Skip to main content

Realizing Epistemic Democracy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Design ((DESI))

Abstract

Many collective decisions depend upon questions about objective facts or probabilities. Several theories in social choice and political philosophy suggest that democratic institutions can obtain accurate answers to such questions. But these theories are founded on assumptions and modelling paradigms that are both implausible and incompatible with one another. I will propose a roadmap for a more realistic and unified approach to this problem.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Melioristic and optimality results are sometimes lumped together and called nonasymptotic ESC results.

  2. 2.

    See Dietrich and Spiekermann (2017) for a recent review of the ESC literature. See also Pivato (2012, 2013) for reviews of the literature on optimality results in particular.

  3. 3.

    See Pivato (2017) for a more detailed summary of this literature.

  4. 4.

    I know of only two models of epistemic social choice which include such effects: Page et al. (2007) and Bednar et al. (2010).

  5. 5.

    See e.g. Acemoğlu and Ozdaglar (2011) and Mossel and Tamuz (2017) for surveys of some interesting mathematical models of opinion dynamics. See Castellano et al. (2009) and Castellano (2012) for surveys of statistical physics models of opinion dynamics.

  6. 6.

    See Lorenz (2007) for an introduction and literature review of computer modelling of social opinion dynamics.

  7. 7.

    See List (2005), Bovens and Rabinowicz (2006), Everaere et al. (2010), Hartmann et al. (2010), Hartmann and Sprenger (2012), Bozbay et al. (2014), Ahn and Oliveros (2014) and D'Alfonso (2016) for preliminary explorations of this approach.

  8. 8.

    This is related to the (supra)Bayesian approach to opinion pooling; see Genest and Zidek (1986, Sect. 4) and Clemen and Winkler (1999; Sect. 2.2) for introductions.

  9. 9.

    See Mongin and Pivato (2017) for an elaboration of this argument. To be clear, we are here talking about the ex ante Pareto axiom (which concerns preferences over social lotteries before the resolution of uncertainty), rather than the ex post Pareto axiom (which concerns preferences over social outcomes after the resolution of uncertainty).

References

  • Acemoğlu, D., & Ozdaglar, A. (2011). Opinion dynamics and learning in social networks. Dynamic Games and Applications, 1(1), 3–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ahn, D. S., & Oliveros, S. (2014). The Condorcet jur(ies) theorem. Journal of Economic Theory, 150, 841–851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. (2005). Deliberation and voting rules. In Austen-Smith, D. & Duggan, J. (Eds.), Social Choice and Strategic Decisions: Essays in honour of Jeffrey S. Banks (pp. 269–316). Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2006). Deliberation, preference uncertainty, and voting rules. American Political Science Review, 100(2), 209–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2009). Information aggregation and communication in committees. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B: Biological Sciences, 364(1518), 763–769.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bächtiger, A., Dryzek, J., Mansbridge, J., & Warren, M. (eds.). (2018). Oxford Handbook of Deliberative Democracy. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bednar, J., Bramson, A., Jones-Rooy, A., & Page, S. E. (2010). Emergent cultural signatures and persistent diversity: A model of conformity and consistency. Rationality and Society, 22(4), 407–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berg, S. (1993). Condorcet’s jury theorem, dependency among jurors. Social Choice and Welfare, 10(1), 87–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovens, L., & Rabinowicz, W. (2006). Democratic answers to complex questions–an epistemic perspective. Synthese, 150(1), 131–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bozbay, I., Dietrich, F., & Peters, H. (2014). Judgment aggregation in search for the truth. Games and Economic Behavior, 87, 571–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castellano, C., Fortunato, S., & Loreto, V. (2009). Statistical physics of social dynamics. Reviews of Modern Physics, 81, 591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castellano, C. (2012). Social influence and the dynamics of opinions: The approach of statistical physics. Managerial and Decision Economics, 33(5–6), 311–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clemen, R. T., & Winkler, R. L. (1999). Combining probability distributions from experts in risk analysis. Risk analysis, 19(2), 187–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1986). An epistemic conception of democracy. Ethics, 97(1), 26–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Condorcet, M. (1785). Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix, Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Alfonso, S. (2016). Belief merging with the aim of truthlikeness. Synthese, 193(7), 2013–2034.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danan, Eric, Gajdos, Thibault, Hill, Brian, & Tallon, Jean-Marc. (2016). Robust social decisions. American Economic Review, 106(9), 2407–2425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti, B. (1970) [2017]. Theory of probability. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, Ltd. Translated from Italian by Antonio Machi and Adrian Smith.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deimen, I., Ketelaar, F., & Le Quement, M. T. (2015). Consistency and communication in committees. Journal of Economic Theory, 160, 24–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, Franz. (2010). Bayesian group belief. Social Choice and Welfare, 35(4), 595–626.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, Franz, & List, Christian. (2004). A model of jury decisions where all jurors have the same evidence. Synthese, 142(2), 175–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, Franz, & Spiekermann, Kai. (2013a). Epistemic democracy with defensible premises. Economics and Philosophy, 29(1), 87–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, Franz, & Spiekermann, Kai. (2013b). Independent opinions? On the causal foundations of belief formation and jury theorems. Mind, 122(487), 655–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, F., & Spiekermann, K. (2017). “Jury Theorems”. (in press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (Ed.). (1998). Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge UP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everaere, P., Konieczny, S., & Marquis, P. (2010). August. The Epistemic View of Belief Merging: Can We Track the Truth? In The 19th European Conference on Artificial Intelligence (ECAI’10) (pp. 621–626).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, J. S., & Laslett, P. (Eds.). (2003). Debating deliberative democracy. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton, F. (1907). Vox populi. Nature, 75, 450–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Genest, C., & Zidek, J. V. (1986). Combining probability distributions: a critique and an annotated bibliography. Statistical Science, 1, 114–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., Schmeidler, D., & Samet, D. (2004). Utilitarian aggregation of beliefs and tastes. Journal of Political Economy, 112, 932–938.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I. (2009). Theory of decision under uncertainty. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harsanyi, J. C. (1955). Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy, 63, 309–321. Reprinted in Essays on Ethics, Social Behavior, and Scientific Explanation. Dordrecht: P. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S., Pigozzi, G., & Sprenger, J. (2010). Reliable methods of judgement aggregation. Journal of Logic and Computation, 20(2), 603–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, S., & Sprenger, J. (2012). Judgment aggregation and the problem of tracking the truth. Synthese, 187(1), 209–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hylland, A., & Zeckhauser, R. (1979). The impossibility of bayesian group decision making with separate aggregation of beliefs and values. Econometrica, 47, 1321–1336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jost, J. T., Hennes, E. P.& Lavine, H. (2013). Hot political cognition: Its self-, group-, and system- serving purposes. In Carlson, D.E. (Ed.), Oxford handbook of social cognition 851–875. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. M. (2016). The politically motivated reasoning paradigm, part 1: What politically motivated reasoning is and how to measure it. Emerging Trends in the Social and Behavioral Sciences: An Interdisciplinary, Searchable, and Linkable Resource.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladha, K. K. (1992). The Condorcet Jury Theorem, free speech, and correlated votes. American Journal of Political Science, 36, 617–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladha, K. K. (1993). Condorcet’s jury theorem in light of de Finetti’s theorem. Majority-rule voting with correlated votes. Social Choice and Welfare, 10(1), 69–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladha, K. K. (1995). Information pooling through majority-rule voting: Condorcet’s jury theorem with correlated votes. Journal of Economic Behaviour and Organization, 26, 353–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, H. (2013). Democratic reason: Politics, collective intelligence, and the rule of the many. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landemore, H., & Elster, J. (2012). Collective wisdom: Principles and mechanisms. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • List, C. (2005). Group knowledge and group rationality: A judgment aggregation perspective. Episteme, 2(1), 25–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Quement, M., & Yokeeswaran, V. (2015). Subgroup deliberation and voting. Social Choice and Welfare, 45(1), 155–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lodge, Milton, & Taber, Charles. (2013). The rationalizing voter. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lorenz, Jan. (2007). Continuous opinion dynamics under bounded confidence: A survey. International Journal of Modern Physics C, 18(12), 1819–1838.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meirowitz, A. (2006). Designing institutions to aggregate preferences and information. Quarterly Journal of Political Science, 1(4), 373–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meirowitz, A. (2007a). Communication and bargaining in the spatial model. International Journal of Game Theory, 35(2), 251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meirowitz, A. (2007b). In defense of exclusionary deliberation: communication and voting with private beliefs and values. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 19(3), 301–327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mongin, P. (1995). Consistent Bayesian aggregation. Journal of Economic Theory, 66(2), 313–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mongin, P., & Pivato, M. (2015). Ranking Multidimensional Alternatives and Uncertain Prospects. Journal of Economic Theory, 157, 146–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mongin, P., & Pivato, M. (2017). Social preference under twofold uncertainty (preprint).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mossel, E., & Tamuz, O. (2017). Opinion exchange dynamics. Probability Surveys, 14, 155–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S., & Paroush, J. (1984). The significance of independent decisions in uncertain dichotomous choice situations. Theory and Decision, 17(1), 47–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Page, S. E., Sander, L., & Schneider-Mizell, C. (2007). Conformity and dissonance in generalized voter models. Journal of Statistical Physics, 128, 1279–1297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg, B., & Zamir, S. (2012). Extending the Condorcet jury theorem to a general dependent jury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pivato, M. (2012). A statistical approach to epistemic democracy. Episteme, 9, 115–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pivato, M. (2013). Voting rules as statistical estimators. Social Choice and Welfare, 40(2), 581–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pivato, M. (2017). Epistemic democracy with correlated voters. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 72, 51–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartzberg, Melissa. (2015). Epistemic democracy and its challenges. Annual Review of Political Science, 18, 187–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2003). The law of group polarization. In Fishkin and Laslett (pp. 80–101).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. (2009). Republic.com 2.0. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Gabriel Carroll, Franz Dietrich, Umberto Grandi, Justin Leroux, Christian List, Arianna Novaro, Kai Spiekermann, and Bill Zwicker for their very helpful comments. None of them are responsible for any errors.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marcus Pivato .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Pivato, M. (2019). Realizing Epistemic Democracy. In: Laslier, JF., Moulin, H., Sanver, M., Zwicker, W. (eds) The Future of Economic Design. Studies in Economic Design. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-18050-8_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics