 115–137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Pivato, M. (2013). Voting rules as statistical estimators. Social Choice and Welfare, 40(2), 581–630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Pivato, M. (2017). Epistemic democracy with correlated voters. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 72, 51–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Schwartzberg, Melissa. (2015). Epistemic democracy and its challenges. Annual Review of Political Science, 18, 187–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Sunstein, C. R. (2003). The law of group polarization. In Fishkin and Laslett (pp. 80–101).Google Scholar
  62. Sunstein, C. (2009). Republic.com 2.0. Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Université de Cergy-PontoiseCergyFrance

Personalised recommendations