Skip to main content

Dimensions of the Bodily Creativity. For an Extended Theory of Performativity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Extended Theory of Cognitive Creativity

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 23))

Abstract

In our project the performance is a product of performativity. Performativity is the cognitive ability to produce physical or mental actions. Studying performance and studying performativity sets different scientific activities. Studying how to enhance the perfòrmances belongs to the behavioral science. On the contrary, studying performativity belongs to a general cognitive procedure that must not be confused with the description of behaviors, requiring a specific theorization in the cognitive sciences instead. The aim of this research project is to focus on the hypothesis that performativity is not a property confined to certain specific human skills, or to certain specific acts of language. Instead, the executive and motor component of cognitive behavior should be considered an intrinsic part of the physiological functioning of the mind and as endowed with self-generative power.

Performativity as a physiological tool of cognitive creativity has precise neural correlates and procedural properties. The firsts are summarized briefly in the central part of the essay. The latter are more widely discussed in the following chapters. From the point of view of procedures, instead, it is argued that performativity is a cognitive property that arises from the absence of an algorithm designed to carry out a given performance. Acting in a non-planned way, learning by trial and error, applying familiar behavioral patterns to new situations: these are just a few examples of what is performativity and of how it works. Thus, performativity is intrinsically creative because its nature is to face situations that cannot be solved by the application of already known algorithms. In a nutshell, performative creativity is a procedural system that is somewhere between what Chomsky called “rule governed creativity” and “rule-changing creativity”. Performativity however bears a peculiar kind of creativity, which is different from the one generated by the competence but still shares some features with the latter: in fact, it is a fully embodied and free-from-rules process that is carried out through trial and error, that is to say it depends on the bodily practice (locomotion, language, perception, etc.) made in everyday experience.

It is for this reason that Embodied Cognition (EC) should be the theoretical framework to explain the functioning of the performativity. EC indeed is the answer to all those cerebrocentric theories that consider only the computational function of the brain and ignore the role of the body as the main responsible for all the abilities of humans, animals and machines, describing performance just as an executive function. The EC however addresses the issue of performativity from the point of view of the individual rather than from that of the species. From this perspective it makes difficult to incorporate performativity into a general theory of cognition. Its phenomenological instances come into conflict with the naturalism of cognitive sciences. On the contrary, an extended theory of performativity cannot do without ethological and evolutionist perspectives. These perspectives are addressed in the second part of the essay, both from the point of view of the historical reconstruction and from that of the current debate.

In the light of the considerations made in the last part, the final hypothesis that we support is that performativity is not an attribute belonging to some human abilities only, nor to the faculty of language, nor to uniquely creative intelligence of homo sapiens. On the contrary, it can be defined as a fundamental element for any species’ cognitive process. From an evolutionary point of view, performativity probably developed in parallel with the structural and functional transformations occurred in homo sapiens that led to the species-specificity of language and let embodied simulation be our model of perception. For what concerns other species, performativity had a different development for any of them and led to other kinds of cognitive abilities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Abutalebi, J., Brambati, S.M., Annoni, J.M., Moro, A., Cappa, S.F., & Perani, D. (2007). The neural cost of the auditory perception of language switches: An event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging study in bilinguals. The Journal of Neuroscience, 27(50), 13762–13769.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. (2010). The coupling-constitution fallacy revisited. Cognitive Systems Research, 11, 332–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. (2014). The enactivist revolution. Avant, 5(2), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. (2015). The renaissance extended mind. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (PH) Physica. In P. H. Wicksteed & F. M. Cornford (Eds.), The physics: II vol. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. (1957)

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J.A. (1962). How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1896). Matter and memory (1896) (Trans.: N.M. Paul & W. Scott Palmer). London: George Allen and Unwin (1911).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1908). Memory of the present and false recognition. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 134–185). Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1911). Life and consciousness. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 3–36). Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1912). The soul and the body. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 37–74). Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1913). Phantasms of the living” and psychical research. In Bergson 1919 (pp. 75–103). Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1919). Mind-energy: Lectures and essays. Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berwick, R.C., & Chomsky, N. (2016). Why only us. Language and evolution. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolhuis, J., Tattersall, I., Chomsky, N., & Berwick, R. (2014). How could language have evolved? PLoS Biology, 12(8), 1–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R.A. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1), 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (2002). Flesh and machine: How robots will change us. New York: Pantheon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calvo, P., & Keijzer, F. (2009). Cognition in plants. In F. Baluska (Ed.), Plant-environment interactions: From sensory plant biology to active plant behavior (pp. 247–266). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1959). A review of B.F. Skinner’s verbal behavior. In L.A. Jakobovits, & M.S. Miron (Eds.), Readings in the psychology of the language (pp. 142–143). Prentice-Hall, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1960). Explanatory models in linguistics. In Studies in logic and the foundations of mathematics (Vol. 44, pp. 528–550).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1964). Current issues in the linguistic theory. The Hague/Paris: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1966). Cartesian linguistics: A chapter in the history of rationalist thought. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1982). A note on the creative aspect of language use. The Philosophical Review III, 1982, 423–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008a). Supersizing the mind. Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008b). Surfing uncertainty. Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Surfing uncertainty. Prediction, action and the embodied mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clowry, G.J. (2014). Seeking clues in brain development to explain the extraordinary evolution of language in humans. Language Sciences, 46, 220–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coello, C.A., Lamont, G.B., & Van Veldhuizen, D.A. (2007). Evolutionary algorithms for solving multi-objective problems. Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cook, J.Th. (1991). Spinoza’s science of the ‘idea of the body. In J.C. Smith (Ed.), Historical Foundation of Cognitive Science (pp. 81–98). Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error: Emotion, reason and the human brain. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of consciousness. Mariner Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (2004). Looking for Spinoza: Joy, sorrow, and the feeling brain. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Della Rocca, M. (2008). Spinoza. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., & De Jaegher, H. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017a). Enactivist interventions rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017b). Theory, practice and performance. Connection Science, 29(I), 106–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2018). Mindfulness and mindlessness in performance. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 1, 5–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Zahavi, D. (2008). The phenomenological mind. An introduction to philosophy of mind and cognitive science. London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • García-Moreno, F., Vasistha, N.A., Trevia, N., Bourne, J.A., & Molnár, Z. (2011). Compartmentalization of cerebral cortical germinal zones in a lissencephalic primate and gyr-encephalic rodent. Cerebral Cortex, bhr312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghazanfar, A.A., & Rendall, D. (2008). Evolution of human vocal production. Current Biology, 18(11), R457–R460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R.W. (2005). Embodiment and cognitive science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R.W. (2008). The Cambridge handbook of metaphor and thought. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. (1977). The theory of affordances. In R. Shaw & J. Bransford (Eds.), Perceiving, acting, and knowing (pp. 67–82). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2001). On the status and explanatory structure of developmental systems theory. In P. E. Griffiths & R. D. Gray (Eds.), Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution (pp. 283–298). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. (2001). Perception and action: Alternative views. Synthese, 129, 3–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., Myin, E. (2013). Radicalising enactivism. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jansen, T. (2013). Analyzing evolutionary algorithms. The computer science perspective. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaquet, C. (2004). L’unité du corps et de l’esprit. Affects, actions et passions chez Spinoza. Paris: Puf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, D., Zatorre, R.J., Milner, B., Meyer, E., & Evans, A.C. (1994). Left putaminal activation when speaking a second language: Evidence from PET. Neuroreport, 5(17), 2295–2297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ko, J.H., Antonelli, F., Monchi, O., Ray, N., Rusjan, P., Houle, S., et al. (2013). Prefrontal dopaminergic receptor abnormalities and executive functions in Parkinson’s disease. Human Brain Mapping, 34(7), 1591–1604.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors we live by. London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh. The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J. (1998). The emotional brain. The mysterious underpinnings of emotional life. Touchstone: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • LeDoux, J. (2003). Synaptic self: How our brains become who we are. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leroi-Gourhan, A. (1964). Le geste et la parole (Vol. 2) (trad: Bostock, A., Gesture and speech. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993). Paris: Albin Michel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leroi-Gourhan, A. (1983). Mécaniques vivant. Le crâne des vertébrés du poisson à l’homme. Paris: Fayard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libet, B. (2004). Mind time. The temporal factor in consciousness. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, P. (2013). The unpredictable species. What makes humans unique. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lieberman, P., & McCarthy, R. (2007). Tracking the evolution of language and speech: Comparing vocal tracts to identify speech capabilities. Expedition: The magazine of the University of Pennsylvania, 49(2), 15–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucretius, C.T. (DRN). In H.A.J. Munro & J.D. Duff (Eds.), Titi Lucreti Cari De rerum natura libri sex. London: G. Bell and Sons. (1903)

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2006). Radical Enactivism. Intentionality, phenomenology and narrative. Amsterdam: Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010). The extended mind. New Edition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Monchi, O., Petrides, M., Petre, V., Worsley, K., & Dagher, A. (2001). Wisconsin card sorting revisited: Distinct neural circuits participating in different stages of the task identified by event-related functional magnetic resonance imaging. The Journal of Neuroscience, 21(19), 7733–7741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monchi, O., Petrides, M., Strafella, A.P., Worsley, K.J., & Doyon, J. (2006). Functional role of the basal ganglia in the planning and execution of actions. Annals of Neurology, 59(2), 257–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagano-Saito, A., Leyton, M., Monchi, O., Goldberg, Y.K., He, Y., & Dagher, A. (2008). Dopamine depletion impairs frontostriatal functional connectivity during a set-shifting task. The Journal of Neuroscience, 28(14), 3697–3706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Representation in mind. Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2009). Out of our heads. Why you are not your brain. New York: Farrar-Straus-Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2015). Strange tools. Art and human nature. New York: Farrar-Straus-Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penfield, W., & Rasmussen, T. (1950). The cerebral cortex of man: A clinical study of localization of function. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A. (2006). Patologie e psicopatologie del linguaggio. In A. Pennisi & P. Perconti (Eds.), Le scienze cognitive del linguaggio. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A. (2016). Prospettive evoluzioniste nell’embodied cognition: il cervello “inquilino” del corpo. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 1(2016), 179–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A. (2017). Cosa può un corpo. Spinoza e l’Embodied Cognition, Bollettino del centro di studi filologici e linguistici siciliani, 28/2017, Special Issue In ricordo di Tullio De Mauro, F L. Piparo (Ed.) (pp. 237–264).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, G. (2017). What space for performativity in cognitive science? Insights from CODISCO 2017. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 2(2017), 381–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A. (2018a). Performative dimensions in cognitive sciences. Reti, saperi, linguaggi Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 1(2018), 25–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A. (2018b). Laicità e diritti, Scritti in onore di Demetrio Neri. In F. A. e. L. Formigari (Ed.), Spinoza, Darwin e Nietzsche. L’etica come etologia dei corpi o biopolitica (pp. 61–87). Roma: Aracne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, G. (2018). Towards a deeply embodied Enactivism. Reti, saperi, linguaggi. Italian Journal of Cognitive Sciences, 2(2018), 271–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A. (2019). Spinoza e l’Embodied Cognition, in Atti del Convegno internazionale di studi del CISPELS. Storia del pensiero linguistico e semiotico (Roma 17–19 Settembre 2018), In print Roma: Sapienza University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi, A., & Falzone, A. (2016). Darwinian biolinguistics. Theory and history of naturalistic philosophy on language. Berlin/Heidelberg/New York/Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth and history. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rakic, P. (2009). Evolution of the neocortex: A perspective from developmental biology. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(10), 724–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramachandran, V.S. (2003). The emerging mind: The Reith lectures 2003. London: Profile.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2006). Body language: Representation in action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sangiacomo, A. (2010a). Saggio introduttivo a Spinoza (Op.), pp. 7–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sangiacomo, A. (2010b). Gli strani confini della coscienza: Spinoza e gli animali. Giornale Critico di Storia delle Idee, A.2, n.4, 2010, pp. 145–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sangiacomo, A. (2011). Adequate knowledge and bodily complexity in Spinoza’s account of consciousness, Methodus, 6(2011), 77–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1979). Expression and meaning. Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L.A. (2004). The mind incarnate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L.A. (2011). Embodied cognition London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L.A. (2014). The Routledge handbook of embodied cognition London/New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simard, F., Joanette, Y., Petrides, M., Jubault, T., Madjar, C., & Monchi, O. (2010). Fronto-striatal contribution to lexical set-shifting. Cerebral Cortex, 21, 1084–1093.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skoyles, J.R., & Sagan, D. (2002). Up from dragons: The evolution of human intelligence. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1656-TIE). Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione. In Spinoza CW, pp. 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1661-KV). Korte Verhandeling van God, de Mensch, en dezself Welstand. In Spinoza CW, pp. 31–107.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1663-CM). Cogitata Metaphysica. In Spinoza CW, pp. 177–212.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (2002). (CW) Complete works. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by Michael L. Morgan, Translations by Samuel Shirley, Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1663-DCPP). Renati Des Cartes Principiorum Philosophiæ. In Spinoza CW, pp. 108–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, B. (1677-EOGD). Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata. In Spinoza CW, pp. 213–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (2010). Foundational issues in enaction as a paradigm for cognitive science: From the origin of life to consciousness and writing. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science (pp. 1–31). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thivierge, J.P., Rivest, F., & Monchi, O. (2007). Spiking neurons, dopamine, and plasticity: Timing is everything, but concentration also matters. Synapse/New York, 61(6), 375.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge MA/London: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ventura, S., & Luna, J.M. (2016). Pattern mining with evolutionary algorithms. Cham: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vico, G.B. (1710). De antiquissima Italorum Sapientia ex linguae latinae originibus eruenda. In N. Badaloni & P. Cristofolini (Eds.), GB Vico, Opere filosofiche, G. Firenze: Sansoni. (1971).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pennisi, A. (2020). Dimensions of the Bodily Creativity. For an Extended Theory of Performativity. In: Pennisi, A., Falzone, A. (eds) The Extended Theory of Cognitive Creativity. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22090-7_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22090-7_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-22089-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-22090-7

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics