Skip to main content

The Metaphysics of Identity in Fazang’s Huayan Wujiao Zhang: The Inexhaustible Freedom of Dependent Origination

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Dao Companion to Chinese Buddhist Philosophy

Part of the book series: Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy ((DCCP,volume 9))

Abstract

Fazang’s arguments in his Treatise on the Five Teachings of Huayan provide a philosophical foundation for the Avatamsaka Sutra’s rich and suggestive imagery. This chapter focuses on one of Fazang’s central arguments in that treatise, namely, his argument that mutually reliant dharmas are mutually identical. The chapter presents the background context for Fazang’s argument, reconstructs the argument’s logical structure, interprets the central concepts appearing therein, and explains why Fazang might have found plausible his argument’s premises. Specific discussion points include: the non-duality of existence and emptiness; relations between causes and their conditions; the meaning of creation and identity; connections with the ti-yong paradigm; Fazang’s analogy of the ten coins. The chapter concludes by considering the implications of Fazang’s metaphysics for contemporary discussions of substance and ontological foundations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Chan, Wing-tsit, ed. and trans. 1963. A Source Book in Chinese Philosophy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Garma C.C. 1971. The Buddhist Teaching of Totality: The Philosophy of Hwa Yen Buddhism. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Jinhua. 2007. Philosopher, Practitioner, Politician: The Many Lives of Fazang (643–712). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleary, Thomas. 1983. Entry Into the Inconceivable: An Introduction to Hua-yen Buddhism. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cleary, Thomas. trans. 1993. The Flower Ornament Scripture: A Translation of The Avatamsaka Sutra. Boston: Shambhala.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cho, Sungtaek. 2002. “The Rationalist Tendency in Modern Buddhist Scholarship: A Revaluation.” Philosophy East and West 52.4: 426–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, Francis. 1970. Fa-tsang’s Treatise on the Five Doctrines: An Annotated Translation. Ph.D. Dissertation. University of Wisconsin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, Francis. 1977. Hua-yen Buddhism: The Jewel Net of Indra. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, Francis. 1979. “Causation in the Chinese Hua-yen Tradition,” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 6.4: 367–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahy, Gregory M. 2012. “Huayan Buddhism and Dewey: Emptiness, Compassion, and the Philosophical Fallacy.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 39.2: 260–271.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fazang 法藏. Huayan Jing Tanxuan Ji 華嚴經探玄記 (Account of Investigating the Mysteries of the Avatamsaka Sutra). T 35, 1733.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Dasheng Qixin Lun Yiji 大乘起信論義記 (Commentary on the Awakening of Mahāyāna Faith). T 44, 1846.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Huayan Wujiao Zhang 華嚴五教章 (Treatise on the Five Teachings of Huayan). T 45, 1866.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. Jin Shizi Zhang 金獅子章 (Treatise on the Golden Lion). T 45, 1881.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fung, Yu-lan. 1983. A History of Chinese Philosophy. Vol. II. Trans. by Derk Bodde. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, Jay L. 1994. “Dependent Arising and the Emptiness of Emptiness: Why Did Nagarjuna Start With Causation?” Philosophy East and West 44.2: 219–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, John. 2012. The Universe as We Find It. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hershock, Peter. 2013. “Diversity Matters: Buddhist Reflections on the Meaning of Difference.” In Steven M. Emmanuel, ed. A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 675–692.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jiang, Tao. 2001. “The Problematic of Whole-Part and the Horizon of Enlightenment in Huayan Buddhism.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 28.4: 457–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Nicholaos. 2009. “Fazang’s Total Power Mereology: An Interpretive Analytic Reconstruction.” Asian Philosophy 19.2: 199–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Nicholaos. 2010a. “Mereological Heuristics for Huayan Buddhism.” Philosophy East and West 60.3: 355–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Nicholaos. 2010b. “Nyāya-Vaiśesika Inherence, Buddhist Reduction, and Huayan Total Power.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 37.2: 215–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalupahana, David J. 1986. Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, Winston L. 1979. “Hua-yen Mutually Interpenetrative Identity and Whiteheadean Organic Relation.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 6.4: 387–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, Sallie B. 1997. “The Doctrine of Buddha-Nature Is Impeccably Buddhist.” In Pruning the Bodhi Tree: The Storm Over Critical Buddhism, ed., by Jamie Hubbard. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 174–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kong, Roberta Lion. 1979. “Metaphysics and East-West Philosophy: Applying the Chinese T’i-Yung Paradigm.” Philosophy East and West 29.1: 49–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koseki, Aaron K. 1982. “‘Later Mādhyamika’ in China: Some Current Perspectives on the History of Prajnāpāramitā Thought.” The Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 5.2: 53–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Jeeloo. 2006. An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Ming-wood. 1979. The Teaching of Fa-Tsang: An Examination of Buddhist Metaphysics. Ph.D. Dissertation. University of California, Los Angeles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Ming-wood. 1982. “The Harmonious Universe of Fa-tsang and Leibniz: A Comparative Study.” Philosophy East and West 32.1: 61–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Ming-wood. 1994. Madhyamaka Thought in China. New York: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E.J. 1994. “Primitive Substances.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54.3: 531–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, A. Charles. 1996. “The Composition of Self-Transformation Thought in Classical East Asian Philosophy and Religion,” Bulletin of Toyo Gakuen University 4: 141–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller, A. Charles. 1999. “Essence-Function and Interpenetration: Early Chinese Origins and Manifestations.” Bulletin of Toyo Gakuen University 7: 93–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odin, Steve. 1982. Process Metaphysics and Hua-yen Buddhism: A Critical Study of Cumulative Penetration vs Interpenetration. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oh, Kang Nam. 1976. A Study of Chinese Hua-yen Buddhism With Special Reference to the Dharmadhātu (Fa-Chieh) Doctrine. Ph.D. Dissertation. McMaster University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, Jin Y. 2008. Buddhism and Postmodernity: Zen, Huayan, and the Possibility of Buddhist Postmodern Ethics. New York: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Park, Sung-bae. 1993. Buddhist Faith and Sudden Enlightenment. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, Graham. 2009. “The Structure of Emptiness.” Philosophy East and West 59.4: 467–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, Michael. 2013. “Analytic Theology: Précis.” Journal of the American Academy of Religions 81.3: 573–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ronkin, Noa. 2005. Early Buddhist Metaphysics: The Making of a Philosophical Tradition. New York: RoutledgeCurzon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, Jonathan. 2010. “Monism: The Priority of the Whole.” Philosophical Review 119: 31–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shih, Chang-Qing. 2004. The Two Truths in Chinese Buddhism. Delhi: Motilal Bonarsidass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suh, Jung-hyung. 1997. Taoist Impact on Hua-yen Buddhism: A Study of the Formation of the Hua-yen World View. Ph.D. Dissertation. University of Wisconsin-Madison.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vorenkamp, Dirck. 2004. “Evil, the Bodhisattva Doctrine, and Faith in Chinese Buddhism: Examining Fa Zang’s Three Tests.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 31.2: 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, Youru. 2003. Linguistic Strategies in Daoist Zhuangzi and Chan Buddhism: The Other Way of Speaking. New York: RoutledgeCurzon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Dale S. 1982. “The Significance of Paradoxical Language in Hua-yen Buddhism,” Philosophy East and West 32.3: 325–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, Dainian. 2002. Key Concepts in Chinese Philosophy. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, Michael. 2002. A Buddha Within: The Tathāgatagarbha Sūtra: The Earliest Exposition of the Buddha-Nature Teaching in India. Tokyo: International Research Institute for Advanced Buddhology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziporyn, Brook. 2003. “Li (Principle, Coherence) in Chinese Buddhism.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 30.3–4: 501–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Youru Wang and Ryan Jordan for helpful comments on prior versions of this chapter.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicholaos Jones .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Notes on Methodology

Appendix: Notes on Methodology

Several kinds of English-language scholarship examine Fazang’s claims about mutual identity. Some are expository, focused on paraphrasing claims, reorganizing argument presentation, and adding illustrative examples (see Cook 1977 and Cleary 1983). Others are comparative, contrasting Fazang’s claims with similar theses from other philosophical traditions and cultural contexts (King 1979 and Fahy 2012). Some are heuristic, providing warrants for Fazang’s claims without regard for their textual basis (see Jones 2009 and Jones 2010a). Others are anachronistic, interpreting Fazang’s claims with distinctively modern resources such as set theory or Jungian psychology (see Priest 2009 and Odin 1982). Some, finally, mystify Fazang, taking his use of paradoxical-sounding language to indicate an embrace of genuine contradictions (see Wright 1982).

This chapter’s approach to reconstruction and interpretation differs from each of these efforts in (at least one of) four ways. First, it is charitable rather than mystifying: it presumes that Fazang does not endorse contradictory claims. Second, it is historically sensitive rather than anachronistic, restricted to principles and warrants with which Fazang likely would have been familiar. Third, it is textually grounded rather than heuristic, focused on claims and arguments as they actually appear in Fazang’s writings. Fourth and finally, it is analytic rather than expository or comparative, honoring four prescriptions for rhetorical style:

  1. 1.

    Presume that claims admit of adequate formulation in logically manipulable sentences.

  2. 2.

    Prioritize precision, clarity, and logical coherence.

  3. 3.

    Avoid substantive use of metaphor and other devices the propositional content of which outstrips their semantic content.

  4. 4.

    Work with well-understood primitive concepts, and concepts analyzable with reference thereto (Rea 2013: 574).

In this chapter, respecting these prescriptions involves interpreting central concepts, identifying warrants and missing premises, reconstructing argument structure, and explaining inferential transitions within arguments.

Analytic reconstructions have their limitations. For example, they risk obscuring narrative insights, weakening metaphorical content for methodological rather than substantial reasons, and rationalizing the ineffable (see Cho 2002). In some cases – perhaps including this chapter – they also place high demands on reader attention. Perhaps such costs are less important in a philosophical context than they would be in a context oriented toward theology, praxis, or aesthetics. In any case, shouldering them makes possible several benefits: analytic reconstructions enhance cross-cultural understanding by restricting themselves to propositional contents the meaning of which do not depend upon specific experiences or practices; they help to reveal the extent to which semantic contents are irreducibly non-propositional; and, by virtue of their style being familiar and popular among contemporary European and Anglo-American philosophers, they make philosophy from non-European cultures and traditions more accessible.

This chapter displays many of these benefits. Consider, first, the reconstruction of the logical structure of Fazang’s argument (Sect. 13.3). The reconstructed argument is logically valid: each subargument’s conclusion follows from respective premises in accordance with familiar and well-understood rules of good deductive reasoning. In this respect, the reconstruction improves upon Cook’s analysis, which relies heavily upon examples and metaphors (Cook 1977: 64–66); and it improves upon Liu’s analysis, which inverts the inferential relations between Fazang’s premises and conclusions (Liu 1979: 407–409). Moreover, no premise in the reconstruction is prima-facie self-contradictory and the premise set taken together is jointly consistent. In this respect, the reconstruction improves upon Wright’s approach, which presumes that Fazang “violates the logical rule of non-contradiction” (Wright 1982: 325). Finally, each premise in the reconstructed argument is semantically precise. In this respect, the reconstruction improves upon Park’s analysis, which relies heavily upon examples and unexplicated technical concepts (Park 2008: 164–166).

Consider, next, the interpretation of the content of Fazang’s argument (Sect. 13.4). It avoids appealing to metaphors such as merging (Chang 1971: 139) and inside/outside (Ziporyn 2003: 508). It avoids “scare-quoting” concepts (see Ziporyn 2003: 509). It also relies upon a small set of primitive concepts (such as determination) and illustrates those concepts with several intuitive examples. Further, the interpretation recognizes that Fazang relativizes property possession to specific respects (Sects. 13.3.1 and 13.4.2). This departs from several other analyses (such as Cook 1970 and Liu 1979). While Ziporyn adopts a similar approach, this interpretation departs from Ziporyn’s by identifying the respects as presentations rather than times, subjective perspectives (how “we happen to be viewing”), or some combination thereof (see Ziporyn 2003: 508). In doing so, the interpretation shows that certain criticisms of Fazang’s argument – for example, that if Fazang is correct, the others cannot be identical with A because the others do not exist when A exists and yet identity requires that each relatum exists – are misplaced (see Ziporyn 2003: 509–510). Moreover, the interpretation identifies relatively precise, clear, and logically manipulable principles that support Fazang’s reasoning. This differs from analyses that take Fazang’s reasoning to be based upon a vague “ideal of the round” (see Liu 1979: 217–219; Liu 1982: 62, 65, 69; Jones 2010b: 227). It also reveals that Cook’s analysis, according to which mutual identity among dharmas follows from their common emptiness, is only partially correct (see Cook 1977: 373). For although each dharma’s emptiness entails that dharma’s creation by and identity with others relative to the same presentation as well as its creation and identifying of those others relative to another presentation, these entailments obtain only by virtue of the ti-yong paradigm (Sect. 13.4.3). Finally, because the interpretation points toward foundational presumptions of Fazang’s reasoning (Sect. 13.5.1), it makes Fazang’s metaphysics accessible and relevant to contemporary Anglo-American metaphysicians (see Sect. 13.6.2).

These benefits do not, of course, establish this chapter’s methodology as superior to alternatives. The chapter does not address soteriological issues, such as the way in which Fazang’s choice of language might help to induce particular experiential states or the way in which his conclusions might illuminate or rationalize particular Buddhist practices (see Wright 1982). Nor does it contextualize Fazang’s argument relative to other Buddhist traditions (see Liu 1979). Nor does it reveal the way in which Fazang’s doctrine of mutual identity through different essence coheres with his other distinctive metaphysical theses (see Cook 1977). However, the chapter’s benefits provide good prima-facie reason to suppose that the underlying methodology is appropriate and legitimate for facilitating cross-cultural understanding and engagement.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature B.V.

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Jones, N. (2018). The Metaphysics of Identity in Fazang’s Huayan Wujiao Zhang: The Inexhaustible Freedom of Dependent Origination. In: Wang, Y., Wawrytko, S. (eds) Dao Companion to Chinese Buddhist Philosophy. Dao Companions to Chinese Philosophy, vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-2939-3_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics