Skip to main content

Laws Under Suspicion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Art of Legislating

Part of the book series: Legisprudence Library ((LEGIS,volume 6))

  • 303 Accesses

Abstract

The classical theory of legislation found in the concept of public interest the explanation and justification of laws. The social state was built on the premise that the market is the most natural and efficient mechanism for allocating resources, provided that certain conditions are safeguarded, such as free competition and perfect information. But when the market fails in its distributive function, the public interest demands that the state intervenes to correct such failures. The classical theory of legislation has defended that the state can and must intervene when there is a need to establish natural monopolies, when certain public assets must be guaranteed, when the market produces externalities, when the market does not have access to adequate information or when crisis situations arise. The state must also intervene legislatively to make the ideal of social justice in the community a reality. Facing this classical theory that explains the reasons for of laws, economic theory applied to law is primarily concerned with analysing the reasons why of laws. Particularly relevant in this sense is the Public Choice theory: here we analyse and criticise its methodological premises, together with the deregulatory policies and the mistrust in legislation derived from it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For Posner (1974, pp. 339–340), two factors are usually neglected which would actually improve the explanation as to why the government fails. The first one refers to the intractable character of many of the tasks assigned to regulatory agencies: they are asked the impossible, like ascertaining the costs of regulated companies or connecting their prices with their costs, and there are good reasons to believe that the right tools to measure and control such things simply do not exist. This is the first explanation to their failure. The second factor is the cost of the legislative supervision of the results produced by the agencies. The process of legislative production implies a long negotiation period that entails a very high cost. The government is left with no other option but to delegate more and more normative powers to the agencies, gradually losing control over them.

  2. 2.

    For instance, not every agency pursued initially a public interest that, as time went by, was “perverted”: some agencies where created, from their onset, to defend private interests of the regulated groups. Moreover, the theory lacks predictive potential, for it doesn’t explain what happens when the same agency regulates different industries.

  3. 3.

    The first one to suggest the idea that regulatory agencies have a life cycle that takes them to gradually subordinate the public interest to the private industries was Bernstein (1955). According to Bernstein regulatory agencies have their own “life cycle”. In the first stage of their existence they usually perform their regulatory duty zealously, but after some time they gradually lose power and degenerate to the point of being captured by the regulated groups. This idea was popularised later by Ralph Nader.

  4. 4.

    A somewhat more nuanced position is that of Downs (1973, p. 18), for whom “the organismic view of government is untrue because it is based upon a mythical entity: a state which is a thing apart” from individuals. On the other hand, the “individualistic” approach is incomplete “because it does not take coalitions into consideration”: when a small group of people ally themselves to manage the state apparatus, “we can reasonably speak of the government as a decision-maker separate from individual citizens at large”; this way “we avoid both false personification of a mental construct and an over individualistic view of society”.

  5. 5.

    Regarding the problems that free-riders pose to group dynamics, see the seminal work of Olson (1965). For Olson, rational individuals, naturally selfish, will only act in the interest of the collective if the group is very small or if they are coerced into doing so. The most rational attitude, from this perspective, is to be a social cadger.

  6. 6.

    Peltzman (1976) asks himself why do politicians offer laws, and his answer is because politicians want to maximise electoral majorities.

  7. 7.

    See e.g. Dunleavy (1991), as well as Baldwin et al. (1998).

  8. 8.

    For Downs (1962, p. 10), the struggle for power forces each politician or public servant to develop a conception of public interest which justifies his particular decisions. From the perspective of the citizen, the task of politicians or public servants is to make decisions in favor of the public interest, and therefore it is rational to demand from them public interest arguments for their decisions, even if these were taken for other reasons. From the perspective of politicians, the development of a conception of public interest and its connection with the decisions they make is a way of fighting for power by obtaining the support of the majority.

  9. 9.

    As we will see later (Chap. 5), not all Public Choice scholars share the same views on the importance of laws—see e.g. Lessig (1998) on the distinction between an “old” and a “new” Chicago School .

References

  • Albi E et al (1994) Teoría de la Hacienda Pública, 2nd edn. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Baldwin R, Scout C, Hood C (1998) Introduction. In: A reader on regulation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein MH (1955) Regulating business by independent commission. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bottomley S et al (1991) Law in context. The Federation Press, Canberra

    Google Scholar 

  • Breyer S (1982) Regulation and its reform. Harvard University Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan J (1984) Política sin romanticismo. Esbozo de una teoría positiva de la elección pública y de sus implicaciones normativas. In: El análisis económico de lo político. Lecturas sobre la Teoría de la Elección Pública. Instituto de Estudios Económicos, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan J, Tullock GG (1980) El cálculo del consenso. Fundamentos lógicos de una democracia constitucional. Espasa-Calpe, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Calabresi G (1984) El coste de los accidentes. Ariel, Barcelona

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1962) The public interest: its meaning in a democracy. Soc Res 29:1–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1973) La teoría económica de la democracia. Aguilar, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunleavy P (1991) Democracy, bucreaucracy and public choice. Harverster, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Farber D, Frickey P (1991) Law and public choice: a critical introduction. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1953) The methodology of positive economics. In: Essays in positive economics. University of Chicago Press, Chicago [Ensayos sobre economía positiva. Gredos, Madrid, 1967]

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes T (1999) Leviatán, o la materia, forma y poder de un Estado eclesiástico y civil. Alianza, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelman M (1988) On democracy-bashing: a skeptical look at the theoretical and empirical practice of the public choice movement. Va Law Rev 74:199–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lessig L (1998) The new Chicago School. J Leg Stud 27:661–691

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCormick RE, Tollison RD (1984) Análisis del Estado. In: El análisis económico de lo político. Lecturas sobre la Teoría de la Elección Pública. Instituto de Estudios Económicos, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitnick BM (1989) La economía política de la regulación. FCE, México [The political economy of regulation. Creating, designing, and removing regulatory forms. Columbia University Press, New York, 1989]

    Google Scholar 

  • Muller D, Murrell P (1986) Interest groups and the size of government. Public Choice 48:125–145

    Google Scholar 

  • Niskanen W (1971) Bureaucracy and representative government. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ogus AI (1994) Regulation. Legal form and economic theory. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson M (1965) The logic of collective action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Peltzman S (1976) Towards a more general theory of regulation. J Law Econ 19(2):211–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigou AC (1932) The economics of welfare, 4th edn. Macmillan, London [La economía del bienestar. Aguiar, Madrid, 1946]

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1973) La lógica de la investigación científica. Tecnos, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner R (1974) Theories of economic regulation. Bell J Econ Manag Sci 51(6):335–358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner R (1993) The problems of jurisprudence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau JJ (1973) El contrato social. Aguilar, Madrid

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin EL (1991) Beyond public choice: comprehensive rationality in the writing and reading of statutes. N Y Univ Law Rev 66:1–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin EL (1998) Putting rational actors in their place: economics and phenomenology. Vanderbilt Law Rev 51(6):1705–1728

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin EL (2002) Public choice, phenomenology and the meaning of modern state: keep the bathwater, but throw out that baby. Cornell Law Rev 87:309–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubin EL (2005) The conceptual explanation for legislative failure. Law Soc Inq 30(3):583–606

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schubert GA (1960) The public interest. The Free Press, Glencoe

    Google Scholar 

  • Schütz A (1962) El problema de la realidad social. Amorrortu, Buenos Aires

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorauf FJ (1961) The public interest. Adm Sci Quat 6(2):246–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler G (1971) The theory of economic regulation. Bell J Econ Manag Sci 2:3–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein CR (1990) After the rights revolution. Reconceiving the regulatory state. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W, Miers D (1991) How to do things with rules, 3rd edn. Weidenfeld & Nicholson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber M (1979) Economía y Sociedad. FCE, México

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson JQ (1980) The politics of regulation. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Zapatero Gómez, V. (2019). Laws Under Suspicion. In: The Art of Legislating. Legisprudence Library, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-23388-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-23388-4_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-23387-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-23388-4

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics