Advertisement

Philosophical Naturalism and Scientific Method

  • Brian D. Haig
Chapter
Part of the Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics book series (SAPERE, volume 45)

Abstract

This chapter discusses of the nature of philosophical naturalism and its relation to scientific method. The discussion takes its cue from an interdisciplinary examination of the naturalization of the philosophy of mind by Kievit et al. (2011), who employ statistical methods to construct psychometric models of both the identity and supervenience theories of the mind-body relation. For the most part, the focus of the chapter is on methods of inquiry. After a brief discussion of two different attitudes to naturalized philosophy, two well-known views of naturalism in the philosophy of mind are presented and considered in relation to the naturalism of Kievit et al. Thereafter, some limitations of structural equation modelling, which is the authors’ method of choice, are noted, as is the useful but neglected method of inference to the best explanation. Philosophers and psychologists are encouraged to use one another’s methods, to the benefit of both.

References

  1. Barrett, P. (2007). Structural equation modelling: Adjudging model fit. Personality and Individual Differences, 42, 815–824.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  3. Bishop, M. A., & Trout, J. D. (2005). Epistemology and the psychology of human judgment. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Boyd, R. (1996). Realism, approximate truth, and philosophical method. In D. Papineau (Ed.), Philosophy of science (pp. 215–255). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Nola, R. (Eds.). (2009). Conceptual analysis and philosophical naturalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Capaldi, E. J., & Proctor, R. W. (2000). Laudan’s normative naturalism: A useful philosophy of science for psychology. American Journal of Psychology, 113, 430–454.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Churchland, P. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.Google Scholar
  8. Devitt, M. (2010). Putting metaphysics first: Essays on metaphysics and epistemology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Donovan, A., Laudan, L., & Laudan, R. (Eds.). (1988). Scrutinizing science: Empirical studies of scientific change. Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  10. Faust, D., & Meehl, P. E. (2002). Using meta-scientific studies to clarify or resolve questions in the philosophy and history of science. Philosophy of Science, 69(Suppl.), 185–196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Fletcher, G. (1995). The scientific credibility of folk psychology. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  12. Haig, B. D. (2009). Inference to the best explanation: A neglected approach to theory appraisal in psychology. American Journal of Psychology, 122, 219–234.PubMedGoogle Scholar
  13. Harré, R. (1983). History and philosophy of science in the pedagogical process. In R. W. Home (Ed.), Science under scrutiny (pp. 139–157). Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Hooker, C. A. (1987). A realistic theory of science. New York, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  15. Kaplan, D. (2000). Structural equation modeling: Foundations and extensions. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.Google Scholar
  16. Kievit, R. A., Romeijn, J.-W., Waldorp, L. J., Wicherts, J. M., Scholte, H. S., & Borsboom, D. (2011). Mind the gap: A psychometric approach to the reduction problem. Psychological Inquiry, 22, 67–87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Kim, J. (1988). What is naturalized epistemology? Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 381–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kitcher, P. (1992). The naturalists return. Philosophical Review, 100, 53–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Laudan, L. (1977). Progress and its problems: Towards a theory of scientific growth. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  20. Laudan, L. (1986). Progress or rationality? The prospects for normative naturalism. American Philosophical Quarterly, 24, 19–31.Google Scholar
  21. Laudan, L. (1996). Beyond positivism and relativism. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
  22. Laudan, L., Donovan, A., Laudan, R., Barker, P., Brown, H., Leplin, H., et al. (1986). Scientific change: Philosophical models and historical research. Synthese, 69, 141–223.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Lewis, D. (1983). Philosophical papers (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  24. Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). London, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
  25. Markus, K., Hawes, S. S., & Thasites, R. (2008). Abductive inference to psychological variables: Steiger’s question and best explanations in psychopathy. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 64, 1069–1088.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. McDonald, R. P. (2010). Structural models and the art of approximation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 675–686.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. McMullin, E. (1983). Values in science. In P. Asquith & T. Nickles (Eds.), Philosophy of Science Association 1982 (Vol. 2, pp. 3–25). East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  28. Meehl, P. E. (1992). Cliometric metatheory: The actuarial approach to empirical, history-based philosophy of science. Psychological Reports, 71, 339–467.Google Scholar
  29. Nolan, D. (2005). David Lewis. Chesham, England: Acumen.Google Scholar
  30. Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
  31. Quine, W. V. O. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Quine, W. V. O. (1981). Theories and things. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Rodgers, J. L., & Rowe, D. C. (2002). Theory development should begin (but not end) with good empirical fits: A comment on Roberts and Pashler (2000). Psychological Review, 109, 599–604.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Rosenberg, A. (1996). A field guide to recent species of naturalism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47, 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Rozeboom, W. W. (1977). Metathink—A radical alternative. Canadian Psychological Review, 18, 197–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Sytsma, J. (2010). The proper province of philosophy: Conceptual analysis and empirical investigation. Review of Philosophical Psychology, 1, 427–445.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual revolutions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PsychologyUniversity of CanterburyChristchurchNew Zealand

Personalised recommendations