Skip to main content

Introduction: The Path of Analytical Realism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Interpretation without Truth

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 128))

  • 437 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter purports to provide in turn: (1) an account of the basic claims characterizing “realism” and “scepticism” in the philosophy of law; (2) an overview of the contents of the book; (3) an account of a few alternative ways of conceiving conceptual analysis, where a modest and reconstructive variety is put forth as worthwhile pursuing in jurisprudential enquiries.

El hoy fugaz es tenue y es eterno; otro Cielo no esperes, ni otro Infierno

—J. L. Borges (1964)

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Hart (1961), pp. 124–154; see also Hart (1977), pp. 123–143. Among the theorists who adopt the same, or a similar view, see, e.g., Carrió (1965), part II, Bulygin (1991), Marmor (2005), Moreso (1997a, b).

  2. 2.

    The literature on legal realism (rule-scepticism, realistic jurisprudence, etc.) is immense. Concerning contemporary reflection on legal realism, the reader may profit, to begin with, from essays by Brian Leiter (2007, 2012, 2013), Schauer (2013, 2018), Torben Spaak (2015), Dagan (2013, 2017, 2018), and the law-and-society jurists rallying under the banner of “New Legal Realism”—see, e.g., the papers collected for the Symposium “Is It Time for a New Legal Realism?” (“Wisconsin Law Review”, 2005), the Symposium “The New Legal Realism” (“Law & Social Inquiry”, 2006), and the two recent volumes edited by Elizabeth Mertz, Stewart Macaulay, and Thomas W. Mitchell: Mertz, Macaulay, Mitchell (2016). As it is well known, Leiter vindicates American Legal Realism against Hart’s criticism and presents it as a prototype of a naturalized jurisprudence purporting to “describe legal phenomena” as they in fact are (Leiter 2007, 2012). On the same path, the New Legal Realists advocate a genuine and thorough interdisciplinary, not imperialistic, and methodologically pluralist approach to legal knowledge, combining traditional legal scholarship’s doctrinal analysis with advanced social theory, the study of the “law in books” with the study of the “law in action” (“theory-driven empirical research about law in action that values qualitative as well quantitative and experimental research”: McCann (2016), p. xiv; Mertz (2016), p. 3: “getting formal law and the “real world” (and in particular, the reality of the law in action as it has been revealed by decades of social science) into conversation with one another”). On the Continent, realism is presently the livery of several legal theorists, some of which belonging to the “Genoa School” (see Chiassoni 1998; Ferrer and Ratti 2010; Guastini 2015, pp. 45–54; Barberis 2016, pp. 1–8).

  3. 3.

    I will come back on this thesis in chapter and Chap. 4 below.

  4. 4.

    From a conceptual standpoint, I will account for this phenomenon by means of the notion of conjectural ideological interpretation. See Chap. 2, Sect. 2.2.1.2, below.

  5. 5.

    On this subject, I will come back in Chap. 6, Sect. 6.5.4, below.

  6. 6.

    For this distinction, see Kahneman (2011), pp. 20–24. The reflective character of juristic interpretation will be argued for in this chapter, under the headings of juristic textual, meta-textual and conjectural interpretation. The reflective character of judicial interpretation will be argued for in several parts of the book (Chaps. 26).

  7. 7.

    See Chap. 6 below.

  8. 8.

    See Chap. 6 below.

  9. 9.

    Kelsen (1960), ch. VIII.

  10. 10.

    Guastini (2015, pp. 45–54) claims that judicial and most of juristic interpretation is never purely cognitive in character (never purely a matter of “knowledge”), but always involves some decision (always a matter of “will”), because legal texts, or rule-formulations (like, e.g., a constitutional provision), are indeterminate, and they are indeterminate both at the level of “abstract interpretation”, due to the ambiguity of rule-formulations, and at the level of “concrete interpretation”, due to the vagueness of the predicate terms used in rule-formulations. In other words, Guastini grounds (what we may call) his “universal decisional character” thesis about the nature of legal interpretation on a “universal indeterminacy thesis”: universal indeterminacy makes decision-making necessary, when interpreting a rule-formulation to any practical purpose. Guastini, however, affirms that rule-formulations are “often ambiguous”; furthermore, as we all know, vagueness is an intermittent phenomenon: any predicate term can be vague, but is never vague all the time, as regards to any individual case whatsoever. Such points, clearly, are to the effect of undermining the universal decisional character thesis. Accordingly, if we want to rescue it, the universal indeterminacy thesis must be rephrased, in terms of a universal methodological indeterminacy, and supplemented with further argument, coping with situations where methodological indeterminacy is reduced (overcome) by an on-going cultural (and ideological) convergence upon “one” reasonable method and result. This is what I am going to do in this book, both in the present anticipation of the basic claims of realism, and in the following chapters.

  11. 11.

    See Chap. 6, Sect. 6.3.2, below.

  12. 12.

    In turn, methodological discretion comes in two varieties: selection discretion and application discretion (see Chap. 6, Sect. 6.2, below).

  13. 13.

    See Chap. 6, Sect. 6.6, below.

  14. 14.

    On interpretive codes, see Chap. 3, Sects. 3.4, 3.5, 3.6, and Chap. 6, Sect. 6.3.2, below. In the text, I consider interpretive discretion only. Like conclusions hold for the twin activity of filling up gaps and identifying law’s “implicit” norms. On this issue, see Chap. 2, Sect. 2.2.1.2, and Chap. 7, below.

  15. 15.

    Think, for a telling instance, at the French Exegetical School (Chiassoni 2016a, ch. IV).

  16. 16.

    On these phenomena, see e.g. Celano (2016), pp. 2–16.

  17. 17.

    On judicial creation of law, the most illuminating essays are, to my knowledge, Carrió (1965), Bulygin (1966), Wróblewski (1992). The account I provide in the text takes a different stance, though. I will come back to this issue in Chap. 4 below.

  18. 18.

    When I talk of explicit norms being created by enrichment, I have in mind the situations where a given legal provision, say LP1, which is usually taken to express a certain norm, N1, is made to express also a further norm, N2 (LP1 = N1 & N2, where “=" stands for "means” or “expresses”). On the phenomenon of “complexity” in the meaning of legal provisions, see Guastini (2011a), pp. 41–42. According to Eugenio Bulygin, judges make law whenever the general norm they apply to an individual case at hand is neither identical to any already existing norm, nor a logical derivation from already existing norms (Bulygin 1966, pp. 75–87). This is a normativist approach, deliberately opaque to interpretation. Contrariwise, the five notions of judicial lawmaking I consider in the text are interpretation-transparent. These two theoretical standpoints will be considered with more detail in Chap. 7.

  19. 19.

    On this point, see Chap. 2 below.

  20. 20.

    Ferrajoli (1989), pp. 135–156; Ferrajoli (2012), pp. 216–221. The obvious reference here is also, of course, the work of Jerome Frank: see, e.g., Frank (1930), pp. 170–185, and Frank (1949a), pp. 14–36.

  21. 21.

    On judicial fiction, see Chap. 8 below.

  22. 22.

    On norms as “rhetorical consequences” of source-sentences, see Chap. 2, Sect. 2.3.3.2 below; on legislation from a realistic viewpoint, see Chap. 5, Sect. 5.2, and Chap. 11 below.

  23. 23.

    On this distinction I will come back in Chap. 7 below.

  24. 24.

    According to P. F. Strawson, who coined the expression, “revisionary metaphysics” is to be contrasted with “descriptive metaphysics”. The latter “is content to describe the actual structure of our thought about the world”, it aims “to lay bare the most general features of our conceptual structure”; the former, contrariwise, “is concerned to produce a better structure” (Strawson 1959, p. 9).

  25. 25.

    Quine (1960), pp. 271–276.

  26. 26.

    Leiter (2007), p. 183 ff.; Leiter (2012). On conceptual analysis in (and) jurisprudence, see also Endicott (2002), § 3.1, Bix (2007), pp. 1–7, Marmor (2012), pp. 1–26.

  27. 27.

    Leiter (2007), pp. 1–2: “the method of conceptual analysis via appeal to folk intuitions (as manifest, for example, in ordinary language), a method that was itself at risk of becoming an item of antiquarian interest in the context of the naturalistic revolution of late 20th century philosophy”; Leiter (2012), § 2: “The question that plagues conceptual analysis, post-Quine, is what kind of knowledge such a procedure actually yields? Why should ordinary intuitions about the extension of a concept be deemed reliable or informative? Why think the “folk” are right?”.

  28. 28.

    Leiter (2007), pp. 177–178, 196–197, where, discussing Ian P. Farrell’s defence of the Hartian search for “the concept of law” as a worthwhile piece of “modest conceptual analysis”, retorts: “But on Farrell’s (more plausible) rendering of conceptual analysis, we do not illuminate the reality, i.e., the nature of law, we illuminate, rather, the nature of our “talk” about law […] Modest conceptual analysis illuminates our concepts – our talk, as it were – not the referent we might have intended to understand” (italics in the text, ndr). See also Leiter (2012), § 2. Leiter’s criticism is in order, when, by “modest conceptual analysis”, necessary truths about aspects of reality are looked for. It does not do, contrariwise, when, following J. L. Austin’s suggestion (Austin 1956–1957, pp. 129–130), such an ambitious, and mysterious, task is put down, and a “sharpened awareness of words” is looked for in order to “sharpen our perception of the phenomena”, though “not as the final arbiter of” (italics added; the passage, without this last, quite relevant, qualification, is quoted by Hart in the opening page of the “Preface” to The Concept of Law: Hart 1961, vii). For a defence of “traditional conceptual analysis” in jurisprudence, like the one performed by Hart (1961), against Leiter’s naturalistic attack, see Himma (2007), pp. 1–23; Himma (2015), pp. 65–92. Himma’s defence, however, looks troublesome. It sets forth an apparently inconsistent view of “traditional conceptual analysis”: on the one hand, it would be just about “our” concept of law, and hence would be tied, and limited, to a contingent, changeable, local, experience. On the other hand, it would lead, mysteriously, to making metaphysical claims about the nature or essence of law in general, telling us metaphysical, necessary, truths “about not just all existing legal systems, but all conceptually possible legal systems. Thus conceived, a conceptual analysis of law consists in a set of conceptually (or metaphysically) necessary truths and thus constitutes a piece of metaphysical theorizing – just as an analysis of the concept of free will is a piece of metaphysics” (Himma 2015, § 5). In the same passage, Himma also presents Hart as a torchbearer of such a metaphysical conceptual analysis. This view, nowadays common among jurisprudents, is nonetheless disputable. See, for instance, Marmor (2012), who advocates that the basic thrust of Hart’s jurisprudence was not conceptual analysis, but reductionism. I have argued against the “essentialist” reading of Hart’s conception of conceptual analysis in Chiassoni (2012), § 2.2, and Chiassoni (2016b), pp. 61–71.

  29. 29.

    See Leiter (2007), pp. 1–2, 183–199; the basic source for intuitionist conceptual analysis is Jackson (1998), especially ch. 2.

  30. 30.

    According to Jackson, (intuitionist) “conceptual analysis” is needed, if we want to “have much of an audience”, and do not want turning “interesting philosophical debates into easy exercises in deduction from stipulative definitions together with accepted facts”. If, for instance, our problem is about free action and determinism, the only fruitful way to proceed is by asking “whether free action according to our ordinary conception, or something suitably close to our ordinary conception, exists and is compatible with determinism” (Jackson 1998, pp. 30–31, italics in the text). The ascertainment of our (or folk’s) conception of free action, in turn, requires appealing to ordinary, shared, intuitions, which reveal “our shared theory” (Jackson 1998, pp. 31–32, 46 ff.). This can be carried out by means of introspection and, above all, socio-psychological enquiries. It is worthwhile stressing that, according to Jackson, “in practice”, “the role” he is “recommending for conceptual analysis will often be very like the role Quine gives to the [Benthamite] notion of paraphrase” (Jackson 1998, p. 46). In the light of such remark, the case against “conceptual analysis” à la Jackson from Quinean perspectives seems, at least partly, the fruit of an uncharitable exaggeration.

  31. 31.

    These words, by which I characterize what I call “grand conceptual analysis”, are from Smith Churchland (2013), pp. xi–xii.

  32. 32.

    Such a conception of “linguistic frameworks” is defended, for instance, by Rudolf Carnap. In his view, many questions which are presented as “theoretical questions” (like, e.g., the question “are there natural numbers?”), should be interpreted as “practical questions, i.e., as questions about the decision whether or not to accept a language containing expressions for the particular kind of entities” at stake (italics added, ndr). In his view, “whether or not” a “linguistic framework” should be introduced depends on the purposes one is aiming at, and “is a practical question of language engineering, to be decided on the basis of convenience, fruitfulness, simplicity, and the like” (Carnap 1963, p. 66; see also Carnap 1950, pp. 205–221).

  33. 33.

    Smith Churchland (2013), pp. xi–xiv; “So what is a philosopher to do, if not troll his mind for conceptual truths? The Quinean answer is this: many things, including synthesizing across various subfields and theorizing while immersed in and constrained by available facts. Despite much hand-wringing by overwrought philosophers, Quine did not aim to put an end to philosophy, but to remind us of what the older philosophical tradition had always been: broad, encompassing, knowledgeable of everything relevant, and imaginative” (xiv, italics in the text). For a condensed account by Quine himself, see e.g. Quine (1960), pp. 275–276.

  34. 34.

    See Quine (1992), pp. 56–57.

  35. 35.

    Ian P. Farrell apparently advocates the third variety. Leiter criticizes both forms of (what I call) descriptive conceptual analysis, i.e., the grand and the modest one, while recognizing, following Larry Laudan, the usefulness of something like the modest and reconstructive variety I stand for here (see Leiter 2007, p. 183 footnote 3; see also Leiter (2007), p. 133 footnote 45, 168 ff., 179–181, where, in line with a central, though apparently overlooked, tenet of Logical Positivism, he regards philosophy as “the abstract branch of successful scientific theory […] the abstract and reflective part of empirical science”; Leiter 2008).

  36. 36.

    Austin (1956–1957), p. 130.

  37. 37.

    A more encompassing view of reconstructive conceptual analysis is propounded by Strawson (1962), pp. 112–118, who identifies five intertwining ways (“strands”) of philosophical analysis: (1) conceptual therapy, to be used for solving paradoxes and perplexities; (2) descriptive analysis, which is about the actual working of “our” conceptual and logical apparatus; (3) explanatory analysis, which puts to work philosophical imagination in order to bring to the fore the “natural foundations” of our conceptual and logical apparatus; (4) reformist metaphysics, which puts to work philosophical imagination in view of providing a new and different conceptual framework for “our” same old world; and, finally, (5) descriptive metaphysics, which purports to clarify the “general structure” of “our” conceptual apparatus. My view of conceptual analysis may look a piece of eclecticism, where suggestions from Bentham, Russell, Carnap, Quine and Strawson, among others, are put together in a sort of mental patchwork. It is indeed. In fact, I do not care for strict philosophical allegiance. I care for (hopefully) smoothly working tools for (hopefully) fruitful jurisprudential investigations.

  38. 38.

    A still valuable overview of the several, often intertwining, forms of philosophical analysis is offered by Urmson (1962), pp. 294–301; see also Strawson (1962), pp. 105–118; Strawson (1985), pp. 7–60.

  39. 39.

    Quine (1992), p. 19, italics added. See also Quine (1969), pp. 69–90, where epistemology, as an enquiry on the way empirical knowledge is acquired and processed, is presented as merging “with psychology, as well as with linguistics”.

  40. 40.

    Quine (1975), p. 72, italics added.

  41. 41.

    For an archetype of such a view, see Ross (1958), ch. 1.

References

  • Austin JL (1956–1957 [1961]) A plea for excuses. In: Austin JL (ed) Philosophical papers. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 123–152

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberis M (2016) For a truly realistic theory of law. Revus J Const Theory Philos Law 29:7–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Bix B (2007) Joseph Raz and conceptual analysis. APA Newsl 6(2):1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Borges JL (1964 [1969]) El instante. In: Borges JL (ed) Elogio de la sombra. Emece, Buenos Aires, 1996

    Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin E (1966 [2015]) Judicial decisions and the creation of law. In: Bernal C, Huerta C, Mazzarese T, Moreso JJ, Navarro PE, Paulson SL (eds) Essays in legal philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 75–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bulygin E (1991 [1994]) On Legal Interpretation. In: Koch H-J, Neumann U (eds) Praktische Vernunft und Rechtsanwendung / Legal system and practical reason, ARSP-Beiheft 53. Franz Steiner, Stuttgart, pp 11–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1950 [1956]) Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. In: Carnap R (ed) Meaning and necessity. A study in semantics and modal logic, Enlarged edn. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 205–221

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R (1963) Intellectual autobiography. In: Schilpp PA (ed) The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap, La Salle, Ill. Cambridge University Press, Open Court / London, pp 1–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Carrió GR (1965) Notas sobre derecho y lenguaje. Abeledo-Perrot, Buenos Aires

    Google Scholar 

  • Celano B (2016) Pre-conventions. A fragment of the background. Revus 1:2–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (1998) L’interpretazione dei documenti normativi: Giustiniano e i Glossatori. In: Gianformaggio L, Jori M (eds) Scritti per Uberto Scarpelli. Giuffrè, Milano, pp 199–223

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2012) The model of ordinary analysis. In: Duarte d’Almeida L, Edwards J, Dolcetti A (eds) Reading H. L. A. Hart’s the concept of law. Hart, Oxford, pp 247–267

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2016a) Da Bentham a Kelsen. Sei capitoli per una storia della filosofia analitica del diritto. Giappichelli, Torino

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiassoni P (2016b) Supporting the force of law: a few complementary arguments against essentialist jurisprudence. In: Bezemek C, Ladavac N (eds) The force of law reaffirmed. Frederick Schauer meets the critics. Springer, Switzerland, pp 61–71

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dagan H (2013) Reconstructing American legal realism and rethinking private law theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dagan H (2017) Contemporary legal realism. In: Sellers M, Kirste S (eds) Encyclopedia of the philosophy of law and social philosophy. Springer Science and Business Media B.V

    Google Scholar 

  • Dagan H (2018) The real legacy of American legal realism. Oxf J Legal Stud 38(1):123–146

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Endicott T (2002) Law and language. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, First published Thu Dec 5, 2002; substantive revision Fri Apr 15, 2016

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrajoli L (1989) Diritto e ragione. Teoria del garantismo penale. Laterza, Roma-Bari

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrajoli L (2012 [2014]) El constitucionalismo entre principios y reglas. In: Ferrajoli L, Ruiz Manero J (eds) Un debate sobre principios constitucionales. Palestra, Lima, pp 173–234

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrer J, Ratti GB (eds) (2010) El realismo jurídico genovés, Madrid-Barcelona-Buenos Aires, 2011

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1930) Law and the modern mind. Stevens & Sons, VI Printing, London, p 1949

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank J (1949a) Courts on trial. Myth and reality in American justice. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2011a) Interpretare e argomentare. Giuffrè, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Guastini R (2015) A realistic view on law and legal cognition. Revus J Const Theory Philos Law 27:45–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1961) The concept of law. Third edition, with a Postscript edited by PA Bulloch and J Raz, And with an introduction and notes by L. Green. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (1977 [1983]) American jurisprudence through English Eyes: the Nightmare and the Noble Dream. In: Hart HLA (ed) Essays in jurisprudence and philosophy. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 123–143

    Google Scholar 

  • Himma KE (2007) Reconsidering a Dogma: conceptual analysis, the naturalistic turn, and legal philosophy. In: Freeman MDA, Harrison R (eds) Law and philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 1–23

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson F (1998) From metaphysics to ethics: a defence of conceptual analysis. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Himma KE (2015) Conceptual jurisprudence. An introduction to conceptual analysis and methodology in legal theory. “Revus” 26:65–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking, fast and slow. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen H (1960) Reine Rechtslehre, 2nd edn. Deuticke Wien [eng. tr. The pure theory of law. The University of California Press, Berkeley, and Los Angeles, 1967]

    Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B (2007) Naturalizing jurisprudence. Essays on American legal realism and naturalism in legal philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leiter B (2008) Naturalizing Jurisprudence: Three Approaches. The University of Chicago Law School, Public Law and Legal Theory Working Paper n. 246, http://www.law.uchicago.edu/academics/publiclaw/index.html

  • Leiter B (2012) Naturalism in Legal Philosophy. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lawphil-naturalism/

  • Leiter B (2013) Legal realisms, old and new. Valparaiso Univ Law Rev 47:949–963

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2005) Interpretation and legal theory, 2nd edn. Hart, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2012) Farewell to conceptual analysis (in Jurisprudence). University of Southern California Law School, Los Angeles, CA 90089-0071, USC Legal Studies Research Paper No. 12-2, 1-26

    Google Scholar 

  • McCann M (2016) Preface to the new legal realism volumes I and II. In: Mertz E, Macaulay S, Mitchell TW (eds) The new legal realism. Volume I. Translating law-and-society for today’s legal practice. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp xiii–xxi

    Google Scholar 

  • Mertz E (2016) Introduction. New legal realism: law and social science in the New Millennium. In: Mertz E, Macaulay S, Mitchell TW (eds) The new legal realism. Volume I. Translating law-and-society for today’s legal practice. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 1–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (1997a) La indeterminación del derecho y la interpretación de la Constitución. Centro de Estudios Políticos y Constitucionales, Madrid [Eng. Tr. Legal indeterminacy and constitutional interpretation. Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1998]

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso JJ (1997b) Significado, interpretación y proposiciones normativas. Apunte para un debate. Unpublished presentation at the “Jurisprudence Workshop”, Dipartimento di Cultura Giuridica “Giovanni Tarello” (Genoa, December 15, 1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Spaak T (2015) Realism about the nature of law. Ratio Juris 30:75–104

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. The M.I.T. Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1969) Ontological relativity and other essays. Columbia University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1975 [1981]) Five milestones of empiricism. In: Quine WV (ed) Theories and things. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 67–72

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1992) Pursuit of truth, Revised edn. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross A (1958) On law and justice. Stevens & Sons, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2013) Legal realism untamed. Tex Law Rev 82:749–780

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer F (2018) American legal realism. In: Sellers M, Kirste S (eds) Encyclopedia of the philosophy of law and social philosophy. Springer Science and Business Media B.V

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith Churchland P (2013) Foreword. In: Quine WVO (ed) Word and object, New Edition. The MIT Press, Boston, pp xi–xiv

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1959) Individuals. An essay in descriptive metaphysics. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1962) Analyse, Science et Métaphysique. In: La philosophie analytique. Les Éditions de Minuit, Paris”, pp 105–118

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson PF (1985) Analyse et Métaphysique. Vrin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Urmsom JO (1962 [1992]) The history of philosophical analysis. In: Rorty RM (ed) The linguistic turn. Essays on philosophical method. With two retrospective essays. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 294–301

    Google Scholar 

  • Wróblewski J (1992) In: Bankowski Z, MacCormick N (eds) The judicial application of law. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chiassoni, P. (2019). Introduction: The Path of Analytical Realism. In: Interpretation without Truth. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 128. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15590-2_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-15590-2_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-15588-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-15590-2

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics