Skip to main content

Propositionalism and the Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Implicatures within Legal Language

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 127))

  • 364 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I question the Gricean notion of ‘what is said’. I give an outline of arguments supporting the thesis that there are more pragmatic elements of the ‘what is said’ notion than just disambiguation and reference assignments. These additional elements are referred to as ‘pragmatic enrichments’ by neo-Griceans and are distinguished by them from conversational implicatures. I argue that such pragmatic enrichments are subject to the same strategic framework as strong pragmatic effects such as conversational implicatures.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    ‘It is possible to recover the proposition literally expressed by a well-formed declarative sentence (its semantic content) simply on the basis of knowledge of the lexical entries for the expressions involved and an understanding of the syntactic construction of that sentence, plus, for sentences which contain genuinely context-sensitive elements, a merely minimal conception of the context within which the sentence was produced.’ (Borg 2012).

  2. 2.

    E. Borg was inspired by J. Fodor and his claims on the modularity of the human mind, see (Fodor 1983).

  3. 3.

    This example works on the assumption that this sentence does not have a hidden, syntactical argument for the place. Recanati assumes this on the basis of the following example: imagine a crazy scientist that wants to control the amount of rain across the entire planet (or universe etc.) and places rain detectors all over its surface. Whenever it rains somewhere on Earth, a bell rings. If the scientists says ‘It is raining!’, he does not have in mind a concrete location on Earth (Recanati 2004).

  4. 4.

    ‘When the relevant parameter – the comparison class in the case of ‘small’ – is contextually provided rather than made explicit in the sentence, there is an obvious sense in which the parameter in question is not articulated: no word or morpheme in the sentence stands for it. But there is also a sense in which it is “articulated”. As we have seen, there is an expression in the sentence, namely the adjective “small” itself, that triggers the search for a relevant comparison class, just as an indexical triggers the search for an appropriate contextual value. A truly unarticulated constituent resulting from free enrichment must not even be articulated in that second, weaker sense. It must not result from an obligatory process of saturation or “completion”.’ (Recanati 2002).

  5. 5.

    See http://www.venice.coe.int/images/SITE%20IMAGES/Publications/Rule_of_Law_Check_List.pdf.

  6. 6.

    See http://www.venice.coe.int/images/SITE%20IMAGES/Publications/Rule_of_Law_Check_List.pdf.

  7. 7.

    See http://www.venice.coe.int/images/SITE%20IMAGES/Publications/Rule_of_Law_Check_List.pdf.

  8. 8.

    See http://www.venice.coe.int/images/SITE%20IMAGES/Publications/Rule_of_Law_Check_List.pdf.

  9. 9.

    ‘The critique of the claim on the binding of the interpreting person proves that due to the semantics of language, legal language included, a textualist approach to language is impossible, as is the limitation of lawyers’ discretion proposed by textualists. Language is contextual by its very nature, which means that we cannot talk about the stability of meaning and the clarity of legal text because understanding a text is directly dependent on the context constituted by the features of the reader as well as the circumstances of reading. (…) The pragmatic nature of language is against the claim on the possibility of restricting lawyers’ discretion through the text, especially the influence of pragmatics on semantics – the influence of varying circumstances, in which we employ the same text, on the changes in the meaning.’ [translated by IS] (Matczak 2007).

  10. 10.

    Worrall v. Commercial Banking Co of Sydney Ltd (1917) 24 CLR 28 at 32.

  11. 11.

    Asgeirsson notes that Marmor has a similar example: ‘Suppose that a municipal regulation requires cafés and restaurants to have “clean and well-kept indoor restrooms”. Given the context of such a requirement, surely it would be implicated by this regulation that the restrooms must be actually open for the patrons to use.’ (Marmor 2014).

  12. 12.

    This is a worry that also appears when one analyses Larry Solum’s definition of construction.

  13. 13.

    You might wonder whether such a reformulation works with an externalist account of meaning. However, to be an externalist does not mean than one is precluded from speaking about legislative intentions. It does not mean claiming that judges cannot reconstruct legislative intentions. It means only to claim that legislative intentions are not reducible to a sum of the psychological mental states of the legislator. Thus, it is always possible to reconstruct the intention on the basis of context and conventions (for instance documents issued by legislative committees about the grounds of legislation, purposes of a statute, social campaigns etc.).

  14. 14.

    In reconstructing the legislative intention, the judge uses some facts that are independent of him; for instance, the text of the statute, committee reports, social campaigns etc. In other words, there are serious constraints on the reconstruction of intentions. Imagine a situation in which 101 members of parliament vote on a statute. 50 endorse version A and 51 endorse version B (vote against version A). An internalist would have to say that it is not possible to state clearly what the legislative intention was. By contrast, an externalist would claim that the intention is the outcome of the rules of voting, namely version B.

References

  • Asgeirsson H (2017) On the possibility of non-literal legislative speech. In: Poggi F, Capone A (eds) Pragmatics and law. Perspectives in pragmatics, philosophy & psychology, vol 10. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin J (1832) The province of jurisprudence determined. J. Murray

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin JL (1962) How to do things with words: [the William James lectures delivered at Harvard University in 1955], 2nd edn, [repr.]. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (2006) The excluded middle: semantic minimalism without minimal propositions. Philos Phenomenol Res 73:435–442. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2006.tb00626.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baum-Levenbook B (forthcoming) Beyond legislative intent

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennion FAR (1990) Bennion on statute law, 3rd edn. Longman, Harlow

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg E (2006) Minimal semantics. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg E (2012) Pursuing meaning. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston R (2012) Metaphor and the literal/non-literal distinction. In: Allan K, Jaszczolt K (eds) The Cambridge handbook of pragmatics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston R (2013) Legal texts and canons of construction: a view from current pragmatic theory. In: Freeman MDA, Smith F (eds) Law and language, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekins R (2012) The nature of legislative intent, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1983) The modularity of mind: an essay on faculty psychology. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs RW Jr (2002) A new look at literal meaning in understanding what is said and implicated. J Pragmat 34:457–486. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0378-2166(01)00046-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldsworthy J (1994) Implications in language, law and the constitution. In: Lindell G, Zines L (eds) Future directions in Australian constitutional law: essays in honour of Professor Leslie Zines. Federation Press in association with the Centre for International and Public Law and the Law Faculty. Australian National University, Sydney

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsworthy J (2005) Moderate versus strong intentionalism: Knapp and Michaels revisited. San Diego Law Rev 42:669

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart HLA (2012) The concept of law, 3rd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn LR (2006) The border wars: a neo-Gricean perspective. In: von Heusinger K, Turner K (eds) Where semantics meets pragmatics. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczolt K (2005) Default semantics: foundations of a compositional theory of acts of communication. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jaszczołt K (2016) Minimalizm a kontekstualizm semantyczny [minimalism versus contextualism about semantics]. In: Odrowąż-Sypniewska J (ed) Przewodnik po filozofii języka [Companion to the philosophy of language]. WAM, Kraków

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D (1978) Dthat. In: Cole P (ed) Syntax and semantics. Academic Press, pp 221–243

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2014) The language of law, 1st edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2016) Defeasibility and pragmatic indeterminacy in law. In: Capone A, Poggi F (eds) Pragmatics and law. Perspectives in pragmatics, philosophy & psychology, vol 7. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Matczak M (2007) Summa iniuria: o błędzie formalizmu w stosowaniu prawa [On the mistake of formalism in applying the law]. Wyd. 1. Wydawn.Nauk. “Scholar”, Warszawa

    Google Scholar 

  • Matczak M (2018) Why judicial formalism is incompatible with the rule of law. Can J Law Jurisprudence 31(1):61–85. https://doi.org/10.1017/cjlj.2018.3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee BH (ed) (1989) Binding implicit variables in quantified contexts. In: Compositionality in formal semantics. Blackwell Publishing Ltd, Malden, pp 259–281

    Google Scholar 

  • Perry J (2012) Reference and reflexivity, 2nd edn. rev. and expanded. Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato (294AD) (1952) Plato’s statesman, 2nd edn. Bristol Classical Press, Bristol

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F (2002) Unarticulated constituents. Linguis Philos 25:299–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F (2004) Literal meaning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F (2012) Contextualism: some varieties. In: Allan K, Jaszczolt K (eds) The Cambridge handbook of pragmatics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Skoczeń I (2015) Minimal semantics and legal interpretation. Int J Semiotics Law - Revue Internationale de Sémiotique Juridique. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-015-9448-3

  • Soames S (2013) Deferentialism: a post-originalist theory of legal interpretation. Fordham Law Rev 82:597–617

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley J (2000) Context and logical form. Linguist Philos:391–434. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1005599312747

  • Stanley J (2002) Making it articulated. Mind Lang 17:149–168. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0017.00193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sternau M, Ariel M, Giora R, Fein O (2015) Levels of interpretation: new tools for characterizing intended meanings. J Pragmat 84:86–101. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2015.05.002

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis C (2008) Occasion-sensitivity: selected essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2013) Separation of powers in thought and practice. Boston Coll Law Rev 54:433–468

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron J (2016) The rule of law. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/rule-of-law/

  • Wronkowska S (2005) Podstawowe pojęcia prawa i prawoznawstwa [Basic concepts in the law and jurisprudence]. Ars boni et aequi, Poznań

    Google Scholar 

  • Zieliński M (2012) Wykładnia prawa. Zasady, reguły, wskazówki [Legal Interpretation. Principles, Rules, Hints], 6th edn. Lexis Nexis, Warszawa

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Skoczeń, I. (2019). Propositionalism and the Law. In: Implicatures within Legal Language. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 127. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-12532-5_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-12532-5_4

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-12531-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-12532-5

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics