Skip to main content

From Aristotle to Consciousness and Intentionality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 402 Accesses

Abstract

Neo-Aristotelian accounts of the human psyche incorporate our meaningful contact with the world such that complex connectivity within the brain and between brain and world is the basis of consciousness and mental function (a “contact view”). Intelligent contact with things shapes human consciousness and cognition in ways reflecting truth-related thought and talk about the world in a context of communication, judgement, and knowledge. Human intersubjectivity thus allows us to triangulate on the objects we encounter and configure our dealings with them in communicable ways grounded in truth and falsity. Aristotle’s naturalistic view of the soul as an active, self-organising system implies that distinctively human life corresponds to a progressive integration of neural functions, enabling us to tell (in both senses) what is happening and what things really are.

I knew that seclusion and solitude were very necessary for my friend in those hours of intense mental concentration during which he weighed every particle of evidence, constructed alternative theories, balanced one against the other, and made up his mind as to which points were essential and which immaterial. (p. 205)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Mercier and Sperber (2011).

  2. 2.

    Davidson (2001).

  3. 3.

    CPR B848ff.

  4. 4.

    This is explored in Gillett (1992, esp. Chap. 4).

  5. 5.

    Wittgenstein, On Certainty, #402.

  6. 6.

    Inquiries we have as De Anima (hereinafter DA).

  7. 7.

    DA, 430a16.

  8. 8.

    It is a key feature of embodied cognition theory (Chemero, 2009; Thompson & Varela, 2001) and the product of neural integration between practically and symbolically attuned assemblies (JHJ, e.g. 1887).

  9. 9.

    Aristotle distinguishes human from animal thought in terms of truth and falsity (DA, 427b12ff).

  10. 10.

    The space of reasons is a sustained focus of McDowell’s work (1994, 1998), and the proper role of philosophy is a preoccupation of both Frege and Wittgenstein, both of whom reject the idea that logic merely follows the dispositions of human psychology (a doctrine known as “psychologism”).

  11. 11.

    The relation is explored in relation to concepts and consciousness in Gillett (1992, 2014).

  12. 12.

    Merleau-Ponty (1962, p. 157).

  13. 13.

    Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason (CPR) “discursive” is not further defined and evokes the Greek grammaticos …

  14. 14.

    Frege (1977, p. 4).

  15. 15.

    This will be discussed in Chap. 2.

  16. 16.

    The conceptually distinct rendering is in the Hugh Lawson-Tancred translation.

  17. 17.

    Wittgenstein uses “grammatical” to reflect the origins of logic in correct use of language (PI ## 90; 111) and thereby echoes an ancient Greek usage.

  18. 18.

    The concept of sedimentation is found in Merleau-Ponty (1962, p. 164ff).

  19. 19.

    McDowell (1998, p. P185-5).

  20. 20.

    McDowell (1998, p. 188).

  21. 21.

    McDowell (1998, p. 179).

  22. 22.

    McDowell (1998, p. 183).

  23. 23.

    NE 1103a20–25.

  24. 24.

    Merleau-Ponty (1973, pp. 12, 14, 16, 17, 25, 31).

  25. 25.

    Wood (2003).

  26. 26.

    Chemero uses the term “bringing forth” to denote the fact that something actual, not just ideal, is introduced.

  27. 27.

    This term is used in Dennett (1991).

  28. 28.

    The idea of a bent rule is a problem generated if there is no categorical state that ensures that a performance will always conform to what we intuitively regard as following the rule (Kripke, 1982; Gillett, 2003).

  29. 29.

    Strawson (1974). I have discussed this link in “‘Ought’ and Well-being” (Gillett, 1993).

  30. 30.

    Nussbaum, discussed in a chapter in Love’s Knowledge (1990).

References and Bibliography

  • Adams, F., Drebushenko, D., Fuller, G., & Stecker, R. (1990). Narrow content: Fodor’s folly. Mind & Language, 5(3), 214–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allport, A. (1993). Visual attention. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 631–682). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baars, B. (2002). The conscious access hypothesis: Origins and recent evidence. Trends in Cognitive Science, 6(1), 47–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartolomeo, P. (2002). The relationship between visual perception and visual mental imagery: A reappraisal of the neuropsychological evidence. Cortex, 38(3), 357–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1874 [1973]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint (L. McAlister, Trans.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1929 [1981]). Sensory and noetic consciousness (M. Schattle & L. McAlister, Trans.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (1996). Why Aristotle needs imagination. Phronesis, 41, 20–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1996). The somatic marker hypothesis and the possible functions of the prefrontal cortex. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London, 351, 1413–1429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001). Subjective, intersubjective, objective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Naccache, L. (2001). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of consciousness: Basic evidence and a workspace framework. Cognition, 79, 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Consciousness explained. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H., & Taylor, C. (2015). Retrieving realism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G. (1992). Bright air, brilliant fire: On the matter if the mind. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W. J. (2015). Mechanism and significance of global coherence in scalp EEG. Current Opinion in Biology, 23, 199–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1977). Logical investigations (P. Geach, Trans. & Ed.) Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (P. Geach & M. Black, Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1986). The essentials of psychoanalysis (J. Strachey, Trans.). Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2010). The free energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews/Neuroscience, 11, 127–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. (1992). Representation, meaning and thought. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. (1993). Ought and wellbeing. Inquiry, 36, 287–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. (1997). Husserl, Wittgenstein and the snark. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LVII, 331–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. (2008). Subjectivity and being somebody: Human identity and neuroethics (St Andrews Series on Philosophy and Public Affairs). Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G. (2014). Concepts, consciousness and counting by pigeons. Mind, 123, 1147–1153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G., & Liu, S. (2012). Free will and Necker’s cube: Reason, language and top-down control in cognitive neuroscience. Philosophy, 87(1), 29–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, G., & McMillan, J. (2001). Consciousness and intentionality. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. (1997). What emotions really are. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. (1992). Aquinas and the active intellect. Philosophy, 67, 199–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harre, R., & Gillett, G. (1994). The discursive mind. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughlings Jackson, J. (1887). Remarks on the evolution and dissolution of the nervous system. British Journal of Psychiatry, 33, 25–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1740 [1969]). A treatise of human nature (E. Mossner, Ed.). London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurford, J. R. (2003). The neural basis of predicate-argument structure. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 261–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1950 [1999]). Cartesian meditations (D. Cairns, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1954 [1970]). The crisis of European sciences and transcendental phenomenology (D. Carr, Trans.). Chicago: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1982). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy (F. Kersten, Trans.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette, D. (2004). The Cambridge companion to Brentano. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2010). Essays in the metaphysics of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • King, J. R., Jacobo, D., Faugeras, F., et al. (2013). Information sharing in the brain indexes consciousness in noncommunicative patients. Current Biology, 23, 1914–1919.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knott, A. (2012). Sensorimotor cognition and natural language syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kozma, R., Davies, J., & Freeman, W. J. (2012). Synchronized minima in ECoG power at frequencies between beta-gamma oscillations disclose cortical singularities in cognition. Journal of Neuroscience and Neuroengineering, 1(1), 11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luria, A. R. (1973). The working brain. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1998). Mind, value and reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 34, 57–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). The phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1973). Consciousness and the acquisition of language (H. Silverman, Trans.). Chicago: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San Francisco: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1982). Memory observed. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (1990). Love’s knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rist, J. (1966). Notes on Aristotle De Anima 3.5. Classical Philology, 61, 8–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. (1989). Aristotle’s psychology. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1997). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorabji, R. (1974). Body and soul in Aristotle. Philosophy, 49, 63–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. (1974). Freedom and resentment and other essays. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E., & Varela, F. (2001). Radical embodiment: Neural dynamics and consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5(10), 416–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2014). The natural history of human thinking. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. (1996). The binding problem. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 6, 171–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1999). Phenomenal consciousness: The explanatory gap as a cognitive illusion. Mind, 108, 705–726.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winch, P. (1958). The idea of a social science and its relation to philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, A. (2003). Kant and the problem of human nature. In B. Jacobs & P. Kain (Eds.), Essays on Kant’s anthropology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2003). Husserl’s phenomenology. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Gillett, G. (2018). From Aristotle to Consciousness and Intentionality. In: From Aristotle to Cognitive Neuroscience. Palgrave Pivot, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-93635-2_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics