Skip to main content

Coquetting with Dialectics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 511 Accesses

Part of the book series: Marx, Engels, and Marxisms ((MAENMA))

Abstract

Many have attributed a unique and uniquely successful methodology of dialectics to Marx. Others regard dialectics as a disaster of obscurity and confusion, if not meaninglessness. Many now hold that Engels foisted a rigid “formalization” of dialectics on Marx’s work, and yet Marx coquetted with dialectics making positive references here and there. Analytical Marxists have almost universally rejected dialectics in Marxism, turning to clear analyses instead. This chapter, from a perspective of analytical philosophy, begins with an analysis of Marx’s own methodology and then contests some core claims about methodology by analytical Marxists, with primary focus on philosophical questions about methodological individualism and about mechanisms. With a more open understanding, one can see the plausibility for Marx, and Marxists, to coquette with dialectics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For a general discussion of dialectics, see Roy Bhaskar, Dialectic in Bottomore (1991, pp. 143–150) and Wilde (1991).

  2. 2.

    A good place to begin in understanding Marx’s relation to Hegel is Norman Levine (2012, with an extensive bibliography), Wilde (1991), and Bhaskar, Dialectic in Bottomore (1991).

  3. 3.

    Engels was the one who wrote extensively on Hegel’s dialectic, and, like Marx, he was “no longer a Hegelian,” but he held “a deep feeling of piety and devotion for the titanic old fellow” (Engels to Lange, 29 March 1865; MECW 42, p. 138).

  4. 4.

    This seems to be a rather different view of Marx’s method than Carver suggests in a focus on Engels with such ideas, but I think Marx’s comments are clear about what he was doing. See Carver (1983, pp. 96–117), where he concludes that Engels “invented [Marxist] dialectics” (p. 117). My focus is on Marx, and I mention Engels’ work for confirmation or clarification of what Marx said.

  5. 5.

    For a discussion of a more extensive use of Hegel by Marx, see Uchida , who claims that the “ Grundrisse is the most suitable text for studying the relation of [Marx’s] critique of political economy to [Hegel’s ] Logic” (Uchida 1988, p. 6).

  6. 6.

    In an important and interesting work, Tony Smith argues adroitly for the position that Marx’s goal “is nothing more that the Hegelian goal of reconstructing the world in thought through working out a systematic theory of categories” (Smith 1990, p. 35; see also Smith 1993). I see Marx as less tied to Hegel’s methodology and more focused on the goal of developing a scientific theory about real phenomena, a view that is also more congenial to retrieving his work on the basis of contemporary observations and theorizing.

  7. 7.

    Some will appreciate his quips about German philosophy , for example, when he quotes Goethe : “words are excellent for fighting with, with words a system may be built” (MECW 24, p. 547). Or as Marx and Engels wrote in The German Ideology, the “imaginary rising above the world is the ideological expression of the impotence of philosophers in face of the world” (MECW 5, p. 379). None of this is true of his “analytic method” of the real world—or good contemporary analytic philosophy!

  8. 8.

    Philosophical positions, for example, about the fundamental nature of reality, were not topics of discussion or analysis for Marx, but he said enough to indicate that he thought the world was composed only of matter, including anything thought to be spiritual or mental. The mind, the will, and spirit, if they are anything, are on this view compatible with the material (physical) world. Compatibilism was developed in depth by David Hume (1711–1776) and is almost universally held by philosophers , and others, today. Marx was almost certainly also a realist, believing that there is a real world independent of the mind (materially understood).

    Of course metaphysical materialism is different from any form of historical materialism, according to which material things, for example, productive forces, are determining conditions of social relations such as economic power and political institutions.

  9. 9.

    Positivism has a long, complex, and distinguished history that would take at least a book to discuss and still not have an agreed resolution. Marx did not go into the philosophical details and of course worked before many of the developments, especially in the last century. The issues and ideas get even more confused in most of those who wrote about Marx. It is Marx’s investigations, and analyses, that is the focus in this chapter.

  10. 10.

    The idea of a category mistake was developed and explicated by the important Oxford analytical philosopher Gilbert Ryle. See Ryle (1949, pp. 18–23). It may be a pragmatic rather than conceptual mistake.

  11. 11.

    Here I pass over a lot of good philosophical discussions of perception and knowledge about which there are still plausible positivist contributions. My focus is on critics who seem to mischaracterize the methods that Marx followed.

    For a good discussion of another aspect (and criticism) of positivism, the covering-law model about cause and effect, see Richard Miller (“Replacing Positivism” in Miller 1984, pp. 271–313) on “the [Marxist] mode of production theory … as a successful theory of how change takes place” (p. 292).

  12. 12.

    Andrew Levine (2003, p. 68). Levine also notes other forms of holism (discussed below) that recognizes (but Levine questions) lesser wholes of constituents that cannot be understood by the constituents alone.

  13. 13.

    It should not be an “a priori beginning point,” as David Harvey tells us, nor should it be something that is chosen because, as Harvey suggests, it is “something that is familiar to us all” (Harvey 2010, p. 15). If there are reasons for a beginning, presumably they should be scientific.

  14. 14.

    I knew Cohen personally for over 40 years and always regarded his work with the utmost admiration and continue to feel the loss of a great Marxist intellect since his death in 2009. Nevertheless, I demur at counting him and a couple of others as the founders of analytical Marxism. Many analytical philosophers turned to Marxism in the 1960s and 1970s, with Cohen certainly being an important leader. I also think it is misleading to think of analytical philosophy having techniques. I continue in the text to criticize some of Cohen’s “oppositions,” but all in the style of analytical philosophy that we practised together.

  15. 15.

    See Wood (2004, p. 97) on ascribing interests to groups as well as to individuals, which “is closely connected to several other concepts: what benefits it, what is good for it, what makes it well off” all of which apply to collectives, classes, and corporations. Thus, corporations can be interested in merging with other corporations and be responsible for polluting the atmosphere. Elsewhere, I have discussed responsibility of collective agents partly because of such features. (See Ware, 2014; see also Graham 2002 and 1992 (especially pp. 24–34) on collectives.)

  16. 16.

    An influential leader or outside wealthy lobbyist might decide the results, but such “participants” do not make the decision. See Chap. 9 on emancipatory democracy for more on the relevant distinction.

  17. 17.

    There is now a substantive body of literature on group action, including, very selectively, Gilbert (2000), Graham (2002, Chap. 3), Tollefsen (2015), Tuomela (1995, 2013), Ware (1988, 2014).

  18. 18.

    Further examples and classifications, based on an earlier manuscript of mine, are given in Tuomela (1995, pp. 249–253). This natural comparison, of course, does not prove a metaphysical point, however that would be done.

  19. 19.

    It appears that once Marx “coquetted” with the dialectic, it was natural for him to look to collectives rather than simple cause and effect, but one does not have to be a dialectician to get to a plausible form of methodological holism.

  20. 20.

    See Matthen and Ware (1994), Wright et al. (1992), and Wimsatt (1980).

  21. 21.

    Chomsky’s point in “The Mysteries of Nature: How Deeply Hidden” (Chomsky 2016, pp. 81–127) is that some aspects of the world, including gravity and consciousness, are inconceivable to our common-sense beliefs and conceptions. An understanding of this, no doubt, was an influence in the new directions in natural science towards the end of the nineteenth century.

    Hedström and Swedberg recognize the history in nineteenth-century physics and that the word “mechanism” is not used in physics, but they try to justify that it is still appropriate in social sciences (Hedström and Swedberg 1998, p. 2n4).

  22. 22.

    Engels seemed to show an openness to new developments, which does not suit the systematic logic that he apparently wanted, as he followed the unifying work on chemistry and physics in the late nineteenth century. He must have gone beyond Marx in seeing the influence of Hegel in a new dawn of philosophy such that although “[n]atural scientists [and presumably social scientists] may adopt whatever attitude they please, they are still under the domination of philosophy” (MECW 25, p. 491).

References

  • Note: References to the work of Frederick Engels and Karl Marx are from Karl Marx, Frederick Engels, Collected Works. 50 Volumes, 1975–2004. New York, NY: International Publishers. (Referred to in text as “MECW” with volume and page).

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, Jeffrey C., Bernhard Giesen, Richard Münch, and Neil J. Smelser, eds. 1987. The Micro-Macro Link. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottomore, Tom, ed. 1991. A Dictionary of Marxist Thought. 2nd ed. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carver, Terrell, ed. 1983. Marx & Engels: The Intellectual Relationship. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———, ed. 1991. The Cambridge Companion to Marx. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, Noam. 2016. What Kind of Creatures Are We? New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2001 [1978]. Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence. Expanded ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. (Published in 1978 by Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, Jon. 1985. Making Sense of Marx. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Marxism and Individualism. In Knowledge and Politics: Case Studies in the Relationship between Epistemology and Political Philosophy, ed. M. Dascal and O. Gruengard. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, Margaret. 2000. Sociality and Responsibility: New Essays in Plural Subject Theory. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, Keith. 1992. Karl Marx Our Contemporary: Social Theory for a Post-Leninist World. Toronto, ON: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Practical Reasoning in a Social World. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harvey, David. 2010. A Companion to Marx’s Capital. London, UK: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter, and Peter Bearman, eds. 2009. The Oxford Handbook of Analytical Sociology. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter, and Richard Swedberg, eds. 1998. Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to Social Theory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Andrew. 2003. A Future for Marxism?: Althusser, the Analytical Turn and the Revival of Socialist Theory. London, UK: Pluto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, Norman. 2012. Marx’s Discourse with Hegel. Houndmills, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, Richard, and Richard Lewontin. 1985. The Dialectical Biologist. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, Mohan and R. X. Ware, eds. 1994. Biology & Society: Reflections on Methodology. Supplementary Volume 20 of Canadian Journal of Philosophy. Calgary, AB: University of Calgary Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, Richard W. 1984. Analyzing Marx: Morality Power and History. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ollman, Bertell. 2003. Dance of the Dialectic: Steps in Marx’s Method. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, Gilbert. 1949. The Concept of Mind. London, UK: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Tony. 1990. The Logic of Marx’s Capital: Replies to Hegelian Criticisms. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Dialectical Social Theory and Its Critics. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tollefsen, Deborah Perron. 2015. Groups as Agents. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, Raimo. 1995. The Importance of Us: A Philosophical Study of Basic Social Notions. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Uchida, Hiroshi. 1988. Marx’s Grundrisse and Hegel’s Logic. Ed. Terrell Carver. London, UK: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, David M. 2001. Marx, Methodology and Science. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ware, Robert. 1988. Group Action and Social Ontology. Analyse & Kritik 10 (1): 48–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Review of Dance of the Dialectic. Philosophy in Review xxiv (4): 281–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Collective Responsibility. In Encyclopedia of Quality of Life and Well-Being Research, ed. Alex Michalos. Netherlands: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilde, Lawrence. 1991. Logic: Dialectic and Contradiction. In The Cambridge Companion to Marx, ed. Terrell Carver, 275–295. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, William. 1980. Reductionistic Research Strategies and Their Biases in the Units of Selection Controversy. In Scientific Discovery: Case Studies, ed. T. Nickles. Dordrecht, Netherlands: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wood, Allen W. 2004. Karl Marx. 2nd ed. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, Erik Olin, Andrew Levine, and Elliott Sober. 1992. Reconstructing Marxism: Essays on Explanation and the Theory of History. London, UK: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Ware, R.X. (2019). Coquetting with Dialectics. In: Marx on Emancipation and Socialist Goals. Marx, Engels, and Marxisms. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-97716-4_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics