Advertisement

Conventionalism Unchained and Sceptical. A Defence of a Quasi-Realist Account of Legal Statements Against Dworkin’s Criticisms

  • Federico José Arena
Chapter
Part of the Law and Philosophy Library book series (LAPS, volume 126)

Abstract

Dworkin famously argued that Hart’s practice theory is not able to give an account of legal duties and therefore that it is a bad theory of law. Conventions were then proposed as a substitute for the practice theory capable of showing the existence of legal duties. In this text Arena examines two different conventionalist strategies that have been proposed as answers to Dworkin’s criticisms—Marmor’s constitutive conventionalism and Postema’s constructive conventionalism. Arena claims that both proposals remain captive of Dworkin’s premises and that this has led them to overstate the cooperative dimension of legal practice. Dworkin’s argument is based on the premise that without explaining the existence of legal duties a theory would be unable to explain some essential features of law: judges’ statements of duty and disagreements. Arena argues against this premise by claiming, first, that judges’ statements of duty are just a projection of their attitudes both on the action considered mandatory or forbidden and on the conventional interpretative method they use to ground that statement. Second, that this projectivist perspective may account for judges’ talk in terms of truth value and for their disagreements. On the one hand, by following a quasi-realist schema, Arena claims that judges must earn their right to talk about truth and, on the other hand, he claims that judges’ disagreements are genuine disagreements in attitudes.

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Pierluigi Chiassoni and Dimitrios Kyritsis for their insights and comments on previous drafts of this paper.

References

  1. Arena FJ (2012) Antirrealismo moral vs. positivismo jurídico. Revista de Filosofía del derecho - Infojus 1(2):185–201Google Scholar
  2. Arena FJ (2013) Una alternativa para el escepticismo interpretativo: convenciones y cuasirrealismo en la interpretación jurídica. Doxa 36:417–438Google Scholar
  3. Bayón Mohino JC (2002a) El contenido mínimo del positivismo jurídico. In: Zapatero Gómez V (ed) Horizontes de la filosofía del derecho: homenaje a Luis García San Miguel, vol 2. Universidad de Alcalá de Henares, Alcalá de Henares, pp 33–54Google Scholar
  4. Bayón Mohino JC (2002b) Derecho, convencionalismo y controversia. In: Navarro PE, Redondo MC (eds) La relevancia del derecho. Gedisa, Barcelona, pp 57–92Google Scholar
  5. Blackburn S (1984) Spreading the word: groundings in the philosophy of language. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  6. Blackburn S (1998) Ruling passions. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  7. Blackburn S (2005) Quasi-realism no fictionalism. In: Kalderon ME (ed) Fictionalism in metaphysics. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 322–338Google Scholar
  8. Canale D, Tuzet G (2014) Intenzioni del legislatore e ragionamento controfattuale. Analisi e diritto, 195–209.Google Scholar
  9. Celano B (2005) Legal reasoning: three key issues, and what philosophy can(not) do about them. Analisi e diritto, 99–114Google Scholar
  10. Celano B (2010a) [1997] Interazione strategica e convenzione. In: Celano B Fatti istituzionali, consuetudini, convenzioni. Aracne, Roma, pp 281–322Google Scholar
  11. Celano B (2010b) [2003] La regola di riconoscimento è una convenzione?. In: Celano B Fatti istituzionali, consuetudini, convenzioni. Aracne, Roma, pp 323–341Google Scholar
  12. Celano B (2017) Due problemi aperti della Teoria dell'interpretazione giuridica. Mucchi editore, ModenaGoogle Scholar
  13. Chiassoni P (2000) Interpretative games: statutory construction through Gricean eyes. Analisi e diritto 1999:79–99Google Scholar
  14. Chiassoni P (2004) Codici interpretativi: Progetto di voce per un Vademecum giuridico. Analisi e diritto 2002–2003:55–124Google Scholar
  15. Chiassoni P (2007) Tecnica dell'interpretazione giuridica. Il Mulino, BolognaGoogle Scholar
  16. Coleman JL (1982) Negative and positive positivism. J Legal Stud 11(1):139–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Coleman JL (2001a) The conventionality thesis. Philos Issues 11(1):354–387CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Coleman JL (2001b) [1998] Incorporationism, conventionality and the practical difference thesis. In: Coleman JL (ed) Hart’s postscript. Essays on the postscript to “the concept of law”. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 99–148Google Scholar
  19. den Hartogh G (2002) Mutual expectations. A conventionalist theory of law. Kluwer, La HayaGoogle Scholar
  20. Dickson J (2007) Is the rule of recognition really a conventional rule? Oxf J Legal Stud 27(3):373–402CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Dworkin R (1978) Taking rights seriously. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  22. Dworkin R (1986) Law’s empire. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  23. Dworkin R (2011) Justice for hedgehogs. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  24. Dworkin R (2017) [1994] Hart’s posthumous reply. Harv Law Rev 130(8):2096–2130Google Scholar
  25. Gibbard A (2003) Thinking how to live. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  26. Green L (1999) Positivism and conventionalism. Can J Law Jurisprud 12(1):35–52CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Guastini R (2011) Rule scepticism restated. In: Green L, Leiter B (eds) Oxford studies in philosophy of law, vol 1. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 138–161CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Hart HLA (1994) [1961] The concept of law. In: Bulloch PA, Raz J (eds) 2nd edn. Clarendon Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  29. Jamieson D (1975) David Lewis on convention. Can J Philos 5:73–81CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Joyce R (2007) Moral Anti-realism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. <URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-anti-realism/>, Accessed 26 Aug 2015
  31. Kyritsis D (2008) What is good about legal conventionalism? Legal Theory 14(2):135–166CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Lagerspetz E (1995) The opposite mirrors. An essay on the conventionalist theory of institutions. Kluwer, DordrechtGoogle Scholar
  33. Lewis D (1969) Convention. A philosophical study. Basil Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  34. Lewis D (1976) Convention: reply to Jamieson. Can J Philos 6(1):113–120CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Mackie JL (1977) Ethics. Inventing right and wrong. Penguin, LondonGoogle Scholar
  36. Marmor A (2009) Social conventions. From language to law. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  37. Marmor A (2011) Conventions revisited: a reply to critics. Jurisprudence 2(2):493–506CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Marmor A (2014) Convenciones, razones y derecho. In: Ramírez Ludeña L, Vilajosana Rubio JM (eds) Convencionalismo y derecho. Marcial Pons, Madrid, pp 67–88Google Scholar
  39. Postema G (1982) Coordination and convention at the foundation of law. J Legal Stud 11(1):165–203CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Postema G (2011) In: A treatise of legal philosophy and general jurisprudence, vol 11: Legal philosophy in the twentieth century: the common law world. Springer, DordrechtCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Ratti GB (2008) Los desacuerdos jurídicos en la jurisprudence anglosajona. Analisi e diritto, 301–331Google Scholar
  42. Rawls J (1955) Two concepts of rules. Philos Rev 64(1):3–32CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Raz J (1990) [1975] Practical reason and norms. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  44. Ross A (1958) On law and justice. Stevens and Sons, LondonGoogle Scholar
  45. Ross A (1968) Directives and norms. Routledge and Keagan Paul, London. Cited by the Italian Translation by M Jori. Direttive e norme. Giuffrè, Milán, 1978Google Scholar
  46. Searle JR (1969) Speech acts. An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press, LondonCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Searle JR (1995) The construction of social reality. Free Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  48. Searle JR (2010) Making the social world. The structure of human civilization. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  49. Shapiro S (2007) The ‘Hart-Dworkin’ debate: a short guide for the perplexed. In: Ripstein A (ed) Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  50. Stevenson CL (1945) Ethics and language. Yale University Press, New HavenGoogle Scholar
  51. Swaminathan S (2014) Toh’s Hartian project: expressivist turn, relativist returns. Aust J Legal Philos 39:87–117Google Scholar
  52. Swaminathan S (2016) Projectivism and the metaethical foundation of the normativity of law. Jurisprudence 7(2):231–266CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Toh K (2005) Hart’s expressivism and his benthamite project. Legal Theory 11:75–123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Toh K (2011) Legal judgments as plural acceptance of norms. In: Green L, Leiter B (eds) Oxford studies in philosophy of law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 107–137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Vilajosana Rubio JM (2010) Una defensa del convencionalismo jurídico. Doxa 33:471–501CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Conicet (U.N.C.) – Universidad Blas PascalCórdobaArgentina

Personalised recommendations