Advertisement

Representation and Its Limits

  • Dror PimentelEmail author
Chapter

Abstract

Dasein; the aletheic space as the space of human attunement to Being; freedom as relatedness to Being, as letting beings be, without mastery or appropriation, as congenial engagement with beings; dual (active/passive) conception of the gaze; the gaze, the divine, and Being, are names for the aletheic space; gazing, encountering, engaging with the Other; gazing and seeing; the intentionality of sight; human vision as responsiveness to Being’s gaze; knowledge is constituted by responsiveness to Being’s solicitation; modernity’s conception of the gaze as the reflexive act of a sovereign subject, an act that doubles beings by representing them; Heidegger’s critique of the modern conception of gaze; two kinds of gaze corresponding to two human types, Greek man and metaphysical man; the relation between metaphysics and modernity, between encountering and conquering; egoism, subjectivity, and selfhood; man as zoon logon echon and as animal rationale; Heidegger’s reading of the cogito; representation as imposing the subject’s calculative, numeric, measures on the represented thing; modernity’s assumption that nature is configured in measures accessible to human understanding (mathesis universalis); the violence of representation: appropriation of the represented thing for the sake of affirming the representing thing (the subject); modern consciousness as reifying, as self-consciousness; representation and the I; modernity identifies Being with representedness; Heidegger’s reading of Protagoras’ ‘man is the measure’ dictum; Protagoras’ “measure” does not originate in man, but in belongingness to the aletheic space, which entails self-delimiting in line with Being; mindfulness and be-ing; two kinds of thinking; two kinds of consciousness; two kinds of man.

References

  1. Emad, Parvis. 2007. On the Way to Heidegger’s Contributions to Philosophy. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  2. Heidegger, Martin. 1971. “What Are Poets For?” In Poetry, Language, Thought, translated by Albert Hofstadter, 89–142. New York: Harper & Row. First composed 1946.Google Scholar
  3. Heidegger, Martin. 1982. Nihilism. Translated by Frank A. Capuzzy. Vol. 4 of Nietzsche, edited by David F. Krell. San Francisco: Harper & Row. First composed 1961.Google Scholar
  4. Heidegger, Martin. 1984. “Logos (Heraclitus, Fragment B 50).” In Early Greek Thinking, translated by David F. Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi, 59–78. San Francisco: Harper & Row. First composed 1951.Google Scholar
  5. Heidegger, Martin. 1992. Parmenides. Translated by André Schuwer and Richard Rojcewicz. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. First composed 1943.Google Scholar
  6. Heidegger, Martin. 1993a. Basic Concepts. Translated by Gary A. Aylesworth. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. First composed 1941.Google Scholar
  7. Heidegger, Martin. 1993b. “On the Essence of Truth,” translated by John Sallis. In Basic Writings, 115–38. New York: Harper & Row. First composed 1930.Google Scholar
  8. Heidegger, Martin. 1999. Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning). Translated by Parvis Emad and Kenneth Maly. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. First composed 1936–1938.Google Scholar
  9. Heidegger, Martin. 2000. Introduction to Metaphysics. Translated by Gregory Fried and Richard Polt. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. First composed 1935.Google Scholar
  10. Heidegger, Martin. 2006. Mindfulness. Translated by Parvis Emad and Thomas Kalary. London and New York: Continuum. First composed 1939.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Bezalel Academy of Art and DesignJerusalemIsrael

Personalised recommendations