Advertisement

Extrinsic Denomination and the Origins of Early Modern Metaphysics: The Scholastic Context of Descartes’s Regulae

  • Tarek R. DikaEmail author
Chapter
Part of the Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action book series (HSNA, volume 7)

Abstract

An assessment of Descartes’s relation to his Aristotelian contemporaries in his Regulae ad directionem ingenii—and more specifically his relation to the theory of scientific habitus—has never been undertaken and is long overdue. Despite broad scholarly consensus that Descartes rejected the scholastic theory of scientific habitus in the Regulae, I will show that, in fact, he redefines a centuries-old scholastic debate about the unity of science, and that he does so by employing, not rejecting, the concept of scientific habitus. For Descartes, the sciences are collectively one in virtue of a habitus which inclines the intellect to regard all things, not as they are in reality, but rather as they are relative to the intellect alone. Descartes establishes the unity of science via what Suárez refers to as “extrinsic denomination” in Disputationes metaphysicae 44.11.64. This creates a serious problem. As he no doubt knew and as Suárez would have rightly pointed out, the extrinsic denominations that Descartes employs in the Regulae have no ontological basis in the things denominated. Descartes’s method creates, arguably for the first time, a chasm between how things can be known by the intellect and how they are in reality—i.e., between “epistemology” and “ontology”—that motivates him to pursue metaphysics after the Regulae.

Keywords

Descartes Method Habitus Extrinsic denomination Metaphysics 

References

Primary Literature

  1. Conimbricenses. 1607. Commentarii in universam dialecticam Aristotelis Stagiritae. Cologne.Google Scholar
  2. Francisco Suárez. 1965. Disputationes metaphysicae, 2 vols. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
  3. John Duns Scotus. 1997. Questions on the Metaphysics of Aristotle. Trans. Girard J. Etzkorn and Allan B. Wolter. 2 vols. St. Bonaventure: Franciscan Institute.Google Scholar
  4. ———. 1998. Opera omnia: editio minor, ed. Giovanni Lauriola. Alberrobello: ABA.Google Scholar
  5. René Descartes. 1985–1991. The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, ed. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch, and Anthony Kenny. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  6. ———. 1996. Œuvres de Descartes, 11 vols, ed. Charles Adam and Paul Tannery. 11 vols. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  7. Thomas Aquinas. 1888–1896. Summa theologiae, ed. Commissio Leonina. 9 vols. Opera Omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita 4–12. Rome: Ex Typographia Polyglotta.Google Scholar
  8. ———. 1963. The Division and Methods of the Sciences: Questions V and VI of His Commentary on the De Trinitate of Boethius. Trans. Armand A. Maurer. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.Google Scholar
  9. ———. 1992. Super Boetium De Trinitate, ed. Commissio Leonina. Opera Omnia iussu Leonis XIII P. M. edita 50. Rome: Commissio Leonina; Paris: Éditions du Cerf.Google Scholar
  10. ———. 1997. Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, 2 vols. Trans. Anton C. Pegis. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.Google Scholar
  11. William Ockham. 1967–1988. Guillelmi de Ockham opera philosophica et theologica, ed. Gedeon Gál et al. 17 vols. St. Bonaventure: Franciscan Institute.Google Scholar
  12. ———. 1990. Philosophical Writings: A Selection. Trans. Philotheus Boehner and Stephen F. Brown. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar

Secondary Literature

  1. Ariew, Roger. 1990. Christopher Clavius and the classification of the sciences. Synthese 83 (2): 293–300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beck, John Leslie. 1952. The Method of Descartes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  3. Chenu, Marie Dominique. 1957. La théologie comme science au XIIIe siècle. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  4. Courtine, François. 1990. Suárez et le système de la métaphysique. Paris: Vrin.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Darge, Rolf. 2015. Suárez on the subject of metaphysics. In A Companion to Francisco Suárez, ed. Victor M. Salas and Robert L. Fastiggi, 91–123. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  6. Demange, Dominique. 2004. Objet premier d’inclusion virtuelle: Introduction à la théorie de la science de Jean Duns Scot. In Duns Scot à Paris (1302–2002), ed. Olivier Boulnois, Elizabeth Karger, Jean-Luc Solère, and Gérard Sondag, 89–116. Turnhout: Brepols.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. ———. 2009a. La théologie est-elle une science? La réponse de Duns Scot à Godefroid de Fontaines dans le prologue des Reportata Parisiensia. Documenti e studi sulla tradizione filosofica medievale 20: 547–572.Google Scholar
  8. ———. 2009b. Structure et unité de la science selon Duns Scot. Itinerarium 55: 329–356.Google Scholar
  9. Doyle, John. 1984. Prolegomena to a study of extrinsic denomination in the work of Francisco Suárez, S.J. Vivarium 22 (2): 121–156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. ———. 1991. Suárez on the unity of a scientific habit. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 63 (3): 311–334.Google Scholar
  11. ———. 1997. Between transcendental and transcendental: The missing link? The Review of Metaphysics 50: 783–815.Google Scholar
  12. Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes’ Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  13. ———. 2001. Descartes Embodied: Reading Cartesian Philosophy Through Cartesian Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Garber, Daniel, and Sophie Roux, eds. 2013. The Mechanization of Natural Philosophy. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  15. Gauvin, Jean-François. 2011. Instruments of knowledge. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy in Early Modern Europe, ed. Desmonde M. Clarke and Catherine Wilson, 315–388. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Gracia, Jorge. 1991. Suárez’s conception of metaphysics: A step in the direction of mentalism? American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 65 (3): 287–309.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. ———. 1993. Suárez and metaphysical mentalism. American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 67 (2): 349–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Heidegger, Martin. 1967. What is a thing? Trans. W.B. Barton, Jr. and Vera Deutsch. South Bend: Gateway Editions.Google Scholar
  19. Kambouchner, Denis. 2009. Descartes et le problème de la doctrine. In Vera Doctrina: Zur Begriffsgeschichte der Lehre von Augustinus bis Descartes, ed. Philippe Büttgen, Ruedi Imbach, and U.J. Schneider, 365–379. Wiesbaden: Harrassowitz.Google Scholar
  20. ———. 2016. Methodical invention: Cartesian ingenium at work. UnpublishedGoogle Scholar
  21. Livesey, Steven J. 1982. Metabasis: The Interrelationship of the Sciences in Antiquity and the Middle Ages. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
  22. Marion, Jean-Luc. 1975. Sur l’ontologie grise de Descartes: Science cartésienne et savoir aristotélicien dans les Regulae. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  23. Maurer, Armand A. 1958. Ockham’s conception of the unity of science. Mediaeval Studies 20: 98–112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. ———. 1974. The unity of a science: St. Thomas and the nominalists. In St. Thomas Aquinas 1274–1974: Commemorative Studies, ed. Armand A. Maurer, 269–291. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies.Google Scholar
  25. McKirahan, Richard. 1992. Principles and Proofs: Aristotle’s Theory of Demonstrative Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Miralbell-Guerin, Ignacio. 1990. Rational science and real science in William of Ockham (an introduction to Ockham’s philosophy of science). In Knowledge and the Sciences in Medieval Philosophy: Proceedings of the Eighth International Congress of Medieval Philosophy (S.I.E.P.M.), Helsinki 24–29 August 1987, ed. Reijo Työrinoja, vol. 3, 134–143. Helsinki: Annals of the Finnish Society for Missiology and Ecumenics.Google Scholar
  27. Pelletier, Jenny E. 2013. William Ockham on Metaphysics: The Science of Being and God. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
  28. Perini-Santos, E. 2006. La théorie ockhamienne de la connaissance evidente. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  29. Schuster, John. 2013. Descartes-Agonistes: Physico-Mathematics, Method, & Corpuscular-Mechanism, 1618–33. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Shapin, Steven. 1996. The Scientific Revolution. Chicago: Chicago University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Van Berkel, Klaas. 2013. Isaac Beeckman on Matter and Motion: Mechanical Philosophy in the Making. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Volpi, Franco. 1993. Suárez et le problème de la métaphysique. Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 3: 396–411.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2018

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.University of Notre DameNotre DameUSA

Personalised recommendations