Advertisement

Descriptions in Use

  • Paolo LeonardiEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology book series (PEPRPHPS, volume 20)

Abstract

For more than 50 years now, Donnellan’s distinction between referential and attributive descriptions has been discussed, criticized, supported and considered from many points of view. The facts have largely been agreed upon but the debate still revolves around how to account for them, especially for referring by a misdescription, i.e., a description that does not fit what it is being used to refer to, for example when I refer to the man near the window as the man drinking a martini, whereas he has a tonic water. Here, I offer a reconstruction of the issue and sketch a meaning as use framework (in fact, Donnellan distinguishes two uses of descriptions), within which I discuss an account for referential descriptions, including apparent ones. Before closing, I put forward a unitary account of the two uses of a description, whereby the descriptive condition is always relevant, while denying that a description in referential use operates in the same way as a proper name.

References

  1. J. Almog 2012 Referential uses and the foundations of direct reference (in Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds New York/Oxford Oxford UP: 176–184).Google Scholar
  2. J. Almog 2014 Refential mechanism (New York/Oxford Oxford UP).Google Scholar
  3. J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds 2012 Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan (New York/Oxford Oxford UP).Google Scholar
  4. Augustine 397–400 Confessions (Eng tr. by J.K. Ryan New York Image Books 1960).Google Scholar
  5. E. Bach 1968 Nouns and Noun Phrases (Universals in Linguistic Theory E. Bach and R.T. Harms eds New York 1968:. 91–122).Google Scholar
  6. J.M. Bell 1973 What is referential opacity? (Journal of Philosophical Logic 2: 155–80).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. C. Beyer 2001 A neo-Husserlian theory of speaker’s reference (Erkenntnis Google Scholar
  8. A. Bezuidenhout 2013 “The (in)significance of the referential-attributive distinction” (in Perspectives on Pragmatics and Philosophy A. Capone, M. Carapezza, F. Lo Piparo eds Berlin Springer).Google Scholar
  9. A. Capuano 2012 The ground zero of semnatics (in Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds New York/Oxford Oxford UP: 7–29).Google Scholar
  10. H.-N. Castañeda 1977 On the philosophical foundations of the theory of communication: reference (in Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, French, Uehling, and Wettstein eds, Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press:125–143).Google Scholar
  11. G. Cinque 2008 Two types of non-restrictive relatives (Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics O. Bonami & P. Cabredo Hofherr eds 7:. 99–137).Google Scholar
  12. D. Davidson 1986 A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs (in Philosophical Grounds of Rationality/Intentions, Categories, Ends (R. Grandy and R. Warner eds. Oxford Clarendon, pp. 157–74).Google Scholar
  13. M. Devitt 1974 Singular terms (The Journal of Philosophy 71: 183–205).Google Scholar
  14. M. Devitt 1981 Donnellan distinction (Midwest Studies in Philosophy 6 (1):511–526).Google Scholar
  15. M. Devitt 2004 The Case for Referential Descriptions (in Descriptions and Beyond M. Reimer & A Bezuidenhout eds., Oxford at the UP, pp. 280–305).Google Scholar
  16. M. Devitt 2013 Three Methodological Flaws of Linguistic Pragmatism (in What is Said and What is Not. F. Domaneschi and C. Penco eds Stanford CSLI Publication: 285–300).Google Scholar
  17. K. Donnellan 1963 “Knowing What I Am Doing” (The Journal of Philosophy 60: 401–9).Google Scholar
  18. K. Donnellan 1966 Reference and Definite Descriptions (The Philosophical Review 75: 281–304).Google Scholar
  19. K. Donnellan 1968 Putting Humpty Dumpty Together Again (The Philosophical Review 77: 203–15).Google Scholar
  20. K. Donnellan 1978 Speaker Reference, Descriptions, and Anaphora (in Syntax and Semantics 9: Pragmatics P. Cole ed., New York Academic Press, pp. 47–68; reprinted in Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol. II Contemporary Philosophy of Language, rev. ed. 1979, pp. 28–43).Google Scholar
  21. G. Evans 1982 Varieties of reference (Oxford )Google Scholar
  22. P. Grice 1957 Meaning (The Philosophical Review 66: 377–388).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. P. Grice 1989 Studies in the way of words (Cambridge MA Harvard UP).Google Scholar
  24. P. Horwich 1998 Meaning (Oxford Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
  25. P. Horwich 2005 Reflections on Meaning (Oxford Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
  26. P. Horwich 2012 Wittgenstein’s Metaphilosophy (New York Oxford UP).Google Scholar
  27. E. Husserl 1987 Husserliana – Edmund Husserl: Gesammelte Werke 26 : Vorlesungen über Bedeutungslehre. Sommersemester 1908 [Lectures on the doctrine of meaning: summer semester 1908.] U. Panzer ed (The Hague Nijhoff).Google Scholar
  28. D. Kaplan 2012 Having in mind (in Having in mind/The philosophy of Keith Donnellan J. Almog & P. Leonardi eds New York/Oxford Oxford UP: 122–175).Google Scholar
  29. S. Kripke [1972] 1980 Naming and Necessity (in Semantics of Natural Language D. Davidson & G. Harman eds. Dordrecht: Reidel) pp. 253–355, 763–769 (reprinted in book format with added a Preface Oxford Blackwell 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. S. Kripke [1973] 2013 Reference and Existence/The John Locke Lectures [1973] (Oxford/New York Oxford UP).Google Scholar
  31. S. Kripke 1977 Speaker Reference and Semantic Reference (in Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, French, Uehling, and Wettstein eds, Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press: 6–27).Google Scholar
  32. G. Leech, M. Hundt, C. Mair, and N. Smith 2009 Change in contemporary English/A grammatical study (Cambridge Cambridge UP).Google Scholar
  33. P. Ludlow and S. Neale 2006 ‘Descriptions’ (in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language M. Devitt ed Oxford Blackwell: 288–313).Google Scholar
  34. G. Martí 2008 Direct reference and definite descriptions (Dialectica 62: 43–57).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. S. Neale 1990 Descriptions (Cambridge MA Mit Press).Google Scholar
  36. S. Neale 2004 This, that, and the other (in Descriptions and Beyond M. Reimer & A Bezuidenhout eds., Oxford at the UP, pp. 68–182).Google Scholar
  37. F. Orilia 2009 Singular reference/A descriptivist perspective (Dordrecht Springer).Google Scholar
  38. C. Penco 2017 Donnellan’s misdescriptions and loose talk (In Reference and Representation in Language and Thought K. Korta and M. De Ponte eds Oxford Oxford UP: pp. 104–125).
  39. F. Recanati 2013 Reference through mental files (in What is said and what is not F. Domaneschi and C. Penco eds Stanford CSLI Publications: 159–173).Google Scholar
  40. M. Reimer 1998 Donnellan’s Distinction/Kripke’s Test (Analysis 58: 89–100).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. B. Russell 1905 On denoting (Mind 14: 479–493).Google Scholar
  42. J.R. Searle 1979 Referential and attributive (The Monist 62: 190–208).Google Scholar
  43. H.A. Simon 19963 The sciences of the artificial (Cambridge MA MIT Press).Google Scholar
  44. D. Sperber and M. Wilson 1986 Relevance/Communication and cognition (Oxford Blackwell).Google Scholar
  45. P.F. Strawson 1950 On referring (Mind 59: 320–344).Google Scholar
  46. R. L. Trask 2009 Why do languages change? (Cambridge Cambridge UP).Google Scholar
  47. A.N. Whitehead 1920 The concept of nature (Cambridge Cambridge UP)Google Scholar
  48. L. Wittgenstein 1953 [20094] Philosophischen Untersuchungen/Philosophical Investigations (Engl. tr. by G.E.M. Anscombe, P.M.S. Hacker and J. Schulte eds. Oxford Blackwell/Wiley).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2019

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Università di BolognaBolognaItaly

Personalised recommendations