Advertisement

Why a World State Is Unavoidable in Planetary Defense: On Loopholes in the Vision of a Cosmopolitan Governance

  • Pavel DufekEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Space and Society book series (SPSO)

Abstract

The main claim of this chapter is that planetary defense against asteroids cannot be implemented under a decentralized model of democratic global governance, as espoused elsewhere in this book. All relevant indices point to the necessity of establishing a centralized global political authority with legitimate coercive powers. It remains to be seen, however, whether such a political system can be in any recognizable sense democratic. It seems unconvincing that planetary-wide physical-threat, all-comprehensive macrosecuritization, coupled with deep transformations of international law, global centralization of core decision-making powers, de-stigmatization of nuclear weapons and the like can proceed, succeed, and be implemented in a non-hierarchical international system where planetary defense constitutes only one regime among many, and where states basically remain the decisive actors. Although rationally and scientifically robust, the project suffers from oversimplification, as well as naivety with respect to how both international and domestic politics works. Among other topics, this chapter discusses problems associated with the rule of law and constituent powers, political representation and sources of legitimacy, conditions of multilevel collective action, or limits of theoretical idealization. The general message is that the planetary defense community needs to be more aware of the social and political context of its own enterprise.

Keywords

Cosmopolitan governance World state Global macrosecuritization Democratic legitimacy Collective action Common identity 

Notes

Acknowledgments

The text is an output of a research project supported by the Czech Science Foundation (code GA16-13980S). I thank Nikola Schmidt for many suggestions regarding the shape of my argument, as well as for heated debates, both past and future, about real and imaginary limits to idealistic visions of global governance.

References

  1. Alter, K. J., & Meunier, S. (2009). The politics of international regime complexity. Perspectives on Politics, 7(1), 13–24. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592709090033CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Anzenbacher, A. (1998). Christliche Sozialethik: Einführung und Prinzipien. Paderborn: Ferdinand SchöningGoogle Scholar
  3. Arato, A. (2016). Post Sovereign Constitutional Making: Learning and Legitimacy. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  4. Avbelj, M., Fontanelli, F., & Martinico, G. (2014). Kadi on trial: a multifaceted analysis of the Kadi trial. Abingdon: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
  5. Barnett, M., & Finnemore, M. (1999). The politics, power, and pathologies of international organizations. International organization, 53(4), 699–732CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Barnett, M., & Finnemore, M. (2004). Rules of the World: International Organizations in Global Politics. Ithaca and London: Cornell University PressGoogle Scholar
  7. Belling, V. (2014). Exekutivní vládnutí jako nový model politiky v Evropské unii? Krizová politika EU a její dopady na politický systém. Mezinarodni Vztahy, 49(4), 9–27Google Scholar
  8. Bicchieri, C. (2006). The Grammar of Society: The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  9. Bláhová, S., & Dufek, P. (2018). Identita v liberální politické teorii a dilema kosmopolitismu. Filosofický časopis, 66(3 or 4 (Forthcoming))Google Scholar
  10. Buzan, B., & Waever, O. (2009). Macrosecuritization and security constellations: reconsidering scale in securitization theory. Review of International Studies, 35(April 2009), 253–276. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0260210509008511CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Caney, S. (2005). Justice Beyond Borders. A Global Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  12. Catherine, L. (2012). World Government. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosohy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/world-government/
  13. Craig, P. P., & Búrca, G. De. (2012). EU Law: Text, Cases, and Material (6th ed.). Oxford: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. De Búrca, G. (2010). The European court of Justice and the international legal order after Kadi. Harvard International Law Journal, 51(1), 1–49Google Scholar
  15. De Búrca, G., Keohane, R. O., & Sabel, C. (2014). Global experimentalist governance. British Journal of Political Science, 44(3), 477–486. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0007123414000076CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Drezner, D. W. (2009). The power and peril of international regime complexity. Perspectives on Politics, 7(1), 65–70. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1537592709090100CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Dufek, P. (2013). Why strong moral cosmopolitanism requires a world-state. International Theory, 5(02), 177–212. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/S1752971913000171CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Dufek, P. (2018). Lidská práva, ideologie a veřejné ospravedlnění: co obnáší brát pluralismus vážně. Právník, 157(1), 50–70Google Scholar
  19. Dufek, P., & Mochtak, M. (2017). A case for global democracy? Arms exports and conflicting goals in democracy promotion. Journal of International Relations and Development. doi: https://doi.org/10.1057/s41268-017-0114-0
  20. Floyd, R. (2011). Can Securitization Theory be Used in Normative Analysis? Towards a Just Securitization Theory. Security Dialogue, 42(4–5), 427–439. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0967010611418712CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Fuller, L. L. (1969). The Morality of Law (2nd ed.). New Heaven: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
  22. Gaus, G. (2008). On Philosophy, Politics, and Economics. Belmont: Thomson WadsworthGoogle Scholar
  23. Gaus, G. (2011). The Order of Public Reason: A Theory of Freedom and Morality in a Diverse and Bounded World. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  24. Gaus, G. (2017). The Open Society and Its Friends. The Critique, January 15. http://www.thecritique.com/articles/open-society-and-its-friends/
  25. Greene, J. (2013). Moral Tribes: Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Them and Us. New York: Penguin BooksGoogle Scholar
  26. Grimm, S., & Leininger, J. (2012). Not all good things go together: conflicting objectives in democracy promotion. Democratization, 19(3), 391–414. doi: https://doi.org/10.1080/13510347.2012.674355CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Habermas, J. (2008). A Political Constitution for a Pluralist World Society? In J. Habermas (Ed.), Between Naturalism and Religion: Philosophical Essays (pp. 312–352). Cambridge: Polity PressGoogle Scholar
  28. Habermas, J. (2011). Zur Verfassung Europas: Ein Essay. Berlin: SuhrkampGoogle Scholar
  29. Haidt, J. (2012). The Righteous Mind: Why Good People are Divided by Politics and Religion. New York: Pantheon BooksGoogle Scholar
  30. Hart, H. L. (1994). The Concept of Law (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon PressGoogle Scholar
  31. Held, D. (2010). Cosmopolitanism: Ideals and Realities. PolityGoogle Scholar
  32. Held, D. (2016). Elements of a theory of global governance. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 42(9), 837–846. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0191453716659520CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kumm, M. (2016). Constituent power, cosmopolitan constitutionalism, and post-positivist law. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 14(3), 697–711. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mow050CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. List, C., & Koenig-Archibugi, M. (2010). Can There Be a Global Demos? An Agency-Based Approach. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38(1), 76–110. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2009.01174.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Loghlin, M. (2010). The Foundations of Public Law. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  36. MacCormick, N. (1999). Questioning Sovereignty. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  37. Mayer, M., & Acuto, M. (2015). The Global Governance of Large Technical Systems. Millennium - Journal of International Studies, 43(2), 660–683. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0305829814561540CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Mulieri, A. (2013). Beyond Electoral Democracy? A Critical Assessment of Constructivist Representation in the Global Arena. Representation, 49(4), 515–527. doi: https://doi.org/10.1080/00344893.2013.846276CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Müller, J. W. (2009). Constitutional Patriotism. Princenton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
  40. Nili, S. (2015). Who’s afraid of a world state? A global sovereign and the statist-cosmopolitan debate. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 18(3), 241–263. doi: https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2013.850833CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Ondřejek, P. (2016). Státní moc a mezinárodní právo mezi nadřazeností a dialogem. In J. Kysela & P. Ondřejek (Eds.), Kolos na hliněných nohou? K proměnám srtátu a jeho rolí (pp. 101–129). Praha: LegesGoogle Scholar
  42. Palombella, G. (2009). The rule of law beyond the state: Failures, promises, and theory. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 7(3), 442–467. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mop012CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Patberg, M. (2016). Against democratic intergovernmentalism: The case for a theory of constituent power in the global realm. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 14(3), 622–638. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mow040CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Peters, A. (2009). Membership in the Global Constitutional Community. In J. Klabbers, A. Peters, & G. Ulfstein (Eds.), The constitutionalization of international law (pp. 153–178). Oxford: Oxford University PressCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Peters, A. (2015). Constitutional Fragments: On the Interaction of Constitutionalization and Fragmentation in International Law. CGC Working Paper, (No. 2), 1–42Google Scholar
  46. Pogge, T. (2008). World Poverty and Human Rights (2nd ed.). Cambridge: PolityGoogle Scholar
  47. Price, R. (2008). Moral limit and possibility in world politics. International Organization, 62(2), 191–220. doi: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020818308080132
  48. Rhodes, R. A. W. (1996). The New Governance: Governing without Government. Political Studies, 44(4), 652–667. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.1996.tb01747.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  49. Roe, P. (2012). Is securitization a ‘negative’ concept? Revisiting the normative debate over normal versus extraordinary politics. Security Dialogue, 43(3), 249–266. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0967010612443723CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Rosenau, J. (2006). Study of World Politics, Volume II: Globalization and Governance. Abingdon, UK: RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
  51. Rosenau, J., & Czempiel, O. (Eds.). (1992). Governance without Government: Order and Change in World Politics. Cambridge: Vambridge UPGoogle Scholar
  52. Rosenfeld, M. (2008). Rethinking constitutional ordering in an era of legal and ideological pluralism. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 6(3–4), 415–455. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mon023CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Saward, M. (2010). The Representative Claim. Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  54. Scheuerman, W. E. (2002). Cosmopolitan Democracy and the Rule of Law. Ratio Juris, 15(4), 439–457. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9337.00218CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Scheuerman, W. E. (2011). The Realist Case for Global Reform. Cambridge, UK: PolityGoogle Scholar
  56. Schmidt, N. (2018). The political desirability, feasibility, and sustainability of planetary defense governance. Acta Astronautica. doi: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.actaastro.2018.06.037
  57. Schmitt, C. (2011). Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. Chicago: University of Chicago PressGoogle Scholar
  58. Shapiro, I. (1999). Democratic Justice. Yale: Yale University PressGoogle Scholar
  59. Somek, A. (2012). Monism: A Tale of the Undead. In M. Avbelj & J. Komárek (Eds.), Constitutional Pluralism in the European Union and Beyond (pp. 343–380). Oxford: Hart PublishingGoogle Scholar
  60. Tajfel, H., Billig, M. G., Bundy, R. P., & Flament, C. (1971). Social categorization and intergroup behaviour. European Journal of Social Psychology, 1(2), 149–178. doi: https://doi.org/10.1002/ejsp.2420010202CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  61. Tamanaha, B. (2004). On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University PressGoogle Scholar
  62. Wæver, O. (2011). Politics, security, theory. Security Dialogue, 42(4–5), 465–480. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0967010611418718CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Walker, N. (2008). Beyond boundary disputes and basic grids: Mapping the global disorder of normative orders. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 6(3–4), 373–396. doi: https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/mon016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Weiss, T. G., & Wilkinson, R. (2014). Rethinking Global Governance? Complexity, Authority, Power, Change. International Studies Quarterly, 58(1), 207–215. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/isqu.12082CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Wendt, A. (2003). Why a World State is Inevitable. European Journal of International Relations, 9(4), 491–542. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/135406610394001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Wendt, A. (2011). Why a World State is Inevitable. In L. Cabrera (Ed.), Global Governance, Global Government. International Visions for an Evolving World System (pp. 27–63). Albany: SUNY PressGoogle Scholar
  67. Ypi, L. (2008). Statist cosmopolitanism. Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(1), 48–71. doi: https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2008.00308.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  68. Ypi, L. (2012). Global Justice and Avant-Garde Political Agency. Oxford: Oxford University PressGoogle Scholar
  69. Zolo, D. (2007). The Rule of Law: A Critical Reappraisal. In P. Costa & D. Zolo (Eds.), The Rule of Law: History, Theory and Criticism (p. 24). Dordrecht: SpringerCrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Political Science, Faculty of Social StudiesMasaryk UniversityBrnoCzech Republic

Personalised recommendations