Skip to main content

The Graz Period

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 165 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind ((SHPM,volume 21))

Abstract

Vittorio Benussi should be considered the empiricist of the Graz School. His emphasis on the primacy of experience was absolutely radical. Moreover, he constantly warned about the perils of constructing global theories holding that to do so inevitably deforms empirical data, especially when researchers are forced to fit the same data into a systematic edifice. This problem, Benussi held, was no less serious when the acquired data was arrived at by means of methodologically sound procedures.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Benussi Archive, Lessons, 1920, box 7, file 14.

  2. 2.

    Benussi Archive, Curriculum vitae, box 17, file 2.

  3. 3.

    Meinong’s letter of reference of 26.12.1918 attached to Benussi’s application for the appointment as full professor (Vittorio Benussi, Personal file, Central State Archive, Rome).

  4. 4.

    Sante De Sanctis’s letter to the Rector of the Faculty of Philosophy of the Royal University of Padua, Rome, 19.05.1919 (Vittorio Benussi, Personal file, Central State Archive, Rome).

  5. 5.

    Benussi Archive, Autobiographical notes, box 14, file 5.

  6. 6.

    As we have seen, Meinong in fact avoided using the terms ‘intentional’ and ‘intentionality’, preferring to refer to the concept of “objectuality” (Gegenständlichkeit) for the mental phenomena characteristic of ‘having something as an object’.

  7. 7.

    In his Grundlinien der Psychologie, as already mentioned, Witasek abandoned the thesis of Sinnestäuschung in favour of Produktionstäuschung, by endorsing the theoretical and experimental results which Benussi had found in the meantime (Witasek 1908, pp. 239–246).

  8. 8.

    Benussi Archive, Psychologie der inadäquaten Auffassung (The Psychology of Inadequate Apprehension), 1913, box 5, file 3. See also Benussi 1914a, pp. 401 f. [346 f.].

  9. 9.

    The cases of inadequate perception refer to an abnormality on the presentational level, not to the Meinongian Objektiv (Benussi 1906b, pp. 153 f.).

  10. 10.

    Benussi 1904, p. 391 [86 f.]; 1905b, pp. 442 f. Cf. Benussi 1914a, p. 402 [346 f.] and 1907a, p. 25, n. 1 [157, n. 6].

  11. 11.

    Brentano 1887–1901, pp. 84–88. This distinction was already implicitly formulated in Brentano’s Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (Brentano 1874a).

  12. 12.

    See Benussi 1914a, p. 402 [347]: “It is, therefore, absurd to speak of sensory illusions, since sense data are by no means assertions or deceptive convictions. But it makes sense to speak of deceptions by the senses. If the senses supply inappropriate data, and when we use this data to build assertions, we are accepting an illusion. If we abstain from any assertion, and if the sense data in question continue unhindered, this aspect does not change at all. Nevertheless, we call them inadequate or unadjusted in the sense that they may lead to deceptive convictions.” Cf. Benussi 1906a, p. 25, n. 1 [157, n. 6].

  13. 13.

    “To perceive an object is to experience its presence.” (Benussi 1925b, p. 2 [192])

  14. 14.

    See Benussi Archive, Psychologie der inadäquaten Auffassung (The Psychology of Inadequate Apprehension), box 5, file 3: “What has to be investigated and systematically classified is the inadequate intuition (Anschauung), and the contribution of different intellectual processes that allow it to arise, which needs to be specified. The moment of conviction is a non-essential side-effect, a fortuitous consequence of an intuition with this or that result, it is quite undifferentiated and accidental, and it does not contribute at all to the characteristics of what is said to be an equivocal illusion and an unequivocal inadequacy.”

  15. 15.

    Benussi Archive, Studien zur experimentellen Psychologie der Gestaltwahrnehmungen (Adäquatheit und Inadäquatheit) (Studies on the Experimental Psychology of Gestalt Perceptions [Adequacy and Inadequacy]), 1910, box 3, file 11. This thesis is repeatedly supported by Benussi: “Errors do not exist in psychology. They only make sense if one considers the intellectual performance of a given process, thus, if one assumes the external point of view that pertains to theories of knowledge.” (Benussi Archive, Curriculum vitae, box 17, file 2)

  16. 16.

    Benussi Archive, Notes, box 16, file 22.

  17. 17.

    With the term ‘Gestalt ambiguity’ or ‘equivocity’ (Gestaltmehrdeutigkeit) Benussi designates the specific property of a given set of real objects serving as foundations for different higher-order objects: “If, on the one hand, different Gestalten (production objects) […] are given on the basis of one and the same complex of sensory objects, on the other hand, the presentations of different Gestalten can be formed, starting from one and the same complex of sensations. This (sensory) complex can be designated “presentationally ambiguous” (vorstellungsmehrdeutig). The Gestalt ambiguity of a complex of (sensory) objects thus, corresponds to the (Gestalt) presentational ambiguity of a given sensory complex.” (Benussi 1906a, p. 23 [155 f.]) Cf. Benussi 1906b, pp. 155 f.

  18. 18.

    “The term ‘A-reaction’ indicates the case in which the subject must refrain from this gestaltic comprehension, and grasp the main line of the figure as an independent and isolated object.” (Benussi 1904, p. 310 [8])

  19. 19.

    “The term ‘G-reaction’ indicates the case in which the subject is asked […] to consider the main line of the figure as part of a whole Gestalt, which is simultaneously perceived, and used for the comparison.” (Ibid.)

  20. 20.

    “Finally, ‘S-reaction’ denotes the case in which the subject is not prescribed a particular reaction, in which case she will react spontaneously in the sense of either A or G.” (Benussi 1904, p. 310 [8 f.])

  21. 21.

    Ibid., Sect. 7, pp. 321–334 [19–31]: Die doppelseitige (A- und G-) Übung (The Double-Sided (A and G) Exercise).

  22. 22.

    Benussi 1904, pp. 413 f. [108]: “As regards the position of the production process within the opposites ‘active’ and ‘passive’, one has to point to the ‘exercise’ characterising both types of reaction. Insofar as exercisability is regarded as a criterion for activity, one is entitled to regard the production process as a form of mental activity.”

  23. 23.

    Benussi 1904, Sect. 20, pp. 395–403 [95–97]: Der Anteil der Farbe an der Täuschungsgröße. Die Verbindung durch die Farbenaufdringlichkeit (The Contribution of Colour to the Size of Illusions. The Connection through Colour Obtrusiveness).

  24. 24.

    On the concept of “real relation” see Meinong 1899, Sect. 6 and above, Chap. 2, Sect. 2.4.4.1.

  25. 25.

    Benussi 1904, Sect. 10, pp. 392–395 [88–90]: Die Ursache des inadäquaten Vorstellens gegebener Inhalte (The Cause of the Inadequate Presenting of Given Contents).

  26. 26.

    Benussi 1914a, p. 403 [348]: “Whether an inadequate impression is a case of the first or the second kind cannot be inferred through direct self-observation; just as self-observation cannot teach us whether we ‘hear’ a melody in the same sense as we unquestionably speak of hearing an individual sound.”

  27. 27.

    “To justify the changes in terminology”, Benussi (1914a, pp. 400 f. [345 f.]) explained: “In substance, what I understand by a presentation of non-sensory origin coincides with what Meinong qualified as the production of presentations (Vorstellungsproduktion), following the corresponding theoretical remarks of R. Ameseder, who, in turn, was inspired by the precise distinction between content and act of the presentation made by Meinong himself. For Meinong, the contrast with the reproduction of presentations was decisive. On the other hand, Meinong and Ameseder proceeded from the nature of objects in their explanation. Factually, in my view, there is nothing to object. I did not find the term ‘production’ convenient, and I became increasingly convinced of this because of the questions posed by my students. Likewise, the characterisation of the produced presentations by recourse to the (ideal) nature of the Gestalten also seemed difficult to understand and misleading. Only for these reasons I preferred the expression presentations of non-sensory origin, and if possible, the description of these presentations should only be carried out by considering the lack of corresponding stimuli for any sense-organ.”

  28. 28.

    Benussi systematically studied the reversal configurations from 1904 onward, well before the well-known research on this topic conducted by Edgar Rubin (Rubin 1915a, b).

  29. 29.

    With the term Grundlage, Benussi means the objectual basis or foundation (Meinong’s inferiora), on which emerge multiple and different Gestalten, by virtue of otherwise productive acts. As mentioned, the term goes back to Ehrenfels, who used it to illustrate his concept of “Gestalt quality”.

  30. 30.

    Benussi Archive, Auffälligkeit (Salience), 1905, box 1, file 11.

  31. 31.

    Benussi Archive, Psychologie der inadäquaten Auffassung (The Psychology of Inadequate Apprehension), 1913, box 5, file 3. A first formulation can already be found in Benussi 1904, pp. 385 ff. [81 ff.], and Benussi 1905a, pp. 265 f.

  32. 32.

    Benussi Archive, Psychologie der inadäquaten Auffassung (The Psychology of Inadequate Apprehension), 1913, box 5, file 3.

  33. 33.

    Benussi 1913a, pp. 4 f. [9]. “The psychology of time has to investigate the conditions under which the means for understanding time, that is, temporal presentations, are such that the objects which are made accessible to us through them are adequate with respect to actual present-time; it has to establish through which internal events the various relations between subjective or grasped time, and objective or actual time are made possible.”

  34. 34.

    On Brentano’s theory of time see especially Kraus 1930; Kastil 1939; Chisholm 1981; Volpi 1989.

  35. 35.

    Benussi explicitly made his reference points clear in the “object-theoretical” or “phenomenological” analysis: “Fortunately, of late, the insight into the importance of an accurate analysis of the phenomena for any kind of psychological analysis has increasingly spread. In addition to the fundamental works of object-theoretical and phenomenological nature of A. Meinong and E. Husserl, a whole series of detailed investigations stemming from the Würzburg School can also be considered.” (Benussi 1913a, p. 62, n. 1 [51, n. 4]) “Undoubtedly, also time psychology has to expect some advantages from an object-theoretical clarification of the extra-mental phenomena associated with it.” (Ibid., p. 496, n. 2 [356, n. 8]) With explicit reference to Meinong’s theories of complexions, relations and objectives, of which he stressed the importance for the studies of D. Katz on colours and of P. F. Linke and M. Wertheimer on apparent motion and Gestalt illusions, Benussi wrote: “The more one becomes convinced that a-psychologism is of equal importance to psychology, as psychologism for the philosophical disciplines connected with psychology.” (Ibid.) Cf. Benussi 1907b, p. 376, n. 2.

  36. 36.

    Benussi 1913a, Chap. I, pp. 9–58 [13–47]: Die einfachsten Beziehungen zwischen subjektiver und objektiver Zeit (The Simplest Relationships between Subjective and Objective Time).

  37. 37.

    Ibid., pp. 10 f. [14]: “The contrast between intuitive and the non-intuitive can […] become sufficiently precise by saying: if a mere process of presentation is sufficient for the characterisation of the intellectual experiences which are necessary to make present (vergegenwärtigen) an object, then we will be able to call the grasping of this object intuitive; if, on the other hand, these events are insufficient, then we shall speak of non-intuitive apprehension. Thus, one can make present a second through a mere presentation, while the duration of a year requires a peculiar inner attitude […], or the thought: ‘the time between two limits, which can be determined by means of external limits’.”

  38. 38.

    Benussi 1913a, pp. 19 f. [20]: “Self-observation points to two significant factors which are of importance to our problem: on the one hand, by grasping short times there is a growing difficulty in analysing the temporal stretch between the delimiting noises, as well as the two delimiting noises themselves; in the apprehension of long times, on the other hand, the increase in their length is accompanied by an increase in the difficulty of summarising the two delimiting noises as boundary points of a stretch. What is difficult here, therefore, is not the analysis of the temporal stretch from the total experienced impression, but the synthesis of the two boundaries into a close unity. […] Thus, apart from the qualitative differences of the more salient moments between short and long times, there seems to be a qualitative difference between the inner intellectual processes which are actualised in grasping short or long time. The effort to ignore the boundaries during short times contrasts with the effort, during long times, to hold together the limiting noises.”

  39. 39.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 60 [50 f.]: “As soon as we wish to know more about the relations between objective and subjective time, we depend on a comparison of time. In this way, the participation of moments become possible, which do not regard the comprehending of time, that is, do not regard the emergence of a time-presentation, but the comparison of time. […] From this unavoidable interference of the comparison with the experiences actually to be investigated, arises the methodical requirement to question and to decide for each concrete result, to what extent this result depends on conditions related to the origin of the time presentation as such, or to what extent the result depends on processes leading to comparative statements related to the objects of temporal presentations. In other words, and making use of terminology that will be introduced later, one has to question whether one is dealing with a presentational or a comparative eventuality.”

  40. 40.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 174 [130]: “Thus, a comparative statement is not directly dependent on the objective temporal magnitudes, but on the Gestalt with which its limits are grasped. Since this Gestalt is determined by the different degrees of unity among its founding elements, i.e. the delimiting noises, it has to be designated as a grouping or phrasing Gestalt.” Ibid., pp. 107 f. [82 f.]: “Here as there, the objective state of affairs is not important for our statement, but it is the nature of the comprehension (Auffassung), that is, something which already lies beyond a passive sense activity. […] Theoretically, this parallelism is of great importance because it shows that the peculiarities which one encounters in the investigation of the factors on which the production of the middle of a time stretch depends are not specific to time perception. They are as little bound to time perception, as they seem to be bound to the function of sense organs. Rather, they can be found whenever we are considering the comprehension of a distance, or of a gap, whenever there is an opportunity for comprehending, elaborating or forming.” Ibid., pp. 130 f. [100]: “In this regard, the comparison with the so numerous and contradictory explanatory attempts of so-called geometric-optical illusions becomes necessary. Here, too, we tried to make sense-moments responsible for the most diverse types of inadequacy in our presenting, and only recently we began to understand the fact that a moment alien to sensation plays a leading role in all these phenomena, namely the unitary grasping of the given material in a closed Gestalt.”

  41. 41.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 189 [141]: “The above-mentioned absolute impression of a long duration does not arise because we subjectively ‘extend’ the time that passes, but because we estimate it by using data that we gained under circumstances which can subjectively shorten time. […] With regard to what I have said, I am entitled to the supposition that we are usually subject to time-shortening, but not to time-extending illusions.”

  42. 42.

    See above, Chap. 2, Sect. 2.4.9.3.

  43. 43.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 222 [163 f.]: “The magnitude of a ‘duration’ is completely determined by the magnitude of the difference of the temporal instants delimiting it to the same extent as the magnitude of a stretch is determined by the magnitude of the difference of the spatial points circumscribing it. This relationship of dependence is due to the fact that the two phenomena of ‘duration’ and ‘time difference’ between the endpoints, as objects, cannot be separated from each other, and therefore cannot subsist independently of one another.”

  44. 44.

    Benussi 1913a, pp. 222 f. [164]: “This dependence regarding subsistence (Bestandabhängigkeit) on the level of objects, however, does not imply any dependence regarding existence (Existenzabhängigkeit) on the level of intellectual processes, which allow them to be present to us. The temporal difference can be presented and observed independently from the corresponding temporal duration, the spatial difference independently from the spatial distance, which is connected with it only as an object and in its subsistence.”

  45. 45.

    See this Chapter, Sect. 4.3.5.

  46. 46.

    Benussi 1913a, Chap. IV, pp. 198–220 [145–162]: Die Pause (The Pause).

  47. 47.

    Ibid., pp. 234 f. [171 f.]: “With regard to the contrast between content and act, one could also speak, respectively, of content-experiences and act-experiences. In fact, one labels those (objects grasping) processes which are completely free of intuitive, ‘acts’”. Benussi adds: “The contrast between intuitive and non-intuitive would thus be due to the contrast between an apprehension of an object of an act or of a content type. From this would also result that there are no non-intuitive presentations, since the term ‘presentation’ (i.e. imaginative mode of presentification [Vergegenwärtigung]) usually signifies only imaginative contents. […] The controversy about intuition arose only because different modes of presentation were assumed, whereas actually there are only different processes of apprehension.”

  48. 48.

    The distance from Meinong’s position is clear. For Meinong, in fact, the production of non-intuitive presentations took place through the mediation of acts of assumption. See Meinong 1910, Chap. VIII.

  49. 49.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 234, n. 1 [171, n. 12]: “[T]he emphatic pointing out of directional experiences (Richtungserlebnisse) is one of the merits of the Würzburg School […]”. The concepts of Akterlebnis and Richtungserlebnis undoubtedly refer to the “intention” of Karl Bühler, and to the “tendency” (Tendenz) of Narziß Ach, who in turn referred to Husserl’s Bedeutungsintention. On the Würzburg School see Humphrey 1951; Ronco 1963. On the relations between the Graz School and the Würzburg School see Lindenfeld 1980, pp. 225 ff.

  50. 50.

    Benussi 1913a, pp. 208 f. [153 f.]: “By immediately grasping the given times, of the two objects (the ‘complex of the delimiting noises’ and the ‘time interval between the noises’) that are comprehensible and are also actually comprehended, the complex becomes more salient. This (relative) maximum of salience shifts during the pause to the time interval as such, as soon as the whole complex is present by means of immediate mnestic data (these data do not imply the occurrence of actual mnemonic presentations, i.e. intellectual experiences which are due to reproductive processes, but only imply the mental direction to the no longer present object).”

  51. 51.

    Ibid., pp. 209 f. [154 f.]: “This displacement of salience, however, has the consequence that, as soon as the second temporal moment is given, and thus the basis for grasping a ratio of time magnitudes is perfect, objects which are not subjectively homogeneous in all respects are used as basis for comparison. This basis is given, on the one hand, by the presentation of the first temporal moment, which already belongs to the past (whereby, in the first place, this memory-like mental direction is aimed at the temporal stretch as such); on the other hand, it is given by the direct impression of the second temporal moment, in which attention is directed, in the first instance, to the complex of delimiting noises. The objectual moment, which, by means of a corresponding presentation or direction of thought, fills, or at least ‘accompanies’ the expectation of the second temporal moment, is, by its very nature, something quantitative, something to which size adheres. On the other hand, that which completes the basis of the comparison through its addition, and makes possible the formation of the statement, is, by its very nature, something that is not quantitative, but qualitative: the complex, the group of delimiting noises.”

  52. 52.

    Benussi 1913a, pp. 270 f. [196 f.]: “Impressions which are more or less remotely assigned to the objects to be detected can give rise to presentations of a non-sensory origin, to productive presentations, and these can both modify the subjective character of those objects, and indirectly turn attention to moments that do not belong to the actual ones to be compared. Finally, such moments can also have a direct influence on the comparative statement, in that the given circumstances are capable of increasing their salience.”

  53. 53.

    Ibid., p. 258 [188]: “For the resulting statement, the relationship of salience between the proper and the simultaneously comprehended improper objects of comparison is decisive, since the statement is determined by the more salient objects. […] On the presupposition of an equivocally determined basis of comparison, the comparative result is determined primarily by the (relative) nature of the more salient objects, no matter whether these are the proper or improper objects of comparison. However, the comparative statement is based not on the former, but on the latter.” Cf. ibid., p. 282 [205 f.].

  54. 54.

    Ibid., pp. 283 f. [206 f.]: “Inner perception can only teach us about the existence of states of consciousness; in our case, for example, only about the fact that at the present time, and whether at the present time, there is a current presentation of difference in me or whether it exists in me. However, inner perception can say as little about where this presentation of difference comes from, about its source, as an external perception can say about whether there is a causal link between the lighting of a match and the appearance of a flame. Hence, the fact that a comparative statement is based on objects (or impressions) foreign to the comparison does not contradict the evidence of inner perception, for the latter only provides us with knowledge about the instantaneous existence of mental states, but not about their relations.” Cf. Benussi 1907b, pp. 375 f.

  55. 55.

    Specifically, Benussi reported the following data: when space (d) and time (t) of Vs were both larger (or smaller) than those of Ss, the percentage of correct answers was equal to 55.62% (53.12% when they were both smaller), whereas when t of Vs was longer (or shorter), but d was shorter (or longer), this rate was equal to 31.87% (36.24%).

  56. 56.

    Benussi 1913a, pp. 287 f. [209 f.]: “This tendency […] is due to the fact that, under the same circumstances, the temporal differences are much more salient than the spatial ones. Although the temporal differences are foreign to comparisons from an intentional point of view, they strongly determine the result of the comparison. It should also be noted that the temporal differences act even more indirectly on the apparent spatial difference, in that the points following one another are grouped together, and grouping, as we already know, operates both on temporal and spatial levels, by diminishing what is contained in the ‘group delimitation’.”

  57. 57.

    Benussi Archive, Experimental-Psychologie der Phantasie- und Vorstellungsvorgänge (Experimental Psychology of the Imaginative and Presentational Processes), 1906/07, box 1, file 23.

  58. 58.

    Ibid. Cf. Benussi Archive, Ein Beispiel zur Einmischung uneigentlicher Vergleichsgroößen (An Example of the Intrusion of Improper Comparison Magnitudes), 1906, box 1, file 22.

  59. 59.

    Benussi 1913a, Chap. VI, pp. 272–339 [199–246]: Zeitgröße und Begrenzungsart (Time Magnitude and Types of Boundary).

  60. 60.

    Ibid., pp. 300 f. [218 f.]: “If the greater attentional time (Aufmerksamkeitszeit), and hence the greater present-time (Gegenwartszeit) fall on the first note (the sound at the beginning), then it seems to us as if it ceases a little later – the following short time must thus must be subjectively shortened; if, instead, the greater attentional time is directed toward the final sound, then the apparent magnitude of the temporal stretch must change in the opposite direction.”

  61. 61.

    See above, Chap. 2, Sect. 2.4.9.6.

  62. 62.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 387 [279]: “These [lights] are not presentified by means of two successive acts, but by a single act of Gestalt presentification, and they are experienced as non-simultaneous. The direction of this ‘non-simultaneous’ comprehending depends only on the difference of salience of the two lights, i.e. on whether the grasped Gestalt has a closed character.”

  63. 63.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 390 [281]: “The distribution of attention determines an earlier grasping, that of salience, a grasping as earlier of a given light; but both the ‘earlier’ and the ‘as earlier’ are explained in terms of ‘precedence’.”

  64. 64.

    Benussi 1913a, p. 501 [358]: “In any case, every attempt that considers memory to be involved in the development of time-consciousness suffers from being a tautology: is it not more natural to think of time consciousness as being a condition of memory?”

  65. 65.

    Ibid., p. 503 [360 f.]: “It seems to me to be out of the question that the inner process which allow temporal apprehension (Zeitauffassung) to unfold are intimately related to those intellectual (Gestalt-comprehending) processes which give us a mental direction toward melodies, differences, and distances in general, and further, in a similar way, that the presentification of time (Zeitvergegenwärtigung) is most likely attributed to the group of presentations which we call productive presentations or presentations of a non-sensory origin.” Cf. ibid., p. 8 [12].

  66. 66.

    Ibid., p. 505 [362]: “Here, too, as is obvious, we find ourselves conceptually embarrassed, and at present, there is no trustworthy path toward clarity. Actually, the matter is far worse, for we are not even able to grasp our embarrassment at its roots, and thereby we cannot take a first step towards the resolution of the question, which would require understanding the obstacles that need to be overcome.”

  67. 67.

    Benussi Archive, Notes, box 16, file 22.

  68. 68.

    In this regard, Husserl introduced the example of unstable perceptions, that is, perceptual situations in which, faced with the same set of sensory data, a conflict develops between two different apperceptive interpretations of the same complex (mannequin – real person). Husserl used this example on several occasions; see, e.g., Husserl 1948, pp. 99 f.; Eng. 92 f.

  69. 69.

    Benussi’s work – especially his research on time consciousness – did not escape Husserl’s notice and he kept a copy of Benussi’s Psychologie der Zeitauffassung (see Hoofdwoordencataloog – 09.04.87) in his library. Benussi is also expressly mentioned in some of Husserl’s manuscripts (D 13 III / 208a; K II 4 / 59–62; BQ 27 / Vorbl.). Cf. Schuhmann 1975.

  70. 70.

    Of course, beyond the often very surprising affinities between Husserl and Benussi’s projects, a fundamental difference remains: while Husserl’s genetic phenomenology programmatically intended to be an eidetic investigation, designed to bring out the necessary stages through which intentional experience is formed, Benussi’s project was an empirical and experimental investigation of the stages or phases, that can be determined empirically, through which our consciousness of objects is constituted in time. It made use of the instruments available to the experimental psychologist at the time: tachistoscopic presentations of visual and acoustic stimuli of different temporal amplitudes, increases or decreases in the intensity and brightness of the elements of Gestalt complexes, increases, reductions and rotations of visual Gestalten – techniques which were of great importance to cognitive psychology during the last decades. The use of these techniques aimed to analyse the Teil- or Vorgestalten, characterised by a relative mutability in the relationship between their parts, and their tendency to gradually take on a more stable shape.

    Benussi’s research on Gestaltzeit (Gestalt Time) (Benussi 1914a; cf. Benussi Archive, Die Gestaltzeit, 1912, box 4, files 2, 3, 4, 6, 7, 9) has to be placed in this framework. The Gestaltzeit being the time required by the apprehensive act in order for the sensory data to gradually organise themselves into (relatively) stable percepts. Benussi used figural complexes attributable to well-known illusory figures and tachistoscopically projected some of their figural elements (e.g., the slanting segments of the Müller-Lyer figure) with different exposure times (brief, indifferent, long), while assessing the exposure time necessary for the occurrence of the maximum illusory effect, or for the full implementation of a grouping or Gestalt attitude. He discovered that this time was variable, depending on the constitutionally analytical or synthetic tendency of the observer.

  71. 71.

    See above all Husserl 1966, 1973. Of the available large critical literature, I limit myself by only reporting Kern 1964; Held 1966; Brand 1969; Holenstein 1972; Yamaguchi 1982; Miller 1984; Rang 1990; Römpp 1992; Kühn 1998; Taguchi 2006; Sandmeyer 2009; Biceaga 2010.

  72. 72.

    Husserl then goes on to the formations of pure actuality, to the constitution of the individuality of the monad, to the inter-monadicity, and the implication of a monad in the genesis of another, to finally conclude with the intersubjective constitution of a single world, which is intersubjectively valid for all subjects. In the 1930s Husserl would calls this double, outward and backward movement Abbau-Analyse (deconstruction analysis) and Aufbau-Analyse (construction analysis).

  73. 73.

    On Meinong’s distinction between subjective or ideal relations (produced by the mind), and objective or real relations (“encountered relations”) see above, Chap. 2, Sect. 2.4.4.1.

  74. 74.

    Benussi Archive, Auffälligkeit (Salience), 1905, box 1, file 11.

  75. 75.

    Ibid.

  76. 76.

    Benussi Archive, Notes, box 16, file 22.

  77. 77.

    Koffka 1935, p. 147: “In the first place, under certain circumstances, we find the field organisation dependent upon attitudes, i.e. forces which have their origin not in the surrounding field at all, but in the Ego of the observer. This is a new indication that our task of investigating the surrounding field alone is somewhat artificial, and that we shall understand its organisation completely only when we study the total field which includes the Ego within its environment.” Cf. ibid., pp. 319 ff., 519 ff., 594 ff.; Köhler 1947, pp. 123 ff.; Metzger 1954, pp. 81 ff. and Chap. VIII.

  78. 78.

    See in this regard: Pupp 1932; Musatti 1929a; Keiler 1980; Metelli 1987; Smith 1988a, , b; Ash 1995, pp. 139–147.

  79. 79.

    Benussi Archive, Notes, box 16, file 22: “[T]he (apparent) motion represents the perfect synthesis of spatial and temporal perceptual data, fused together in a single non-sensory perception: that of motion.”

  80. 80.

    The most important were Schumann’s tachistoscope, and a slide projector or slider device (Schieber) of his own invention. The front part of the device was made of two laminae with slots. One foil was fixed, while the other was fitted with a handle and could be made to slide forward and backward behind the first.

  81. 81.

    In addition to (1) the time interval between stimulus exposures, Wertheimer varied: (2) the distance between the stimuli, (3) the form, (4) the colour, (5) the intensity and (6) the mutual relationships of the two stimulus objects. He also introduced further objects in the exposure field, and considered the effects of the “variations in subjective behaviour”, which included prolonged observation, positions or attitudes, and attention to a focal point.

  82. 82.

    Wertheimer 1912, p. 251; Eng. 78: “The basic supposition here is that the excitatory processes in the stimulated cells themselves (received from the periphery or through “associative connections”), or the sum of these individual excitations, is not at all that is essential: rather, characteristic transverse and holistic processes [Quer- und Gesamtvorgänge], resulting from the stimulation of individual loci – perhaps as a point of incidence, as a specific whole of greater scope – must play an important role, directly relevant for some factors that still need to be clarified psychologically.”

  83. 83.

    Ibid., p. 252; Eng. 79 f.: “With a favourable temporal sequence of the onset of the two spreading activations of a and b, cross-over of an excitation occurs, but if t is very short, then the spreading begins to make its appearance too close to simultaneity to enable the directional short circuit. But in this case, what would occurs initially for certain effects is a kind of physiological connectedness and indeed a uniform overall process [Gesamtprozess], resulting as a whole from the individual physiological excitations: a simultaneous φ function.”

  84. 84.

    Paul Ferdinand Linke (1876–1955) should be mentioned among the most significant scholars who, starting from the study of stroboscopic motion, contributed to the renewal of the conception of Gestalt in the early decades of the 1900s. He was a former pupil of Wundt, and vigorously rejected associationism and the constancy hypothesis. He devoted a part of his Grundfragen der Wahrnehmungslehre (Basic Issues of the Theory of Perception) (Linke 1918) to a criticism of Wertheimer’s interpretation of the results of his experiments on apparent motion. Linke himself had faced the same problem in 1907 (Linke 1907; see also Linke 1915, 1916), presenting his identification theory and the importance of fusion phenomena associated with stroboscopic motion.

  85. 85.

    As Wertheimer himself wrote when summarising his analyses on the Gestalt principles or laws in his “Investigations on Gestalt Principles. I” (Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt. I.) (Wertheimer 1922, pp. 54–55): “The core of the statements can be found in the general sentences at the end of the “Experimental Studies on Seeing Motion” (Zeitschr. f. Psych., 1912, pp. 91–92, especially footnote 3) in a pure physiological terminology; in only physiological terms because of the great burden carried by the usual psychological and epistemological concepts.”

  86. 86.

    Benussi 1912, pp. 41 f. [306]: “The apprehension (Auffassung) of a uniformly appearing positional change is motion perception.”

  87. 87.

    Curiously, those were the days during which both Wertheimer and Benussi were taken into account by the University of Prague for a chair at the Faculty of Philosophy of the Charles University, which was vacated after the retirement of Anton Marty, and which was to be assigned to an experimental psychologist (cf. Ash 1995, p. 133). Despite the efforts of Christian von Ehrenfels, president of the appointed commission, neither Wertheimer nor Benussi received the summons, the first most likely because of his Jewish origins, the second because of his nationality. To this was added the hostility of the orthodox Brentanians’, especially of Marty’s pupils Oskar Kraus and Alfred Kastil, who had considerable influence within the faculty.

  88. 88.

    Adhémar Gelb (1887–1936), a student of Carl Stumpf who had initially supported his theses about the status of Gestalt qualities in his dissertation of 1911 (Gelb 1911), after moving to Frankfurt became an ardent advocate of Wertheimer’s theories.

  89. 89.

    The Congress also included Edgar Rubin, who presented a preliminary report on his seminal research on reversible configurations (Rubin 1915b).

  90. 90.

    Benussi underlined that in individuals born blind the impression of apparent motion develops in an even more clear and evident manner than in people with normal vision, although the latter have a more pronounced ability to deliberately influence the organisation of motion.

  91. 91.

    “[…] beside a number of general laws of form, [I could] establish the law of the tendency to a simple Gestalt (law of the ‘Prägnanz of the Gestalt’).” (Wertheimer 1914, p. 148)

  92. 92.

    Studying stroboscopic motion in the visual field, Gelb had discovered that three lights arranged in a straight line and flashing in sequence, tended to be perceived as equally spaced, even when there was a threefold distance between the first and the second light compared to the distance between the second and the third – a perceptual effect very similar to the tau-phenomenon discovered by Benussi. Gelb also obtained similar results for other sensory modalities. The perceptual system thus operated with a clear tendency towards symmetry, “in line with the laws of Gestalt (discovered by Max Wertheimer, but not yet published […])” (Gelb 1914, p. 42).

  93. 93.

    Vom Congress hier möchte ich dies berichten, dass sich zwischen Benussi und mir lange Gestaltgespräche ergaben, die mich sehr freuten: Benussi, den ich früher nicht näher kannte, scheint mir ein höchst erfreulicher Mensch! Wir verstehen uns auch theoretisch ausgezeichnet miteinander, wie wir zu unserem beiderseitigen Erstaunen erfreut […] weiter feststellten.” Max Wertheimer’s letter to Christian von Ehrenfels, Göttingen, 10.04.1914, Forschungsstelle und Dokumentationszentrum für österreichische Philosophie, Graz.

  94. 94.

    In this work, Bühler had analysed the different research orientations in the study of Gestalt perception, and experimentally determined the psychophysical differential thresholds for Gestalt perception of both the spatial and acoustic-temporal proportions. The book attracted Benussi’s attention, who reviewed it extensively in Benussi 1914f.

  95. 95.

    The full title of the journal was: Die Geisteswissenschaften. Wochenschrift für das gesamte Gebiet der Philosophie, Psychologie, Mathematik, Religionswissenschaft, Geschichtswissenschaft, Sprach- und Literaturwissenschaft, Kunstwissenschaft, Rechts- und Staatswissenschaft, Gesellschaftswissenschaft, Volkswirtschaftslehre und Statistik, Militärwissenschaft, Länder- und Völkerkunde, Pädagogik.

  96. 96.

    To these must be added the polemic against behaviourism lead by Köhler in the early 1930s. See Köhler 1933, Chap. I.

  97. 97.

    Koffka 1915, p. 26: “When establishing Gestalt ambiguity, and beyond any theory, what must be considered a fact? Obviously, it is that the same stimulus can determine different experiences […]. But B[enussi], as we have seen, expresses this fact differently: he does not only speak of a constant stimulus, but also of constant sensory material.”

  98. 98.

    See this Chapter, Sect. 4.3.5. Cf. Koffka 1915, pp. 17 f.

  99. 99.

    With the following justification: “The work of Ameseder [1904] and the two books by Witasek [Witasek 1908, 1910] we referred to were often called into play by Benussi himself.” (Koffka 1915, p. 15)

  100. 100.

    Ibid., p. 16: “The production process, which is alien to the sensations and to judgment, is carried out by sensations, which often proceeds starting from sensations in a perceivable temporal development.”

  101. 101.

    See this Chapter, Sect. 4.5.1.

  102. 102.

    Benussi Archive, Notes, box 16, file 22.

  103. 103.

    The reference is to Dewey 1903, and to Rahn 1913. But while Dewey’s, and more generally the North American functionalists’, concepts were guided by evolutionary and instrumentalist considerations, Koffka’s and the gestaltist’s interests were mainly ontological and physiological (cf. Ash 1995, p. 145).

  104. 104.

    As Ash suggested (1995, p. 143), the reference is probably to the concept of a “biologically appropriate” stimulus by Ludwig Edinger (1855–1918), the German neurologist who founded the first German Neurological Institute at the University of Frankfurt, and who can be considered the founder of neuroanatomy.

  105. 105.

    In correspondence to his functionalist approach, Koffka emphasised “that many of these deviations have a tremendous teleological and biological value; they are, with respect to our behaviour, precisely characterised by their adequacy” (Koffka 1915, p. 65).

  106. 106.

    Koffka had essentially branded Benussi’s scientific approach as flawed, due to his philosophical prejudice in considering consciousness to be unintelligible on a purely material basis: Produktion could therefore be considered the umpteenth deus ex machina.

  107. 107.

    Benussi 1917, p. 61, n. 2: “Koffka rightly notes (and this seems to me to be the main point) that ‘ambiguity’ cannot be a criterion for Gestalt perception, because it can also be found in the undisputable sensory field. Lately this has also been imposing on me, in terms of a self-objection, in opposition to my earlier statements in this respect, and this is on the basis of the following experiment, which is a variation of an older one, of Meyer and Wundt […]: about 20 grey small discs are arranged on a half red and half green background, so that half of the circle appears on a red background and the other half on a green one; the contrast effect diminishes when the circle Gestalt is analytically observed. The same experiment […] is also quoted by Koffka.”

    In reality, this “self-objection” was made by Benussi as early as 1907. In an unpublished manuscript of that year (Zur Einführung in das Arbeitsgebiet experimentalpsychologischer Forschung [Introduction to the Field of Study of Experimental-Psychological Research], 1907, Benussi Archive, box 2, file 2) Benussi, starting from a further variation of the experiment described above, concluded: “The inadequacy of a colour is greater, the less one can abstain from perceiving the colour of the background while observing it.” This was a clear admission of the influence of the subjective setting on the phenomenon of antagonist chromatic contrast, which Benussi at all other times cited as a paradigmatic example of the presentational inadequacy of sensory origin.

  108. 108.

    Benussi Archive, Notes, box 16, file 22.

  109. 109.

    Metzger 1954, p. 82: “Gestalt theory is […] not at all ‘opposed to attention’. Careful readers cannot have had the impression that it regards subjects or their organs of perception as a ‘tabula rasa’ or a wax plate, into which stimuli simply ‘imprint’ something. […] Rather, in this theory, the effects of attention, of the direction of observations, of modes of apprehension, have a very definite place, as special cases of the effect of the whole on the parts (Ganzbestimmtheit der Teile). Again, it merely opposes the unjustified claims of theories of perception based on attention, observation, and comprehension, which are not to be preferred to other, just as possible theories, without first thoroughly examining the domains in which they are valid.”

  110. 110.

    In the first article of the new journal, Stern outlined the nature and the tasks of “Applied Psychology” (Stern 1903) and also coined the term Psychotechnik. In 1908, Stern turned the journal into the Zeitschrift für angewandte Psychologie und psychologische Sammelforschung (Journal of Applied Psychology and Psychological Collective Research), that he directed with Otto Lipmann. This became the organ of the homonymous Institut für angewandte Psychologie und psychologische Sammelforschung (Institute of Applied Psychology and Psychological Collective Research), founded two years earlier, with the support of the Gesellschaft für experimentelle Psychologie (Society for Experimental Psychology), of which Stern was director and Lipmann secretary.

  111. 111.

    A part of Krafft-Ebing’s research was on the relationship between psychiatry and criminal law. Already during his Strasbourg period, Krafft-Ebing published the Grundzüge der Kriminalpsychologie (Principles of Criminal Psychology) (Krafft-Ebing 1872) followed, in 1875, by the massive Lehrbuch der gerichtlichen Psychopathologie (Textbook of Judicial Psychopathology) (Krafft-Ebing 1875).

  112. 112.

    It is perhaps no coincidence that criminology, which entails a close interdisciplinary collaboration especially between law and psychology, came to light in Austria during the late nineteenth century. It was in fact during that period, and especially in Austria, that the traditional idea of a subject with a personal autonomy was questioned. The Ego, traditionally conceptualised as a rational, unitary and autonomous entity, gradually came to be conceived as intrinsically interwoven with forces and demands not under its control, thus leading to its malleability and dissolution. It becomes less and less capable of attributing sense to the world in a meaningful way, by selecting and ordering the multiplicity of realities, as well as by consistently shaping itself through arts, sciences and law. Not only psychoanalysis undermined the comforting image of the self as guided by rational forces; this idea permeated literature (one need only think of Hofmannsthal and Musil), art (the Viennese Secession) and the first Austrian twentieth-century philosophy (see Ernst Mach). This crisis of the subject was a theme in literature, philosophy and art during the early twentieth century, having great implications for key concepts in criminal law. Guilt, responsibility and imputability, fraud and crime presuppose a strong and conscious Ego, a subject able to make rational and responsible decisions. Gross and other jurists felt that the law, and particularly criminal law, needed to move beyond the crisis, beyond an awareness of the “dissolution” of the Ego. It had to attempt to (re)-construct the possibility of founding individuals’ personal responsibility for actions and omissions – an aspiration that could only take place with the contribution of scientific knowledge – in the first instance that of psychological science. This involved a commitment of jurists to reforming and improving the definitions of their categories, making them more appropriate to the new psychosocial context, without giving up the essential governing and regulating functions of the law.

  113. 113.

    Gross himself published a contribution on Tatbestandsdiagnostik (Gross 1905a).

  114. 114.

    From this point of view, Wertheimer and Klein can be considered as the most remote forerunners of the lie-detector test, even though they mainly considered psychological symptoms, rather than physiological (or psychophysiological) symptoms to indicate falsehood.

  115. 115.

    Wertheimer would devote numerous other contributions to the psychological diagnosis of a fact, from his doctoral thesis (Wertheimer 1905), submitted in Würzburg at the Institute of Psychology directed by Külpe, to the research carried out in collaboration with Otto Lipmann (Lipmann and Wertheimer 1908).

  116. 116.

    “The Associations of Normal Subjects” (Experimentelle Untersuchungen über Assoziationen Gesunder) (Jung and Riklin 1904–1905), Jung’s first and most important contribution on this subject, indicated that the Swiss psychiatrist was a rigorous scholar in terms of methodology, and extremely attentive on an epistemological level. Jung described in detail how he attempted to avoid systematic errors and influences of the experimental context; how he introduced interfering variables (background noise, etc.); how the differences in the results obtained by individuals who were more or less educated, male or female could be interpreted; what kinds of inferences could be legitimately made from the results, and so on.

  117. 117.

    Benussi Archive, Lessons, 1926/27, box 12, file 7.

  118. 118.

    Benussi Archive, Lessons, 1920, box 7, file 14.

  119. 119.

    Benussi referred here explicitly to Meinong’s observations on lies (Meinong 1910, pp. 116–120).

  120. 120.

    The unreliability of opinions was particularly evident in the cases in which almost all experts believed they had witnessed a lie, simply because the subject was confused while speaking. Benussi commented: “How often does an examining magistrate find himself a similar situation when, just like most people, he only uses logical deductions as a criterion of truth but not expression, voice, or attitude, etc.! The significance of sincerity, which one ascribes to contradiction, in its exclusiveness is only based on psychological ignorance.” (Benussi 1914b, p. 252; Eng. 58) It should also be taken into consideration that experts tend to consider true statements to be false rather than false statements to be true. “This implies the expression of a non-humanitarian trait which, perhaps, in reality is more common than we are generally inclined to believe.” (Ibid., p. 253; Eng. 58)

  121. 121.

    In Benussi’s experiments, respiratory diagnosis failed only in a single case of truthful testimony and in one untruthful case, because of accidental abnormalities which could be attributed to the specific experimental context.

References

  • Abe, M. (1935). Experimental study on the co-relation between space and time. Tohoku Psychologica Folia, 3, 53–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abe, M. (1936). The spatial effect upon the perception of time. Japanese Journal of Experimental Psychology, 3, 1–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abe, M. (1937). The temporal effect upon the perception of space. Japanese Journal of Experimental Psychology, 4, 83–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ameseder, R. (1904). Über Vorstellungsproduktion. In A. Meinong (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie (pp. 481–508). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aschaffenburg, G. (1903). Das Verbrechen und seine Bekämpfung. Einleitung in die Kriminalpsychologie für Mediziner, Juristen und Soziologen. Ein Beitrag zur Reform der Strafgesetzgebung. Heidelberg: C. Winter. 2nd ed. Heidelberg: C. Winter, 1906. Eng. transl. Crime and its repression. Boston: Little, Brown, and Company, 1913.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ash, M. G. (1995). Gestalt psychology in German culture, 1890–1967: Holism and the quest for objectivity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bachhiesl, C. (2007). Hans Gross und die Anfänge einer naturwissenschaftlich ausgerichteten Kriminologie. Archiv für Kriminologie, 219, 46–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1902). Ueber den Einfluß der Farbe auf die Größe der Zöllner’schen Täuschung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 29, 264–351; 385–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1904). Zur Psychologie des Gestalterfassens (Die Müller-Lyersche Figur). In A. Meinong (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie (pp. 303–448). Leipzig: J. A. Barth. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 3–138). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V (1905a). La natura delle cosidette illusioni ottico-geometriche. In S. De Sanctis (Ed.), Atti del V Congresso Internazionale di Psicologia (pp. 262–267). Rome: Forzani. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Sperimentare l’inconscio. Scritti (1905–1927), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 129–135). Milan: Raffaello Cortina, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1905b). Gli atteggiamenti intellettivi elementari ed i loro oggetti. In S. De Sanctis (Ed.), Atti del V Congresso Internazionale di Psicologia Psicologia (pp. 440–445). Rome: Forzani. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Sperimentare l’inconscio. Scritti (1905–1927), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 147–153). Milan: Raffaello Cortina, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1906a). Experimentelles über Vorstellungsinadäquatheit. I. Das Erfassen gestaltmehrdeutiger Komplexe. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 42, 22–55. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 155–188). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1906b). Die Psychologie in Italien. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 7, Literaturbericht, 141–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1907a). Experimentelles über Vorstellungsinadäquatheit. II. Gestaltmehrdeutigkeit und Inadäquatheitsumkehrung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 45, 188–230. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 188–228). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1907b). Zur experimentellen Analyse des Zeitvergleichs. I. Zeitgröße und Betonungsgestalt. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 9, 366–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1908). Zur experimentellen Analyse des Zeitvergleichs. II. Erwartungszeit und subjektive Zeitgröße. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 13, 71–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1909). Über “Aufmerksamkeitsrichtung” beim Raum- und Zeitvergleich. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 51, 73–107. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 229–261). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1910). Über die Grundlagen des Gewichtseindruckes (Beiträge zur Psychologie des Vergleichens). Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 17, 1–185.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1911). Über die Motive der Scheinkörperlichkeit bei umkehrbaren Zeichnungen. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 20, 363–396. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 263–295). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1912). Stroboskopische Scheinbewegungen und geometrisch-optische Gestalttäuschungen. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 24, 31–62. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 297–328). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1913a). Psychologie der Zeitauffassung. Heidelberg: Winter (Die Psychologie in Einzeldarstellungen, ed. by H. Ebbinghaus and E. Meumann, Vol. 6). Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band II. Psychologie der Zeitauffassung (1913), ed. by M. Antonelli. Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 35).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1913b). Sintomi respiratori della finzione. Rivista di Psicologia, 9, 292–293.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1914a). Gesetze der inadäquaten Gestaltauffassung (Die Ergebnisse meiner bisherigen experimentellen Arbeiten zur Analyse der sogen. geometrisch-optischen Täuschungen [Vorstellungen außersinnlicher Provenienz]). Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 32, 396–419. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 341–364). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1914b). Die Atmungssymptome der Lüge. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 31, 244–273. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 365–394). Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34). Eng. transl., The respiratory symptoms of lying. Polygraph 4(1), 1975, 52–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1914c). Review. Koffka, K., Kenkel, K., “Beiträge zur Psychologie der Gestalt- und Bewegungserlebnisse”, Zeitschr. f. Psychol., Abt. I., 67 (1914), pp. 353–449. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 32, Literaturbericht, 50–57. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Psychologische Schriften. Textkritische Ausgabe in 2 Bänden. Band I. Psychologische Aufsätze (1904–1914), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 329–339). Amsterdam-New York: Rodopi, 2002 (Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie, Vol. 34).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1914d). Kinematohaptische Scheinbewegungen (KSB) und Auffassungsumformung. In F. Schumann (Ed.), BerichVt über den VI. Kongreß für experimentelle Psychologie in Göttingen 1914 (pp. 31–35). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1914e). Versuche zur Bestimmung der Gestaltzeit. In F. Schumann (Ed.), Bericht über den VI. Kongreß für experimentelle Psychologie in Göttingen 1914 (pp. 71–73). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1917). Versuche zur Analyse taktil erweckter Scheinbewegungen (kinematohaptische Erscheinungen) nach ihren äußeren Bedingungen und ihren Beziehungen zu den parallelen optischen Phänomenen. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 36, Literaturbericht, 59–135.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1918b). Lüge und Aufrichtigkeitsdiagnose. Der Friede, 1(15), 359–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1918c). Über den freien Willen. Der Friede, 2(34), 178–181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1922–1923). Introduzione alla psicologia sperimentale. Lezioni tenute nell’anno 1922–23 dal Prof. V. Benussi e raccolte dal Dott. C. L. Musatti (Typescript, FBP, 5).

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1925a). La suggestione e l’ipnosi come mezzi di analisi psichica reale. Zanichelli, Bologna. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Sperimentare l’inconscio. Scritti (1905–1927), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 213–350). Milan: Raffaello Cortina, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1925b). La suggestione e l’ipnosi come mezzi di analisi psichica reale. In Società italiana di psicologia (Ed.), Atti del IV Congresso Nazionale di Psicologia (Firenze 1923) (pp. 35–65). Florence: Stabilimento Tipografico Bandettini. Printed also in Rivista di Psicologia, 21, 1–22. Reprinted in V. Benussi, Sperimentare l’inconscio. Scritti (1905–1927), ed. by M. Antonelli (pp. 191–211). Milan: Raffaello Cortina, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V., & Liel, W. (1904). Die verschobene Schachbrettfigur. In A. Meinong (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie (pp. 449–472). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biceaga, V. (2010). The concept of passivity in Husserl’s phenomenology. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Binet, A. (1899). La suggestibilité du point de vue de la psychologie individuelle. L’Année psychologique, 5, 82–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Binet, A. (1900). La suggestibilité. Paris: Schleicher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binet, A. (1905). La science du témoignage. L’Année psychologique, 11, 128–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, F. E. (1896). The accuracy of recollection and observation. Psychological review, 3, 286–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bozzi, P. (1980). Presentazione. In G. Kanizsa (Ed.), Grammatica del vedere. Saggi su percezione e gestalt (pp. 7–22). Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bozzi, P. (1985). La corrente della coscienza, ovvero i fatti sotto osservazione. Teorie & Modelli, 2(1), 5–38. Reprinted in P. Bozzi, Fenomenologia sperimentale (pp. 235–273). Bologna: Il Mulino, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brand, G. (1969). Welt, Ich und Zeit: nach unveröffentlichten Manuskripten Edmund Husserls. The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874a). Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Leipzig: Dunker & Humblot. Reprinted in F. Brentano, Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Von der Klassifikation psychischer Phänomene (pp. 1–289). Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 2008 (Franz Brentano, Sämtliche veröffentlichte Schriften, Vol. 1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874b). Über die Gründe der Entmutigung auf philosophischem Gebiete. Vienna: Braumüller. Reprinted in F. Brentano, Über die Zukunft der Philosophie, ed. and introduced by O. Kraus (pp. 83–100). Leipzig: Meiner, 1929. New edition ed. by P. Weintgartner, Hamburg: Meiner, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1892). Über ein optisches Paradoxon. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 3, 349–358. Reprinted in F. Brentano, Untersuchungen zur Sinnespsychologie, 2nd expanded edition ed. by Roderick Chisholm and R. Fabian (pp. 136–142). Hamburg: Meiner, 1979. Reprinted in F. Brentano, Schriften zur Sinnespsychologie (pp. 1–12). Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 2009 (Franz Brentano, Sämtliche veröffentlichte Schriften, vol. 2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1894). Zur Lehre von den optischen Täuschungen. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 6, 1–7. Reprinted in F. Brentano, Untersuchungen zur Sinnespsychologie, 2nd expanded edition ed. by Roderick Chisholm and R. Fabian (pp. 104–113). Hamburg: Meiner, 1979. Reprinted in F. Brentano, Schriften zur Sinnespsychologie (pp. 37–45). Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 2009 (Franz Brentano, Sämtliche veröffentlichte Schriften, Vol. 2).

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. ([1887–1901] 1982). Deskriptive Psychologie, ed. by R. M. Chisholm and W. Baumgartner. Hamburg: Meiner. Eng. transl. by B. Müller, Descriptive Psychology. London: Routledge, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1907). Tatsachen und Probleme zu einer Psychologie der Denkvorgänge. I. Über Gedanken. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 9, 297–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bühler, K. (1913). Die Gestaltwahrnehmungen. Experimentelle Untersuchungen zur psychologischen und ästhetischen Analyse der Raum- und Zeitanschauung. Stuttgart: Spemann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cattell, J. M. K. (1895). Measurements of the accuracy of recollection. Science, 2, 761–766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. M. (1981). Brentano’s analysis of the consciousness of time. Midwest studies in philosophy, 6, 3–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., Hansel, C. E. M., & Sylvester, J. D. (1953). A new phenomenon in time judgment. Nature, 172, 901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J., Hansel, C. E. M., & Sylvester, J. D. (1954). Interdependence of temporal and auditory judgements. Nature, 174, 642–644.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Claparède, É. (1905). La psychologie judiciaire. L’Année psychologique, 11, 275–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Sanctis, S. (1927/28). Commemorazione del Prof. Vittorio Benussi. Annuario della Regia Università di Padova, 241–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1903). Studies in logical theory. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ebbinghaus, H., & Dürr, E. (1911). Grundzüge der Psychologie, 3rd ed. in two vols. Leipzig: Veit.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellenberger, H. F. (1970). The discovery of the unconscious. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1906). Tatbestandsdiagnostik und Psychoanalyse. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 26, 1–10. Eng. transl., Psycho-analysis and the establishment of the facts in legal proceedings, in J. Strachey, The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (1906–1908) (Vol. 9, pp. 103–114). London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psychoanalysis, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelb, A. (1911). Theoretisches über “Gestaltqualitäten”. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 58, 1–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gelb, A. (1914). Versuche auf dem Gebiete der Zeit- und Raumanschauung. In F. Schumann (Ed.), Bericht über den VI. Kongreß für experimentelle Psychologie in Göttingen vom 15. bis 18. April 1914 (pp. 36–42). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grassberger, R. (1956). Pioneers in criminology. XIII – Hans Gross (1847–1915). Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology, and Police Science, 47(4), 397–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1893). Handbuch für Untersuchungsrichter, Polizeibeamte, Gendarmen, usw. Graz: Leuschner & Lubensky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1898). Criminalpsychologie. Graz: Leuschner & Lubensky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1899). Handbuch für Untersuchungsrichter als System der Kriminalistik (3rd ed.). Graz: Leuschner & Lubensky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1901). Review. Sigmund Freud, Ueber den Traum, Wiesbaden: Bergmann, 1901. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 10, 340–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1904). Review. Jos. Breuer/Sigm. Freud, Leipzig/Wien: Fr. Deutike. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 15, 138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1905a). Zur psychologischen Tatbestandsdiagnostik. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 19, 49–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1905b). Antrittsvorlesung, gehalten an der Carola Franziska in Graz am 25. Oktober 1905. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 21, 169–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1905c). Review. Sigmund Freud, Zur Psychopathologie des Alltagslebens, Berlin: S. Karger, 1904. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 18, 271–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (1914). Review. Sigmund Freud, Totem und Tabu, Leipzig-Wien: Hugo Heller & Co., 1913. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 56, 373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, A. (1964). The field of consciousness. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heider, F. (1983). The life of a psychologist: An autobiography. Lawrence: University of Kansas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Held, K. (1966). Lebendige Gegenwart: die Frage nach der Seinsweise des transzendentalen Ich bei Edmund Husserl, entwickelt am Leitfaden der Zeitproblematik. The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Helson, H. (1930). The tau effect: An example of psychological relativity. Science, 71, 536–537.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helson, H., & King, S. M. (1931). The tau effect: An example of psychological relativity. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 14, 202–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holenstein, E. (1972). Phänomenologie der Assoziation: zu Struktur und Funktion eines Grundprinzips der passiven Genesis bei E. Husserl. The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, G. (1951). Thinking. An introduction to its experimental psychology. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1900–1901). Logische Untersuchungen, 2 vols. Vol. 1 ed. by E. Holenstein. Vol. 2, in two Parts, ed. by U. Panzer. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1975–1984 (Husserliana, XVIII, XIX/1, XIX/2). Eng. transl. by J.N. Findlay, Logical Investigations, 2 vols. New York, Humanities Press, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1928). Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins, ed. by M. Heidegger. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 9, 367–498. Reprinted in Husserliana, X: Zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins (1893–1917), ed. by R. Boehm. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1966. Eng. transl. by J. B. Brough, On the phenomenology of the consciousness of internal time (1893–1917). The Hague: Kluwer, 1991.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1948). Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik, ed. by L. Landgrebe. Meiner: Hamburg. Eng. transl. by J. Churchill and K. Ameriks, Experience and judgment. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1966). Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Aus Vorlesungs- und Foschungsmanuskripten (1918–1926), ed. by M. Fleischer. The Hague: Nijhoff (Husserliana, XI). Eng. transl. by A. J. Steinbock, Analyses Concerning Passive and Active Synthesis: Lectures on Transcendental Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität: Texte aus dem Nachlass. Dritter Teil: 1929–1935, ed. by I. Kern. The Hague: Nijhoff, 1973. (Husserliana, XV).

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1905a). Zur psychologischen Tatbestandsdiagnostik. Zentralblatt für Nervenheilkunde und Psychiatrie, 16, 813–815. Eng. transl., On the psychological diagnosis of facts. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 1, pp. 219–221). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1905b). Über das Verhalten der Reaktionszeit beim Assoziationsexperimente. Journal für Psychologie und Neurologie, 6(1), 1–36. Eng. transl., The reaction-time ratio in the association experiment. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 221–271). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1905c). Die psychologische Diagnose des Tatbestandes. Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Strafrecht, 18, 369–408. Eng. transl., The psychological diagnosis of evidence. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung (Vol. 2, pp. 318–352). 2nd ed., Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1906a). Psychoanalyse und Assoziationsexperiment. Journal für Psychologie und Neurologie, 7(1–2), 1–24. Eng. transl., Psychoanalysis and association experiments. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 288–317). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1906b). Die psychopathologische Bedeutung des Assoziationsexperimentes. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 22(2–3), 145–162. Eng. transl., The psychopathological significance of the association experiment. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 408–425). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1907a). Über die Reproduktionsstörungen beim Assoziationsexperiment. Journal für Psychologie und Neurologie, 9(4), 188–197. Eng. transl., Disturbances of reproduction in the association experiment. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 426–438). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1907b). On the psychophysical relations of the association experiment. The Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 1(6), 247–255. Reprinted in Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 483–491). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1907c). Über die Psychologie der Dementia praecox: Ein Versuch. Halle a S.: Marhold. Eng. transl., The psychology of dementia praecox. 1. Critical survey of theoretical views on the psychology of dementia praecox. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 3, pp. 1–37). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1909). Die Assoziationsmethode. Manuscript. Eng. transl., The association method. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 439–465). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1910). Die an der Psychiatrischen Klinik in Zürich gebräuchlichen psychologischen Untersuchungsmethoden. Zeitschrift für angewandte Psychologie, 3, 390. Eng. transl., The psychological methods of investigation used in the psychiatric clinic of the University of Zurich. In Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, p. 597). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1911). On the doctrine of complexes. Australasian Medical Congress, Transactions of the Ninth Session, II, Part 8, 835–839. Reprinted in Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 598–604). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1961). Erinnerungen, Träume, Gedanken. Aufgezeichnet und herausgegeben von Aniela Jaffé. Olten: Walter. Eng. transl. by R. & C. Winston, Memories, dreams, reflections. Recorded and edited by A. Jaffé. New York: Vintage Books, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G., & Peterson, F. (1907). Psychophysical investigations with the galvanometer and pneumograph in normal and insane individuals. Brain. A Journal of Neurology, 30(2), 153–218. Reprinted in Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 492–553). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G., & Ricksher, C. (1907/08). Further investigations on the galvanic phenomenon in normal and insane individuals. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 2(5), 189–217. Reprinted in Collected Works of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 554–580). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G., & Riklin, F. (1904–1905). Experimentelle Untersuchungen über Assoziationen Gesunder. Journal für Psychologie und Neurologie, 3(1), 55–83; 3(4), 145–164; 3(5), 193–214; 3(6), 283–308; 4(1–2), 24–67. Eng. transl., The associations of normal subjects. In Collected sWorks of C. G. Jung, 2nd ed. (Vol. 2, pp. 3–196). Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanizsa, G. (1952). Legittimità di una analisi del processo percettivo fondata su una distinzione in “fasi” o “stadi”. Archivio di Psicologia. Neurologia e Psichiatria, 13, 292–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kastil, A. (1939). Zeitanschauung und Zeitbegriffe. In R. Fürth (Ed.), Naturwissenschaft und Metaphysik. Abhandlungen zum Gedächtnis des 100. Geburtstages von Franz Brentano (pp. 81–107). Brünn/Leipzig: Rohrer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keiler, P. (1980). Isomorphie-Konzept und Wertheimer-Problem. Beiträge zu einer historisch-methodologischen Analyse des Köhlerschen Gestaltansatzes. Gestalt Theory, 2, 78–112.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kern, I. (1964). Husserl und Kant: eine Untersuchung über Husserls Verhältnis zu Kant und zum Neukantianismus. The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • King, D. B., & Wertheimer, M. (2005). Max Wertheimer and Gestalt theory. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K. (1914). Die Psychologie der Wahrnehmung. Die Geisteswissenschaften, 1(26), 711–716; 1(29), 796–800.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K. (1915). Beiträge zur Psychologie der Gestalt- und Bewegungserlebnisse. III. Zur Grundlegung der Wahrnehmungspsychologie. Eine Auseinandersetzung mit V. Benussi. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 73, 11–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt psychology. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Koffka, K., & Kenkel, F. (1913). Beiträge zur Psychologie der Gestalt- und Bewegungserlebnisse. I. Untersuchungen über den Zusammenhang zwischen Erscheinungsgröße und Erscheinungsbewegung bei einigen sogenannten optischen Täuschungen. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 67, 353–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1913). Über unbemerkte Empfindungen und Urteilstäuschungen. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 66, 51–80. Eng. transl., On unnoticed sensations and errors of judgement. In M. Henle (Ed.), The selected papers of Wolfgang Köhler (pp. 13–39). New York: Liveright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1920). Die physischen Gestalten in Ruhe und im stationären Zustand. Braunschweig: Vieweg.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1925). Komplextheorie und Gestalttheorie. Psychologische Forschung, 6, 358–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1933). Psychologische Probleme. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, W. (1947). Gestalt Psychology. An introduction to new concepts in modern psychology. New York: Liveright.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraus, O. (1930). Zur Phänomenognosie des Zeitbewußtseins. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 75, 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühn, R. (1998). Husserls Begriff der Passivität: zur Kritik der passiven Synthesis in der genetischen Phänomenologie. Freiburg i. Br.-Munich: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larguier des Bancels, J. (1906). La psychologie judiciaire. L’Année psychologique, 12, 157–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, A. G. L. (1892). Die Hauptgesetze des menschlichen Gefühlslebens. Eine experimentelle und analytische Untersuchung über die Natur und das Auftreten der Gefühlszustände nebst einem Beitrage zu deren Systematik. Leipzig: Reisland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, A. G. L. (1899–1905). Die körperlichen Äußerungen psychischer Zustände, 3 vols. Leipzig: Reisland; Vol. 1. Plethysmographische Untersuchungen, 1899. Teil 1: Text. Teil 2: Atlas; Vol. 2. Die physischen Äquivalente der Bewusstseinserscheinungen, 1901; Vol. 3. Elemente der Psychodynamik, 1905. Teil 1: Text. Teil 2: Atlas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, A. G. L. (1906). Lehrbuch der psychologischen Methodik. Leipzig: Reisland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann, A. G. L. (1912). Grundzüge der Psychophysiologie. Eine Darstellung der normalen, generellen und individuellen Psychologie. Leipzig: Reisland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindenfeld, D. F. (1980). The Transformation of positivism. Alexius Meinong and European thought, 1888–1920. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linke, P. F. (1907). Die stroboskopische Täuschungen und das Problem des Sehens von. Bewegungen. Psychologische Studien, 3, 393–545.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linke, P. F. (1915). Das Paradoxe Bewegungsphänomen und die ‘neue’ Wahrnehmungslehre. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 33, 261–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linke, P. F. (1916). Phänomenologie und Experiment in der Frage der Bewegungsauffassung. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 2, 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Linke, P. F. (1918). Grundfragen der Wahrnehmungslehre. Untersuchungen über die Bedeutung der Gegenstandstheorie und Phänomenologie für die experimentelle Psychologie. Munich: Reinhardt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipmann, O. (1908). Grundriss der Psychologie für Juristen. Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipmann, O., & Wertheimer, M. (1908). Tatbestandsdiagnostische Kombinationsversuche. Zeitschrift für Angewandte Psychologie und psychologische Sammelforschung, 1, 119–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marbe, K. (1913a). Grundzüge der forensischen Psychologie. Munich: Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marbe, K. (1913b). Psychologische Gutachten zum Prozess wegen des Müllheimer Eisenbahnunglücks. Fortschritte der Psychologie und ihrer Anwendungen, 1, 339–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marhaba, S. (1981). Lineamenti della psicologia italiana: 1870–1945. Florence: Giunti.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1899). Über Gegenstande höherer Ordnung und deren Verhältnis zur inneren Wahmehmung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 21, 182–272. Reprinted in Gesamtausgabe, II, 377–471. Eng. transl. by M.-L. Schubert Kalsi, On objects of higher order and their relationship to internal perception. In A. Meinong, On objects of higher order and Husserl’s phenomenology, ed. by M.-L. Schubert Kalsi (pp. 137–208). The Hague/Boston/London: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1904b). Über Gegenstandstheorie, in A. Meinong (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie (pp. 1–50). Leipzig: J. A. Barth Reprinted in Gesamtausgabe, II, 481–530. Eng. transl. by I. Levi, D. B. Terrell, and R. M. Chisholm, The theory of objects. In R. M. Chisholm (Ed.), Realism and the background of phenomenology (pp. 76–117). Glencoe, IL, Free Press, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1906/1907). Über die Stellung der Gegenstandstheorie im System der Wissenschaften. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 129, 48–94; 155–207; 130, 1–46. Reprinted in Gesamtausgabe, V, 197–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1906). Über die Erfahrungsgrundlagen unseres Wissens, Berlin: J. Springer (Abhandlungen zur Didaktik und Philosophie der Naturwissenschaft. Sonderhefte der Zeitschrift für physikalischen und chemischen Unterricht, I, 6, 379–491). Reprinted in Gesamtausgabe, V, 367–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1910). Über Annahmen. Zweite, umgearbeitete Auflage. Leipzig: J. A. Barth. Reprinted in Gesamtausgabe, IV, 1–389; 517–535. Eng. transl. by J. Heanue, On Assumptions, ed. by J. Heanue. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Messer, A. (1908). Empfindung und Denken. Leipzig: Quelle & Meyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metelli, F. (1987). La polemica Benussi-Koffka. In G. Mucciarelli (Ed.), Vittorio Benussi nella storia della psicologia italiana (pp. 119–132). Bologna: Pitagora Editrice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzger, W. (1954). Psychologie. Die Entwicklung ihrer Grundannahmen seit der Einführung des Experiments, 2nd ed. Darmstadt: Steinkopff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzger, W. (1980). Psicologia della forma. In Enciclopedia del Novecento (Vol. 4, pp. 838–846). Rome: Istituto della Enciclopedia Italiana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, I. (1984). Husserl, perception, and temporal awareness. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mülberger, A. (2009). Teaching psychology to jurists: Initiatives and reactions prior to World War I. History of psychology, 12(2), 60–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. E. (1923). Komplextheorie und Gestaltheorie. Ein Beitrag zur Wahrnehmungspsychologie. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Münsterberg, H. (1908). On the witness stand: Essays on psychology and crime. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musatti, C. (1929a). La psicologia della forma. Rivista di Filosofia, 4, 329–357. Reprinted in Aut-Aut, 89, 1965, 8–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musatti, C. (1931a). Forma e assimilazione. Archivio Italiano di Psicologia, 9, 61–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musatti, C. (1986). Il mio mondo giovanile nell’antica Padova. Belfagor, 41, 81–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papafava, N. (1947). Ricordando Benussi. Gazzettino veneto, 23.11.1947.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pupp, R. (1932). Gestalt und Beziehung im Anschluß an die österreichische Schule. Diss. Univ. München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rang, B. (1990). Husserls Phänomenologie der materiellen Natur. Frankfurt a. M: Klostermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahn, C. (1913). The relation of sensation to other categories in contemporary psychology. A study in the psychology of thinking. New York: Macmillan (The Psychological Monographs, vol. 16, 1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Römpp, G. (1992). Husserls Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität und ihre Bedeutung für eine Theorie intersubjektiver Objektivität und die Konzeption einer phänomenologischen Philosophie. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ronco, A. (1963). La scuola di Würzburg. Contributo storico-critico alla psicologia dei processi conoscitivi. Zürich: PAS-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, E. (1915a). Die visuelle Wahrnehmung von Figuren. In F. Schumann (Ed.), Bericht über den VI. Kongreß für experimentelle Psychologie in Göttingen vom 15. bis 18. April 1914 (pp. 60–63). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin, E. (1915b). Synsoplevede figurer. Studier i psykologisk analyse. København og Kristiania: Gyldendalske, Nordisk forlag. Ger. transl. Visuell wahrgenommene Figuren: Studien in psychologischer Analyse. Copenhagen: Gyldendal, 1921.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandmeyer, B. (2009). Husserl’s constitutive phenomenology: Its problem and promise. London: Routledge.Salvemini, Gaetano (1919). La questione dell’Adriatico. Florence: Libreria della Voce.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schuhmann, K. (1975). Index nominum zum Nachlaß von Edmund Husserl. Leuven.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. (1988b). Gestalt theory. An essay in philosophy. In B. Smith (Ed.), Foundation of Gestalt theory (pp. 11–81). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporer, S. L. (1982). A brief history of the psychology of testimony. Current Psychological Reviews, 2, 323–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporer, S. L. (1997). On the origins of the psychology of testimony. In C. Early, W. Bringmann, H. E. Lück, & R. Miller (Eds.), A pictorial history of psychology (pp. 476–479). Carol Stream: Quintessence Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, L. W. (1897). Psychische Präsenzzeit. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 13, 325–349. Eng. transl. by N. de Warren, Mental presence-time. In The New Yearbook for Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy, 5(1), 2005, 325–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, L. W. (1902). Zur Psychologie der Aussage. Experimentelle Untersuchungen über Erinnerungstreue. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 22, 315–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, L. W. (Ed.) (1903–1906). Beiträge zur Psychologie der Aussage. Mit besonderer Berücksichtigung von Problemen der Rechtspflege, Pädagogik, Psychiatrie und Geschichtsforschung, 2 vols. Leipzig: J. A. Barth. (I Folge: 1903–04; II Folge: 1905–06).

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, L. W. (1903/1904). Angewandte Psychologie. Beiträge zur Psychologie der Aussage, 1(1), 4–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, L. W. (1904). Die Aussage als geistige Leistung und als Verhörsprodukt. Experimentelle Schüleruntersuchungen. Beiträge zur Psychologie der Aussage, 1(3), 1–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, L. W. (1926). Jugendliche Zeugen in Sittlichkeitsprozessen. Leipzig: Quelle & Meyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Störring, G. W. (1906). Experimentelle Beiträge zur Lehre vom Gefühl. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 6, 316–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stucchi, N. (1987a). Percezione, rappresentazione e persuasione nell’attività scientifica di Vittorio Benussi. In G. Mucciarelli (Ed.), Vittorio Benussi nella storia della psicologia italiana (pp. 147–164). Bologna: Pitagora Editrice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stucchi, N. (1996). Seeing and thinking: Vittorio Benussi and the Graz School. Axiomathes, 7, 137–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taguchi, S. (2006). Das Problem des “Ur-Ich” bei Edmund Husserl: die Frage nach der selbstverständlichen “Nähe” des Selbst. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vicario, G. B. (1973). Tempo psicologico ed eventi. Florence: Giunti & Barbèra.

    Google Scholar 

  • Volpi, F. (1989). The experience of temporal objects and the constitution of time-consciousness by Brentano. In The object and its identity. Topoi Supplement, 4, 127–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Ehrenfels, C. (1890). Ueber “Gestaltqualitäten”. Vierteljahresschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie, 14, 249–292. Eng. transl. by B. Smith, On “Gestalt qualities”. In B. Smith (Ed.), Foundation of Gestalt theory (pp. 82–117). Munich/Vienna: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Krafft-Ebing, R. (1872). Grundzüge der Criminalpsychologie auf Grundlage des Strafgesetzbuchs des deutschen Reichs für Aerzte und Juristen. Erlangen: Enke.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Krafft-Ebing, R. (1875). Lehrbuch der gerichtlichen Psychopathologie. Stuttgart: Enke.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Krafft-Ebing, R. (1879/1880) Lehrbuch der Psychiatrie auf klinischer Grundlage für practische Ärzte und Studirende, 3 vols. Stuttgart: Encke.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Krafft-Ebing, R. (1886). Psychopathia sexualis: Eine klinisch-forensische Studie. Stuttgart: Enke.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Liszt, F. (1883). Der Zweckgedanke im Strafrecht. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft, 3(1), 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1905). Experimentelle Untersuchungen zur Tatbestandsdiagnostik. Archiv für die gesamte Psychologie, 6, 59–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1912). Experimentelle Studien über das Sehen von Bewegung. Zeitschrift für Psychologie, 61, 161–265. Reprinted in M. Wertheimer, Drei Abhandlungen zur Gestalttheorie (pp. 1–105). Erlangen: Palm & Enke, 1925. Eng. transl. by M. Wertheimer and K. W. Watkins, Experimental studies on seeing motion. In M. Wertheimer, On perceived motion and figural organization, ed. by L. Spillmann & M. Wertheimer (pp. 1–91). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1914). Diskussion zum Vortrag von Benussi: Kinematohaptische Scheinbewegungen und Auffassungsumformung. In F. Schumann (Ed.), Bericht über den VI. Kongreß für experimentelle Psychologie in Göttingen vom 15. bis 18. April 1914 (p. 148). Leipzig: J. A. Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1922). Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt. I. Prinzipielle Bemerkungen. Psychologische Forschung, 1, 47–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M. (1923). Untersuchungen zur Lehre von der Gestalt. II. Psychologische Forschung, 4, 301–350. Eng. transl. by M. Wertheimer and K. W. Watkins, Investigations on Gestalt principles. In M. Wertheimer, On perceived motion and figural organization, ed. by L. Spillmann & M. Wertheimer (pp. 127–182). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, M., & Klein, J. (1904). Psychologische Tatbestandsdiagnostik. Ideen zu psychologish-experimentellen Methoden zum Zweck der Feststellung der Anteilnahme eines Menschen an einem Tatbestande. Archiv für Kriminal-Anthropologie und Kriminalistik, 15, 72–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wetzell, R. F. (2000). Inventing the criminal: A history of German criminology (1880–1945). Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witasek, S. (1899). Ueber die Natur der geometrisch-optischen Täuschungen. Zeitschrift für Psychologie und Physiologie der Sinnesorgane, 19, 81–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witasek, S. (1908). Grundlinien der Psychologie. Leipzig: Dürr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundt, W. (1910). Grundzüge der physiologischen Psychologie. Sechste umgearbeitete Auflage. 2 vols. Leipzig: Engelmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yamaguchi, I. (1982). Passive Synthesis und Intersubjektivität bei Edmund Husserl. The Hague: Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Antonelli, M. (2018). The Graz Period. In: Vittorio Benussi in the History of Psychology. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-96684-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics