Skip to main content

The Mediated Nature of Knowledge: Paul Ricoeur’s Philosophy as a Means of Teaching Students About Science and Religion

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Science and Religion in Education

Part of the book series: Contemporary Trends and Issues in Science Education ((CTISE,volume 48))

  • 504 Accesses

Abstract

Many in modern Western culture believe that science and religion are pitted against one another, at an impasse due to mutually exclusive and divergent worldviews. This assumption is based upon a problematic epistemological dichotomy in which scientific knowledge is considered concrete and certain, whereas religious knowledge is regarded as existential and experiential. Yet, such a division misrepresents both the nature of science and religion. By highlighting the mediated nature of human understanding, Paul Ricoeur’s philosophy envisages science and religion as approaches to knowledge with potentially compatible epistemological commitments. For Ricoeur, knowledge of the world is always mediated by signs and symbols; these semiotic constructs, such as language and paradigm, enable communication. Indeed, both science and religion use these tools to investigate truth and to transmit knowledge. For this reason, Ricoeur’s epistemological assertions may indicate effective methods for teaching about science and religion. Because teaching methodology ought to arise from understanding of the subject matter itself, viewing science and religion through the lens of Ricoeur’s philosophy suggests the use of particular pedagogical methods, such as visual models, narrative, and other figural means of communication, to explain scientific concepts, religious concepts, and the interaction between these disciplines. This method of teaching, far from detracting from scientific and theological enquiry, in fact mirrors the ways in which humans learn and communicate about the world they inhabit. It is also indicative of means of learning already employed by children and young adults, thereby drawing upon strengths implicit in learners.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Ian Barbour suggests that some of this conflict is brought about due to a failure ‘to distinguish between scientific and philosophical questions…These are alternative belief systems, each claiming to encompass all reality’ (1997, p. 81). Emphasis in quotations here and throughout is original unless otherwise noted.

  2. 2.

    My use of the term ‘science’ refers to the general contours of the discipline as understood in everyday parlance. In reality, the field to which it refers is widely diverse with varying epistemologies and methodologies. In this instance, it is expedient to refer to science as it is understood by the average student in Western culture.

  3. 3.

    For proponents of the conflict thesis, Barbour proposes that ‘[a]s a rough approximation, we may say that religion asks why and science asks how’ (1997, p. 82). He notes that this distinction requires clarification, yet his assessment remains broadly within a modernist framework.

  4. 4.

    Significantly, Barbour’s model makes use of typology, a way of grouping ideas based on conceptual models and hermeneutic reasoning. As will become clear, this type of reasoning is founded upon semiotic structures of communication.

  5. 5.

    This emphasis is clear in Barbour’s earlier work (1974) and reiterated, though less strongly, later (1997, pp. 106–136).

  6. 6.

    Barbour defines a model thusly: ‘Broadly speaking, a model is a symbolic representation of selected aspects of the behaviour of a complex system for particular purposes. It is an imaginative tool for ordering experience, rather than a description of the world’ (1974, p. 6).

  7. 7.

    Substantial differences exist between ways of knowing in these disciplines, but rather than rehearsing the well-trodden ground of dissimilarity, I will here focus on similarities in their epistemologies that enable beneficial cross-disciplinary dialogue. These are significant considerations to which we will later return.

  8. 8.

    Barbour suggests that a paradigm is ‘a tradition transmitted through historical exemplars’ (1974, p. 9).

  9. 9.

    Further, Harrison proposes that this is a product of ‘the distorting projection of our present conceptual maps back onto the intellectual territories of the past’ (2015, p. 4).

  10. 10.

    Harrison suggests that it is the conceptual and linguistic misapplication of these terms that has precipitated confusion (2015, pp. 183–185).

  11. 11.

    To be clear, we must note with Janet Soskice that ‘[m]etaphor is by definition a figure of speech’ (1985, p. 16). Its basis in language, however, does not preclude extension of such reasoning into the ‘world’ of the individual, as Paul Ricoeur (1973) argues. Here, perhaps, we diverge from Soskice’s view.

  12. 12.

    Cf. (Harrison 2015, p. 177). This is predominantly a modern viewpoint that hides the moral import understood by many premodern thinkers to be inherent in the subject matter that has come to be termed ‘science’ and ‘religion’. The moral framework that underlies both scientific and religious enquiry, Harrison argues, is the true source of the supposed conflict at hand (2015, pp. 178, 197).

  13. 13.

    No unique epistemology is inherent to either science or religion; however, as Harrison aptly displays, each discipline has come to be associated with specific ways of knowing.

  14. 14.

    Others have also found Ricoeur’s philosophy fertile ground for such enquiry (Gerhart and Russell 1984; Reynhout 2013). Ricoeur himself had fruitful dialogue with a neuroscientist regarding questions of theology, philosophy and science (Changeux and Ricoeur 2002).

  15. 15.

    Certainly, this also could be seen as a claim to a different sort of ideological metanarrative. For Ricoeur, a paradigmatic ideology is inescapable, but the mediated nature of knowledge does not mean that truth is inaccessible. Ricoeur maintained that the mediation of language in knowledge does not devolve into utter subjectivity (1973, p. 108). In fact, the tension between the truth described by a metaphor and the referent of the metaphor is emblematic of the dialectic nature of human existence more generally (Ricoeur 1978, p. 247).

  16. 16.

    Other scholars, such as J. Wentzel van Huyssteen (2006, p. 225), have suggested that language is a fundamental part of human uniqueness. Others see the structure of existence itself as metaphorical in nature (Lakoff and Johnson 1981).

  17. 17.

    Cf. (Ricoeur 1973).

  18. 18.

    Soskice (1985, p. 137) as well as Barbour are proponents of critical realism, which Barbour suggests ‘avoids naive realism, on the one hand, and instrumentalism, which abandons all concern for truth, on the other’ (1974, p. 11). Cf. (Barbour 1997, p. 89). Care must be taken to preserve the ontology of the relationship between the metaphor and its referent, however. The reality of this relationship is significant for the compatibility of scientific and religious knowledge and is foundational for many within both scientific and religious communities. See (Ricoeur 1984, p. xii).

  19. 19.

    Francis Bacon posits: ‘there is no proceeding in invention of knowledge but by similitude: and God is only self-like, having nothing in common with any creature, otherwise than as in shadow and trope’ (Vickers 1968, p. 153) as cited in (Soskice 1985, p. 63).

  20. 20.

    Cf. (Soskice 1985, p. 66).

  21. 21.

    Ricoeur proposes that ‘all objectifying knowledge…is preceded by a relation of belonging upon which we can never entirely reflect. Before any critical distance, we belong to a history, to a class, to a nation, to a culture, to one or several traditions. In accepting this belonging that precedes and supports us, we accept the very first role of ideology…the mediating function of the image’ (1991b, p. 267).

  22. 22.

    Alister McGrath suggests that secularity is itself a mediated, narrated interpretation of reality (2002, p. 107). In this understanding, the natural sciences are a tradition wherein scientific methodology, community and even output is influenced by social forces (2002, p. 114). Hence, McGrath argues that ‘[a]llegedly neutral, transcendent or “objective” disciplines—such as the social sciences—are in reality no more than narrated interpretations of reality which possess no privileged status permitting them to judge or police others’ (2002, pp. 118–119). Thomas Nagel (2012) further compellingly argues that a natural materialist position is not fully explanatory of human experience.

  23. 23.

    Even within the sciences, an opposition between explanation (physical science) and interpretation (social science) could be understood to exist. Ricoeur does not maintain this distinction and, in fact, sees his work as mediating between the two (Ricoeur 1981a, p. 36).

  24. 24.

    For Ricoeur, the relationship between metaphor and discourse is founded upon the polysemic nature of language in which words derive meaning contextually. Thus, just as the meaning of a word is determined through its context, so too the metaphor derives its meaning as a part of the discourse between symbol, referent and context (Ricoeur 1981b, p. 169).

  25. 25.

    For Ricoeur’s assessment of the reference of discourse, see (Ricoeur 1981b, p. 168). In Ricoeur’s thought, ‘reference’ is both ‘the intentional orientation towards a world and the reflexive orientation towards a self’ (Ricoeur 1981b, p. 171).

  26. 26.

    Ricoeur suggests that the hermeneutical circle ‘entails a sharp opposition to the sort of objectivity and non-implication which is supposed to characterise the scientific explanation of things’ (1981b, p. 165).

  27. 27.

    For example, Black (1962).

  28. 28.

    For example, Hesse (1966).

  29. 29.

    See Kuhn (1962).

  30. 30.

    Citing (Ricoeur 1982, p. 16).

  31. 31.

    McGrath, too, emphasises the importance of metaphorical conceptualisation in both science and religion (1998, pp. 165–206).

  32. 32.

    In Ricoeur’s thought, the mediation of human knowledge introduces both distortion and possibility. Some potential distortions will be considered shortly.

  33. 33.

    I will not here be able to address specific teaching strategies for the use of metaphor and analogy; I only highlight some beneficial aspects of this type of teaching and their philosophical underpinnings.

  34. 34.

    Significantly, Duit cites Kuhn’s understanding of scientific paradigms as the theoretical basis for the construction of new schemata in learning.

  35. 35.

    Cf. (Ricoeur 1981b, p. 167).

  36. 36.

    See also Midgley et al. (2013).

References

  • Barbour, I. G. (1974). Myths, models, and paradigms: A comparative study in science and religion. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, I. G. (1990). Religion in an age of science. San Francisco: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, I. G. (1997). Religion and science: Historical and contemporary issues. San Francisco: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Billingsley, B., Taber, K., Riga, F., & Newdick, H. (2013). Secondary school students’ epistemic insight into the relationships between science and religion—A preliminary enquiry. Research in Science Education, 43(4), 1715–1732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, M. (1962). Models and metaphors. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Changeux, J.-P., & Ricoeur, P. (2002). What makes us think? A neuroscientist and a philosopher argue about ethics, human nature, and the brain (DeBevoise, M.B., Trans.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duit, R. (1991). On the role of analogies and metaphors in learning science. Science Education, 75(6), 649–672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fensham, P. (2006). Foreword. In P. J. Aubusson, A. G. Harrison, & S. M. Ritchie (Eds.), Metaphor and analogy in science education (pp. v–vi). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerhart, M., & Russell, A. M. (1984). Metaphoric process: The creation of scientific and religious understanding. Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, A. G. (2006). The affective dimension of analogy. In P. J. Aubusson, A. G. Harrison, & S. M. Ritchie (Eds.), Metaphor and analogy in science education (pp. 51–63). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, P. (2015). The territories of science and religion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, A. G., & Treagust, D. F. (2006). Teaching and learning with analogies: Friend or foe? In P. J. Aubusson, A. G. Harrison, & S. M. Ritchie (Eds.), Metaphor and analogy in science education (pp. 11–24). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1966). The explanatory function of metaphor. In Models and analogies in science (pp. 157–177). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1981). Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, A. E. (1998). The foundations of dialogue in science and religion. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, A. E. (2002). A scientific theology: Volume 2: Reality. Edinburgh/New York: T&T Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Midgley, W., Trimmer, K., & Davies, A. (Eds.). (2013). Metaphors for, in and of education research. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2012). Mind and cosmos: Why the materialist neo-Darwinian conception of nature is almost certainly false. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reynhout, K. A. (2013). Interdisciplinary interpretation: Paul Ricoeur and the hermeneutics of theology and science. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1973). The model of the text: Meaningful action considered as a text. New Literary History, 5(1), 91–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1978). Rule of metaphor: Multi-disciplinary studies of the creation of meaning in language (trans: Czerny, R., McLaughlin, K., Costello, J.). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1981a). A response by Paul Ricoeur. In J. B. Thompson (Ed.), Hermeneutics and the human sciences: Essays on language, action and interpretation (pp. 32–40). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1981b). Metaphor and the central problem of hermeneutics. In J. B. Thompson (Ed.), Hermeneutics and the human sciences: Essays on language, action and interpretation (pp. 165–181). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1981c). Phenomenology and hermeneutics. In J. B. Thompson (Ed.), Hermeneutics and the human sciences: Essays on language, action and interpretation (pp. 101–128). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1981d). Toward a hermeneutic of the idea of revelation. In L. S. Mudge (Ed.), Essays on biblical interpretation (pp. 73–118). London: SPCK.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1982). Poetry and possibility: An interview with Paul Ricoeur. The Manhattan Review, 2(2), 6–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1984). Foreword. In M. Gerhart & A. M. Russell (Eds.), Metaphoric process: The creation of scientific and religious understanding (pp. xi–xiii). Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1991a). On interpretation. In From text to action: Essays in hermeneutics, II (Blamey, K., & Thompson, J.B., Trans.) (pp. 1–20). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. (1991b). Science and ideology. In From text to action: Essays in hermeneutics, II (Blamey, K., & Thompson, J.B., Trans.) (pp. 246–269). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soskice, J. M. (1985). Metaphor and religious language. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Huyssteen, J. W. (2006). Alone in the world?: Human uniqueness in science and theology. Grand Rapids: Eerdmans.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanhoozer, K. J. (1990). Biblical narrative in the philosophy of Paul Ricoeur: A study in hermeneutics and theology. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, B. (1968). Francis bacon and renaissance prose. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilbers, J., & Duit, R. (2006). Post-festum and heuristic analogies. In P. J. Aubusson, A. G. Harrison, & S. M. Ritchie (Eds.), Metaphor and analogy in science education (pp. 37–49). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

White, N.H. (2019). The Mediated Nature of Knowledge: Paul Ricoeur’s Philosophy as a Means of Teaching Students About Science and Religion. In: Billingsley, B., Chappell, K., Reiss, M.J. (eds) Science and Religion in Education. Contemporary Trends and Issues in Science Education, vol 48. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-17234-3_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-17234-3_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-17233-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-17234-3

  • eBook Packages: EducationEducation (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics