Skip to main content

The Idea of Human Rights in Global Contexts: The Equality Dimension

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Human Rights and Relative Universalism
  • 804 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, the previously outlined method of evaluating the compatibility of certain views and practices with human rights is applied to the equality dimension of human rights. I discuss inclusivist resources in religious as well as non-religious worldviews that can strengthen the notion of a principal equal worth of human beings, and scan various obstacles in that regard. The case examples include religious supremacy, nationalism, misogyny, and “moral disgust”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I offer a more extensive overview in the previous German version of this work (2017).

  2. 2.

    See esp. Yengde forthcoming; The Guardian 2018; Anupama 2009; Clifford 2007; Velassery 2005; Tamari 1991; Ambedkar 1936/2013.

  3. 3.

    See esp. Kirchschläger 2016; Little 2015; Witte and Green 2012; Ghanea 2010; Ghanea et al. 2007; Newlands 2006; Haas 2005; ʻAbdal-Rahim 2005; Florida 2005; Coward 2005; Evans 2001; Rouner 1988.

  4. 4.

    In the words of Locke: “[E]ach person is the last and highest judge of his own salvation; it is his own business, and only his; nobody else stands to lose anything” (1689/2010, p. 32). Or as Thomas Paine puts it: “If he believes not as thou believest, it is a proof that thou believest not as he believeth, and there is no earthly power (sic) can determine between you” (1791–1792/2003, p. 190f.). This view again is rooted in a noncognitivist stance about ultimate religious truth (cf. also Bayle 1686/2007). In Islam, in this vein arguments for toleration were developed by the early Islamic school of the Murjites, who serve as inspiration for modern day reformist minds (cf. Akyol 2011, pp. 83ff.).

  5. 5.

    On the Janus-faced universalism of radical Islam, see also Mustapha 2013.

  6. 6.

    On Daesh’s genocidal wars and the unspeakable atrocities of its fighters, see Dakhil et al. 2017.

  7. 7.

    He points to the example of slavery: “[B]oth Jews and Christians nowadays abhor slavery and condemn it in the name of their traditions, but this requires quite a revolutionary reading of their scripture, since neither Hebrew scriptures nor the New Testament opposes slavery in principle” (ibid., p. 101).

  8. 8.

    For a (diverging) interpretations of this parable, see Waldron 2003; Newlands 2006, p. 64.

  9. 9.

    Other than the CDHRI, the Arab League’s Arab Charter of Human Rights (ArabCHR) (1994) does not entail any such tribute to Islamic supremacism. Its preamble reads: “Having achieved the everlasting principles established by the Islamic Shari‘a and the other divine religions enshrined in brotherhood and equality amongst human beings […].”

  10. 10.

    See esp. Weidner 2008; Oh 2007; Mayr 1999/2007.

  11. 11.

    The distinction between true and false religion is a necessary, but not sufficient condition for violence. The key factor is whether or not the adherents of a specific faith consider themselves as entitled to themselves demarcate this distinction, i.e., for instance to punish or exterminate disbelieving people. However, where this is seen as a privilege of God, worldly coexistence of “true” and “false” religions is possible in principle. It is hence important not only to look at verses in the scripture of a specific religion calling to, for example, “burn” or “wipe out”, the religious other, but to ask who is authorized to do exactly that.

  12. 12.

    Manji further explained: “The truth is, I knew which interpretation I wanted but I didn’t know for sure [and still don’t] which one God wanted” (ibid., p. 35).

  13. 13.

    These are in particular: “To each among you have We prescribed a law and an Open Way. If Allah had so willed, He would have made you a single People, but (His plan is) to test you in what He hath given you: so strive as in a race in all virtues” (5: 48). “He guideth whom He will to a Way that is straight” (2:142).

  14. 14.

    See also Akyol, pp. 83ff. This divinely ordained deep pluralism also features in the philosophy of Roger Williams, who wrote: “It is the will and command of God, that […] a permission of the most Paganish, Jewish, Turkish or Antichristian consciences and worships, bee (sic) granted to all men in all Nations and countries […]” (1644/1869, p. 3). For the Jewish tradition, Elliot N. Dorff states: “God as understood in the Jewish tradition thus wants pluralism not only to demonstrate his grandeur in creating humanity with diversity but also to force human beings to realize their epistemological creatureliness, the limits of human knowledge compared to God” (2002, p. 58).

  15. 15.

    Recently, such a reform was requested by French intellectuals and politicians in their Manifeste contre le nouvel antisémitisme (Le Parisien 2018): “En conséquence, nous demandons que les versets du Coran appelant au meurtre et au châtiment des juifs, des chrétiens et des incroyants soient frappés d’obsolescence par les autorités théologiques […].”

  16. 16.

    This formulation is used by Arendt in the original German version of The Origins of Totalitarianism (1955/2005, ch. 9).

  17. 17.

    In particular populism is sometimes put on a level with nationalism. However, whereas nationalism refers to a pre-political ethnos imagined in cultural, racial, and/or religious terms, populism is best understood as a view centering upon a political demos. Nationalism confers messages like “We are the true natives” or “We are the best people, destined to rule ourselves (and others).” By contrast, populism asserts “We are the true people and not the corrupt or treasonous elite.”

  18. 18.

    See esp. McKim and McMahan 1997; Cohen 1996.

  19. 19.

    For how the movement represents itself, see <http://969movement.org/>.

  20. 20.

    For (Jewish internal) criticism of Zionism, see Sand 2010; Butler 2012/2014; Klug 2011; Ellis 2009; Meyer 2007.

  21. 21.

    Art. 3, common to all four Geneva Conventions, states: “Persons taking no active part in the hostilities, including members of armed forces who have laid down their arms and those placed ‘hors de combat’ by sickness, wounds, detention, or any other cause, shall in all circumstances be treated humanely, without any adverse distinction founded on race, colour, religion or faith, sex, birth or wealth, or any other similar criteria” (1949).

  22. 22.

    The ICC’s Rome Statute lists among its statutory offences: “Intentionally launching an attack in the knowledge that such attack will cause incidental loss of life or injury to civilians or damage to civilian objects or widespread, long-term and severe damage to the natural environment which would be clearly excessive in relation to the concrete and direct overall military advantage anticipated [emphasis added]” (1998, Art. 8, b, iv).

  23. 23.

    Historically, this question arose at the end of the war for the Allies in World War II: Should they risk the lives of 100,000 troops to achieve full victory over Germany and Japan by invading these countries or diminish the forseeable damage by fire (and, ultimately, atomic) bombing of major enemy cities (e.g., Tokyo, Dresden, Hiroshima)?

  24. 24.

    Cf. esp. Horowitz et al. 2011; UNHRC 2015.

  25. 25.

    For the work of the NGO, Breaking the Silence, founded by IDF veterans, see <https://www.breakingthesilence.org.il/>.

  26. 26.

    See esp. Miller 2016; Angeli 2015; Risse 2015; Dauvergne 2008; Benhabib 2004.

  27. 27.

    These numbers need to be interpreted in the context of a situation where many more people passed through Hungary without lodging such a claim and where many registered asylum seekers went into hiding or traveled on.

  28. 28.

    Except the Ukraine and Serbia, all of Hungary’s neighbors are EU member States. Provisions similar to this exist in other EU member States too, for example, in Germany (Basic Law Art. 16a, 2), though they are currently not applied (consistently).

  29. 29.

    Such anxiety about migration/asylum is by no means restricted to Hungary. For Europe’s identity crisis in that context and its deeper causes, see Murray 2017.

  30. 30.

    Unlike the CRSR, which allows for exemptions from the non-refoulement principle in cases where people pose “a danger to the security of the country” or have been convicted of serious crimes, neither CAT nor the Charter of the Fundamental Rights of the European Union allow for the balancing of rights and interests here. Where these conventions apply, the right of the migrant/refugee not to be deported trumps the common good in terms of national security and public safety and thus the rights of others. In recent years, the ramifications of non-refoulement have sparked public controversies in Europe, as, for instance, in the cases of Abu Quatada in the UK in 2013 and Sami A. in Germany in 2018.

  31. 31.

    In a blunt utilitarian vein, one could likewise question the legitimacy of a society’s interest in civil aviation or other amenities in light of human suffering in many parts of the world. There is basically no end to such arguments.

  32. 32.

    This right is conditioned insofar as it “may not be invoked in the case of prosecutions genuinely arising from non-political crimes or from acts contrary to the purposes and principles of the United Nations” (UN 1951, Art. 14, 2). The original UDHR draft did not define the right to asylum as an individual right but as the right of States: “Every State shall have the rights to grant asylum to political refugees” (UN 1947a, Art. 34).

  33. 33.

    Otherwise, rhetoric such as that which follows will resonate with increasing numbers of people: “In Brussels nowadays people believe that it is unfair if one is not born in the country where one would like to live. They believe that it is fair to give people the right to move to wherever they would like to live. In Brussels nowadays there are thousands of paid activists, bureaucrats and politicians working to have migration declared a fundamental human right. Therefore, they want to deprive us of the right to decide for ourselves who we let in to the country and who we refuse entry to” (Orban 2018).

  34. 34.

    The UDHR (1948a) does not yet explicitly address women’s rights beyond stressing “the equal rights of men and women” in its preamble. With the ICCPR and ICESCR, ensuring “the equal right of men and women” became an obligation for the contracting States (1966a,b, Art. 3). For an overview of the evolution of women’s human rights in the UN system, see Hellum and Aasen 2013; Black 2012.

  35. 35.

    Its reservation reads: “In case of contradiction between any term of the Convention and the norms of Islamic law, the Kingdom is not under obligation to observe the contradictory terms of the Convention.”

  36. 36.

    Cf. esp. Sachedina 2009; Krivenko 2008. For strategies of Islamic legal reform, see Waheedi et al. 2018.

  37. 37.

    According to classical Islamic law, women only have custody of their children until the children reach puberty. Upon divorce, they retain custody only if they do not remarry.

  38. 38.

    Another example is the stipulation—based on the Qurʾan, 2: 282, and the Sunnah (al-Buḫāryy Nr. 301)—that a woman’s testimony equals half of that of a man’s. There is no way in which the right to a fair trial is ever reconcilable with this.

  39. 39.

    Cf. also Gregg 2012, pp. 27ff.; Moller Okin 1999; Nussbaum 1999, ch. 3.

  40. 40.

    According to classical Islamic law, Muslim men can marry non-Muslim women if the latter are adherents of monotheistic faiths.

  41. 41.

    See, e.g., the work of Sisters in Islam in Malaysia (<http://www.sistersinislam.org.my/>) or of the global kovement Musawah (<http://www.musawah.org/>). Cf. also Schröter 2017; Amipur 2013; Bennoune 2013; Abu-Zayd 2009.

  42. 42.

    They do so not only because of generational trauma. As a female friend, raised in Bedouin society, explained to me, (grand)mothers often support FGM as the lesser evil in a particular dilemma: either they suppress the girl’s sexuality at a young age or risk her “honor killing” if she were to lose her virginity before marriage.

  43. 43.

    For a noteworthy exception, see Joseph 2009.

  44. 44.

    The question, however, of the extent to which threats to mental health should be considered in this regard, is an intricate one. In Ireland, for example, where, until the recent abortion law reform, abortions were only permissible in cases of rape or when the life of the mother was at risk (cf. Supreme Court of Ireland 1992), suicidal tendencies were regular claims of women seeking a termination of their pregnancy.

  45. 45.

    I agree with Singer that it is not (cf. 1980/2011, p. 154). However, I do not think a leveling of protection to the disadvantage of the unborn is the only option here, much less if we take a human rights perspective.

  46. 46.

    During the negotiations on the UDHR, a supplementary clause according to which human life should be protected from the moment of conception—suggested by Charles Malik—did not find support (cf. UN 1947b, p. 2).

  47. 47.

    For the US abortion debate in the 1990s and its constitutional law aspects, see esp. Dworkin 1993.

  48. 48.

    The argument from potentiality is, of course, not uncontested. Michael Tooley, for example, argues that it does not carry the obligation to not interfere with an unborn’s development, just as there was no obligation to bring a child into the world (1972, pp. 58f.). I am not convinced by this analogy. However, where critics of potentiality have a point is that alone it would not have any moral weight. Only in conjunction with the principle of human dignity can potentiality enfold its full moral potential. From a non-human rights point of view where only “agents” or “persons” have rights personality, such an axiological premise is, however, unacceptable. See Singer 1980/2011; Wellman 2011; Waheedi et al. 2018; MacMahan 2002.

  49. 49.

    See esp. Dershowitz 2002; Ignatieff 2004; Little 2015; Meggle 2005; Jakobs 2006; Köchler 2009; Mayerfeld 2016.

  50. 50.

    Cf. esp. Danner 2005; Meggle 2005; Nowak and Schmidt 2010; Wellman 2013, ch. 5.

References

  • ʻAbdal-Rahim, Muddathir. 2005. The Islamic Tradition. Human Rights and the World’s Major Religions. Vol. 3. London: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Abu-Zayd, Nasr. 2003. The Dilemma of the Literary Approach of the Qur’an. Alif. Journal of Comparative Poetics 23: 8–47. https://doi.org/10.2307/1350075.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. ʻMan’ and the ʻRights of Woman’ in Islamic Discourse – Between the Idealism of Texts and the Crisis of Reality. In Human Rights in Arab Thought. A Reader, ed. Salma K. Jayyusi, 131–137. London: I. B. Tauris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ahmed, Shahab. 2016. What Is Islam? The Importance of Being Islamic. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • [AI]. 2018. Myanmar: New Evidence Reveals Rohingya Armed Group Massacred Scores in Rakhine State. https://www.amnesty.org/en/latest/news/2018/05/myanmar-new-evidence-reveals-rohingya-armed-group-massacred-scores-in-rakhine-state/. Accessed 3 June 2018.

  • Akyol, Mustafa. 2011. Islam Without Extremes. A Muslim Case for Liberty. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • [Al-Khanssaa Brigade]. 2012. Women of the Islamic State. A manifesto on women by the Al-Khanssaa Brigade. Transl. Charlie Winter, 1–41. https://www.quilliaminternational.com/. Accessed 20 Aug 2018.

  • Ambedkar, Bhimrao Ramji. 1936/2013. Annihilation of Caste. In The Essential Writings of B. R. Ambedkar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amesbury, Richard. 2010. Inter-Religious Declarations of Human Rights: Grounding Rights or Constructing ‘Religion’? Religion and Human Rights 5: 43–64. https://doi.org/10.1163/187103210X506907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amipur, Katajun. 2013. Den Islam neu denken. Der Dschihad für Demokratie, Freiheit und Frauenrechte. Munich: C. H. Beck.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Benedict. 1983/2006. Imagined Communities. Reflections on the Origins and Spread of Nationalism. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angeli, Oliviero. 2015. Cosmopolitanism, Self-Determination and Territory. Justice with Borders. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • An-Na‘im, Abdullahi Ahmed. 1988. Mahmud Muhammad Taha and the Crisis in Islamic Reform: Implications for Interreligious Relations. Journal of Ecumenical Studies 25: 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990/1996. Toward an Islamic Reformation. Civil Liberties, Human Rights, and International Law. New York: Syracuse Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anupama, Rao. 2009. The Caste Question. Dalits and the Politics of Modern India. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2005. The Ethics of Identity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1941–1945/2007. The Jewish Writings. New York: Schocken Books. 

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1951. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1955/2005. Elemente und Ursprünge Totaler Herrschaft. Antisemitismus, Imperialismus, Totale Herrschaft. Munich: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1969/1970. On Violence. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, Karen. 2014. Fields of Blood. Religion and the History of Violence. London: Penguin/Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Assmann, Jan. 1996. The Mosaic Distinction: Israel, Egypt, and the Invention of Paganism. Representations 56: 48–67. https://doi.org/10.2307/2928707.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • AU. 2003. “Maputo” Protocol to the ACHPR. http://www.achpr.org/instruments/women-protocol/. Accessed 10 Aug 2018.

  • Avnery, Uri. 2009. The Johnny Procedure. http://zope.gush-shalom.org/home/en/channels/avnery/1247930861. Accessed 26 July 2018.

  • Baderin, Mashood A. 2005. International Human Rights and Islamic Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bassiouni, Mahmoud. 2014. Menschenrechte zwischen Universalität und islamischer Legitimität. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, Bruno. 1843. Die Judenfrage. Braunschweig: Verlag von Friedrich Otto.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayle, Pierre. 1686. Commentaire philosophique sur ces paroles de Jésus-Christ: “Contrains-les d’entrer”. Thomas Litwel: Paris.

    Google Scholar 

  • [BBC]. 2014a. Kenya Attack: 147 Dead in Garissa University Assault. https://www.bbc.com/news/world-africa-32169080. Accessed 16 Aug 2018.

  • ———. 2014b. Pakistan Taliban: Peshawar School Attack Leaves 141 Dead. https://www.bbc.com/news/world-asia-30491435. Accessed 16 Aug 2018.

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2004. The Rights of Others: Aliens, Residents, and Citizens. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Dignity in Adversity. Human Rights in Troubled Times. London: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennoune, Karima. 2013. Your Fatwa Does Not Apply Here: Untold Stories from the Fight Against Muslim Fundamentalism. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovits, Eliezer. 1971. Jewish Universalism. In History and the Idea of Mankind, ed. Warren W. Wagar, 47–71. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beyrer, Chris. 2017. Ethnic Cleansing in Myanmar: The Rohingya Crisis and Human Rights. The Lancet 390: 1570–1573. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(17)32519-9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bidar, Abdennour. 2015. Lettre ouverte au mond musulman. Paris: Les Liens Qui Liberent Editions.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittner, Rüdiger. 2005. Morals in Terrorist Times. In Ethics of Terrorism and Counter-Terrorism, ed. Georg Meggle, 207–213. Frankfurt a. M: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, Allida. 2012. Are Women “Human”? The UN and the Struggle to Recognize Women’s Rights as Human Rights. In The Human Rights Revolution. An International Movement, ed. Akira Iriye, Petra Goedde, and William I. Hitchcock, 132–155. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, Allen, and Russell Powell. 2018. The Evolution of Moral Progress. A Biocultural Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • [Budapest Business Journal]. 2018. Hungary Makes Aiding Asylum Seekers a Crime. https://bbj.hu/politics/hungary-makes-aiding-asylum-seekers-a-crime_151100. Accessed 5 Aug 2018.

  • Butler, Judith. 2012/2014. Parting Ways: Jewishness and the Critique of Zionism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandler, David. 2003. New Rights for Old? Cosmopolitan Citizenship and the Critique of State Sovereignty. Political Studies 51: 332–349. https://doi.org/10.1111/1467-9248.00427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchill, Robert Paul. 2006/2016. Human Rights and Global Diversity. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, Marcus Tullius. 54–51/2013. De re publica/Vom Staat. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clifford, Bob. 2007. “Dalit Rights Are Human Rights”: Caste Discrimination, International Activism, and the Construction of a New Human Rights Issue. Human Rights Quarterly 29: 167–193. https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2007.0001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua, ed. 1996. For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, Paul. 2014. Exodus. Immigration and Multiculturalism in the 21st Century. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coward, Harold. 2005. The Hindu Tradition. Human Rights and the World’s Major Religions. Vol. 4. Westport: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dakhil, Vian, Aldo Zammit Burda, and Alexander R.J. Murray. 2017. “Calling ISIL Atrocities Against the Yazidis by Their Rightful Name”: Do They Constitute the Crime of Genocide? Human Rights Law Review 17: 261–283. https://doi.org/10.1093/hrlr/ngx004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danner, Mark. 2005. Torture and Truth. America, Abu Ghraib and the War on Terror. London: Granta Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dauvergne, Catherine. 2008. Making People Illegal. What Globalization Means for Migration and Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dershowitz, Alan. 2002. Why Terrorism Works. Understanding the Threat, Responding to the Challenge. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • [Die Welt]. 2016. 79-Jährige auf Friedhof vergewaltigt. https://www.welt.de/regionales/nrw/article157308562/79-Jaehrige-auf-Friedhof-vergewaltigt.html. Accessed 16 Aug 2018.

  • Dill, Janina. 2010. Applying the Principle of Proportionality in Combat Operations, Policy Briefing. Oxford Institute for Ethics, Law, and Armed Conflict.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doniger, Wendy. 2010. The Hindus. An Alternative History. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorff, Elliot N. 2002. To Do the Right and the Good. A Jewish Approach to Modern Social Ethics. Philadelphia: The Jewish Society of Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1993. Life’s Dominion. An Argument About Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ECtHR. 2004. Vo vs France, [GC], 53924/00.

    Google Scholar 

  • El Saadawi, Nawal. 1977/2007. The Hidden Face of Eve. Women in the Arab World. Trans. Sherif Hetata. London: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, Marc H. 2009. Judaism Does Not Equal Israel. The Rebirth of the Jewish Prophetic. New York: The New Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erasmus of Rotterdam. 1517/2001. Die Klage des Friedens. Frankfurt a. M: Insel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eriksen, Thomas Hylland. 1994. Nationalism, Mauritian Style: Cultural Unity and Ethnic Diversity. Comparative Studies in Society and History 36: 549–574. https://doi.org/10.1017/S001041750001923X.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • EU. 2000. Charta of Fundamental Rights. http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/pdf/text_en.pdf. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • Evans, Malcom D. 2001. Human Rights, Religious Liberty, and the Universality Debate. In Law and Religion. Current Legal Issues, ed. Richard OʼDair and Andrew Lewis, vol. 4, 203–226. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Florida, Robert E. 2005. The Buddhist Tradition. Human Rights and the World’s Major Religions. Vol. 5. London: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frick, Marie-Luisa. 2010. Ummah’s Rights or Human Rights? Universalism, Individualism and Islamic Ethics in the 21st Century. American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 27: 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Universal Claim and Postcolonial Realities. The Deep Unease over Western-Centered Human Rights Standards in the Global South. In Human Rights and the Third World. Issues and Discourses, ed. Subrata Sankar Bagchi and Arnab Das, 17–30. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Menschenrechte und Menschenwerte. Zur konzeptionellen Belastbarkeit der Menschenrechtsidee in ihrer globalen Akkommodation. Weilerswist: Velbrück.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand. 2011. All Men Are Brothers. Life and Thoughts of Mahatma Gandhi as Told in His Own Words. Delhi: Rajpal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gearty, Conor. 2006. Can Human Rights Survive? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geer, Germaine. 2017. Women and the Struggle for Human Rights. In Fraglie Freedoms. The Global Struggle for Human Rights, ed. Steven Lecce, Neil McArthur, and Arthur Schafer, 195–209. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • [Geneva Conventions]. 1949. https://www.icrc.org/en/document/geneva-conventions-1949-additional-protocols. Accessed 15 July 2018.

  • Ghanea, Nazila, ed. 2010. Religion and Human Rights. Critical Concepts in Religious Studies. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghanea, Nazila, Alan Stephens, and Raphael Walden, eds. 2007. Does God Believe in Human Rights? Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodhart, David. 2017. The Road to Somewhere. The New Tribes Shaping British Politics. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Lenn Evan. 1996. God of Abraham. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, John-Stewart. 2017. Reconciling Female Genital Circumcision with Universal Human Rights. Developing World Bioethics, forthcoming. https://doi.org/10.1111/dewb.12173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goshen-Gottstein, Alon. 2008. Expandierende Identität – Strategien zur Überwindung religiöser Abgrenzung. In Religion. Segen oder Fluch der Menschheit? ed. Michael von Brück, 293–304. Frankfurt a. M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, Joshua. 2013. Moral Tribes. Emotion, Reason, and the Gap Between Us and Them. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregg, Benjamin. 2012. Human Rights as Social Constructions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, James. 2008. On Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • [The Guardian]. 2018. The Unspeakable Truth About Slavery in Mauretania. https://www.theguardian.com/global-development/2018/jun/08/the-unspeakable-truth-about-slavery-in-mauritania. Accessed 10 June 2018.

  • [Guru Granth Sahib]. http://www.sacred-texts.com. Accessed 23 Aug 2015.

  • Gutman, Amy. 1996. Democratic Citizenship. In For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen, 66–71. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haas, Peter J. 2005. The Jewish Tradition. Human Rights and the World’s Major Religions. Vol. 1. London: Praeger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamdani, Yasser Latif. 2011. A Minority Without Rights. http://www.thefridaytimes.com/27052011/page9.shtml. Accessed 2 Aug 2018.

  • Harris, Sam, and Maajid Nawaz. 2015. Islam and the Future of Tolerance. A Dialogue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hellum, Anne, and Henriette Sinding Aasen, eds. 2013. Women’s Human Rights. CEDAW in International, Regional and National Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hennegan, Julie. 2016. Schoolgirls’ Experience and Appraisal of Menstrual Absorbants in Rural Uganda: A Cross-Sectional Evaluation of Reusable Sanitary Pads. Reproductive Health 13: 143. https://doi.org/10.1186/s12978-016-0260-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzl, Theodor. 1896/1998. Der Judenstaat. Versuch einer modernen Lösung der Judenfrage. Zurich: Manesse Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodal, Kate. 2013. Buddhist monk uses racism and rumors to spread hatred in Burma. https://www.theguardian.com/world/2013/apr/18/buddhist-monk-spreads-hatred-burma. Accessed 5 June 2018.

  • Horowitz, Adam, Lizzy Ratner, and Philip Weiss, eds. 2011. The Goldstone Report. The Legacy of the Landmark Investigation of the Gaza Conflict. New York: Nation Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hosken, Fran. 1979. The Hosken Report: Genital/Sexual Mutilation of Females. Lexington, MA: WIN News.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, Rhoda E., and Jack Donnelly. 1986. Human Dignity, Human Rights, and Political Regimes. The American Political Science Review 80: 801–817. https://doi.org/10.2307/1960539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ICC. 1998. Rome Statute. https://www.icc-cpi.int/nr/rdonlyres/ea9aeff7-5752-4f84-be94-0a655eb30e16/0/rome_statute_english.pdf. Accessed 26 July 2018.

  • Ignatieff, Michael. 2004. The Lesser Evil. Political Ethics in an Age of Terror. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Human Rights, Global Ethics, and the Ordinary Virtues. Journal of International Law and International Relations 13: 1–9. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0892679416000629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ilesanmi, Olufemi Ojo. 2015. Islamism, Statehood and Human Rights. A World of Difference. Cambridge: Intersentia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobs, Günter. 2006. Terroristen als Personen im Recht? Zeitschrift für die Gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft 117: 839–851.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, Rita. 2009. Human Rights and the Unborn Child. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1795/2016. Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch. In Kant. Political Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kasher, Asa, and Amos Yadlin. 2009. ʻIsrael and the Rules of War’: An Exchange. The New York Review of Books 56 (10).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kipgen, Nehginpao. 2014. Addressing the Rohingya Problem. Journal of Asian and African Studies 49: 234–247. https://doi.org/10.1177/0021909613505269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchschläger, Peter G. 2016. Menschenrechte und Religionen. Nichtstaatliche Akteure und ihr Verhältnis zu den Menschenrechten. Schöningh: Paderborn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klug, Brian. 2011. Being Jewish and Doing Justice. Bringing Argument to Life. London: Vallentine Mitchell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Köchler, Hans. 2009. The Global War on Terror and the Metaphysical Enemy. In World Order. Vision and Reality. Collected Papers, ed. David Armstrong, 52–73. New Delhi: Manak.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kögler, Hans-Herbert. 2017. The Religious Face of Evil. Ethics and the Critique of Religion. Berlin Journal of Critical Theory 1: 21–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krivenko, Ekaterina Yahyaoui. 2008. Women, Islam and International Law. Leiden: Brill/Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Rethinking Human Rights and Culture Through Female Genital Surgeries. Human Rights Quarterly 37: 107–136. https://doi.org/10.1353/hrq.2015.0008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • [Le Parisien]. 2018. Manifeste contre le nouvel antisémitisme. http://www.leparisien.fr/societe/manifeste-contre-le-nouvel-antisemitisme-21-04-2018-7676787.php. Accessed 1 May 2018.

  • Levinas, Emanuel. 1990. Difficult Freedom. Essays from Judaism. London: The Athlone Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Libby, Hogan. 2018. ʻSlow’ Genocide: Myanmar’s Invisible War on the Kachin Christian Minority. https://www.theguardian.com/world/2018/may/14/slow-genocide-myanmars-invisible-war-on-the-kachin-christian-minority?CMP=fb_gu. Accessed 5 June 2018.

  • de Liguori, Alfonso Maria. 1889. Dignity and Duties of the Priest. In The Complete Works, vol. XII. New York: Benzinger Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lis, Jonathan, and Noa Landau. 2018. Israel Passes Controversial Jewish Nation-State-Bill After Stormy Debate. https://www.haaretz.com/israel-news/israel-passes-controversial-nation-state-bill-1.6291048. Accessed 26 July 2018.

  • Little, David. 2015. Essays on Religion and Human Rights. Ground to Stand on. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Livingstone Smith, David. 2011. Less than Human. Why We Demean, Enslave, and Exterminate Others. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1689/2010. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macklin, Ruth. 1999. Against Relativism. Cultural Diversity and the Search for Ethical Universals in Medicine. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacMahan, Jeff. 2002. The Ethics of Killing. Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Manji, Irshad. 2003. The Trouble with Islam Today. A Muslim’s Call for Reformation in Her Faith. New York: St. Martin’s Griffin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai. 1996. The Decent Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai, and Michael Walzer. 2009a. Israel: Civilians and Combatants. The New York Review of Books 56 (8).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009b. ʻIsrael and the Rules of War’: An Exchange. The New York Review of Books 56 (13).

    Google Scholar 

  • Maritain, Jacques. 1986/2011. The Rights of Man and Natural Law. In Christianity and Democracy and the Rights of Man and the Natural Law. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1844/1978. Zur Judenfrage. In Marx Engels Werke, vol. 1, 347–377. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayerfeld, Jamie. 2016. The Promise of Human Rights. In Constitutional Government, Democratic Legitimacy, and International Law. Pennsylvania: University of Philadelphia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, Ann Elizabeth. 1999/2007. Islam and Human Rights. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKim, Robert, and Jeff McMahan, eds. 1997. The Morality of Nationalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meggle, Georg, ed. 2005. Ethics of Terrorism & Counter-Terrorism. Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, Hajo G. 2007. The End of Judaism. An Ethical Tradition Betrayed. Neu Isenburg: Melzer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, David. 2000. Citizenship and National Identity. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Strangers in Our Midst. The Political Philosophy of Immigration. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Minow, Martha. 1990. Making All the Difference. Inclusion, Exclusion, and American Law. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • [Mohammed]. 1996. The Farewell Sermon of the Holy Prophet Muhammad. Islamabad: International Islamic University Islamabad.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molavi, Shourideh C. 2013. Stateless Citizenship. The Palestinian-Arab Citizens of Israel. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moller Okin, Susan. 1999. Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women? Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, Douglas. 2017. The Strange Death of Europe. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musa, Mohamad Faizal. 2013. The Malaysian Shi‘a: A Preliminary Study of Their History, Oppression, and Denied Rights. Journal of Shi‘a Islamic Studies 6: 411–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Musembi, Celestine Nyamu. 2013. Pulling Apart? Treatment of Pluralism in the CEDAW and the Maputo Protocol. In Women’s Human Rights. CEDAW in International, Regional and National Law, ed. Anne Hellum and Henriette Sinding Aasen, 183–213. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mustapha, Jennifer. 2013. The Mujahideen in Bosnia: The Foreign Fighter as Cosmopolitan Citizen and/or Terrorist. Citizenship Studies 17: 742–755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagan, Winston P., John A.C. Cartner, and Robert J. Munro. 2017. Human Rights and Dynamic Humanism. Leiden: Brill Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newlands, George. 2006. Christ and Human Rights. The Transformative Engagement. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, Manfred, and Roland Schmidt. 2010. Extraordinary Renditions and the Protection of Human Rights. Vienna: NWA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 1996. Patriotism and Cosmopolitanism. In For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen, 3–17. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Sex and Social Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • OAS. 1969. American Convention of Human Rights. https://www.cidh.oas.org/basicos/english/basic3.american%20convention.htm. Accessed 10 Sep 2018.

  • Oba, Adulumini. 2013. New Muslim Perspectives on Human Rights. In Islam and International Law. Engaging Self-Centrism from a Plurality of Perspectives, ed. Marie-Luisa Frick and Andreas Th. Müller, 217–243. Leiden: Brill/Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oh, Irene. 2007. The Rights of God. Human Rights and Comparative Ethics. Washington: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • OIC. 1990. CDHRI. http://www.oic-iphrc.org/en/data/docs/legal_instruments/OIC%20Instruments/Cairo%20Declaration/Cairo%20Declaration%20on%20Human%20Rights%20in%20Islam%20-%20EV.pdf. Accessed 15 Feb 2018.

  • Oo, Khin Maung. 2016. A Flea Cannot Make a Whirl of Dust, But –. http://www.globalnewlightofmyanmar.com/a-flea-cannot-make-a-whirl-of-dust-but/. Accessed 6 Sep 2018.

  • Orban, Viktor. 2014. Speech in Parliament to Present His New Cabinet. http://www.kormany.hu/en/the-prime-minister/the-prime-minister-s-speeches. Accessed 5 Aug 2018.

  • ———. 2015. Interview with BILD Zeitung. http://www.kormany.hu/en/the-prime-minister/the-prime-minister-s-speeches. Accessed 5 Aug 2018.

  • ———. 2018. Address After Swearing the Prime-Ministerial Oath of Office. http://www.kormany.hu/en/the-prime-minister/the-prime-minister-s-speeches. Accessed 5 Aug 2018.

  • Othman, Norani. 1999. Grounding Human Rights Arguments in Non-Western Culture: Shariʼa and the Citizenship Rights of Women in a Modern Islamic State. In The East Asian Challenge for Human Rights, ed. Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel A. Bell, 169–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paine, Thomas. 1791–1792/2003. Rights of Man. In Common Sense, Rights of Man, and Other Essential Writings of Thomas Paine. New York: Signet Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • [Parliament of the World’s Religions]. 1993. Declaration Toward a Global Ethic. https://parliamentofreligions.org/pwr_resources/_includes/FCKcontent/File/TowardsAGlobalEthic.pdf. Accessed 17 July 2018.

  • Plato. 399–395/2008. Euthyphro. In Defense of Socrates, Euthyphro, Citro. Trans. David Gallop. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pryke, Sam. 2009. Nationalism in a Global World. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raday, Frances. 2003. Culture, Religion and Gender. International Journal of Constitutional Law 1: 663–715. https://doi.org/10.1093/icon/1.4.663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • [The Republic of the Union of Myanmar]. 2008. Constitution. http://www.burmalibrary.org/docs5/Myanmar_Constitution-2008-en.pdf. Accessed 10 July 2018.

  • Risse, Matthias. 2015. Taking Up Space on Earth: Theorizing Territorial Rights, the Justification of States and Immigration from a Global Standpoint. Global Constitutionalism 4: 81–113. https://doi.org/10.1017/S2045381714000161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ron, James, et al. 2017. Taking Root. Human Rights and Public Opinion in the Global South. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rouner, Leroy S., ed. 1988. Human Rights and the World’s Religions. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachedina, Abdulaziz. 2006. Human Viceregency: A Blessing or a Curse? In Humanity Before God. Contemporary Faces of Jewish, Christian, and Islamic Ethics, ed. William Schweiker, Michael A. Johnson, and Kevin Jung, 31–54. Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Islam & the Challenge of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sand, Shlomo. 2010. The Invention of the Jewish People. Trans. Yael Lotan. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schröter, Susanne. 2017. Islamic Feminism. National and Transnational Dimensions. In Islam, Gender and Democracy, ed. Jocelyne Cesari, 115–138. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, Kelly J. 2012. The Right to Bodily Integrity. Women’s Rights as Human Rights and the International Movement to End Female Genital Mutilation, 1970s–1990s. In The Human Rights Revolution. An International Movement, ed. Akira Iriye, Petra Goedde, and William I. Hitchcock, 285–310. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sikkink, Kathryn. 2017. Evidence for Hope. Making Human Rights Work in the 21st Century. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter. 1980/2011. Practical Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sipe, Richard. 2003. Celibacy in Crisis. A Secret World Revisited. New York: Brunner-Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Mea Maxima Culpa: Silence in the House of God, directed by Alex Gibney, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Anthony D. 2003. Chosen Peoples. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Norman. 2010. Religion and Human Rights with Special Reference to Judaism. In Does God believe in Human Rights? ed. Nazila Ghanea, Alan Stephens, and Raphael Walden, 89–105. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soroush, Abdolkarim. 2000. Reason, Freedom, and Democracy in Islam. In Essential Writings of Abdolkarim Soroush. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stackhouse, Max L., and Stephen E. Healey. 2010. Religion and Human Rights. A Theological Apologetic. In Religion and Human Rights. Critical Concepts in Religious Studies, ed. Nazila Ghanea, 84–113. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • [State of Israel]. 1948. The Declaration of the Establishment of the State of Israel. http://www.mfa.gov.il/mfa/foreignpolicy/peace/guide/pages/declaration%20of%20establishment%20of%20state%20of%20israel.aspx. Accessed 26 July 2018.

  • [Stichting Justice Initiative]. 2018. The Practice of Female Genital Mutilation in Dagestan: Strategies for Its Elimination. https://www.srji.org/en/about/annual/the-second-fgm-report-based-on-the-results-of-a-study-in-russian-federation/. Accessed 13 June 2018.

  • [Supreme Court of Ireland]. 1992. Attorney General v X. http://www.bailii.org/ie/cases/IESC/1992/1.html. Accessed 15 Aug 2018.

  • Tamari, Tal. 1991. The Development of Caste Systems in West Africa. Journal of African History 32: 221–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1999. A Catholic Modernity. In Charles Taylor’s Marianist Award Lecture, ed. James L. Heft, 13–37. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1971. A Defense of Abortion. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1: 47–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Timmons, Heather, and Sruthi Gottipati. 2012. Woman Dies After a Gang Rape That Galvanized India. https://www.nytimes.com/2012/12/29/world/asia/condition-worsens-for-victim-of-gang-rape-in-india.html. Accessed 16 Aug 2018.

  • Tooley, Michael. 1972. Abortion and Infanticide. Philosophy & Public Affairs 2: 37–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trappolini, Luca, and Tania Motterle. 2012. One Step Beyond: Researching Homophobia in Italy. In Confronting Homophobia in Europe. Social and Legal Perspectives, ed. Luca Trappolini, Alessandro Gasparini, and Robert Wintemute, 21–49. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN. 1947a. Draft Outline of International Bill of Rights, E/CN.4/AC.1/3.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1947b. Drafting Committee Summary Record of the Tenth Meeting, E/CN.4/AC.1/SR.10.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1948a. UDHR, A/RES/3/217.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1948b. Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, A/RES/3/260.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1951. CRSR, A/RES/1775.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966a. ICCPR, A/RES/21/2200.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966b. ICESCR, A/RES/21/2200.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. CEDAW, A/RES/34/180.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. CAT, A/RES/39/46.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. CEDAW General Recommendation Nr. 4, CEDAW/C/GC/4.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action, A/CONF.177/20/Rev.1.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. L.C. v. Peru, CEDAW/C/50/D/22/2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Intensifying Global Efforts for the Elimination of Female Genital Mutilations, A/RES/67/146.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. (New York) Declaration for Refugees and Migrants. https://refugeesmigrants.un.org/declaration. Accessed 5 Aug 2018.

  • ———. 2018a. Treaty Collection. CEDAW Declarations and Reservations. https://treaties.un.org/Pages/ViewDetails.aspx?src=IND&mtdsg_no=IV-8&chapter=4&lang=en. Accessed 10 Aug 2018.

  • ———. 2018b. Report of the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees. Part II: Global Compact for Refugees, A/73/12.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNHCR. 2018. Population Statistics – Asylum Seekers. http://popstats.unhcr.org/en/asylum_seekers_monthly. Accessed 5 Aug 2018.

  • UNHRC. 2015. Report of the Detailed Findings of the Independent Commission of Inquiry on the 2014 Gaza War, A/HRC/29/CPR.4.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2018. Report of the Independent International Fact-Finding Mission on Myanmar, A/HRC/39/64.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNICEF. 2013. Female Genital Mutilation/Cutting: A Statistical Overview and Exploration of the Dynamics of Change. https://www.unicef.org/publications/index_69875.html. Accessed 10 Aug 2018.

  • US Department of State. 2012. Maldives 2012 International Religious Freedom Report. http://www.state.gov/documents/organization/208646.pdf. Accessed 30 July 2017.

  • Velassery, Sebastian. 2005. Casteism and Human Rights. Toward an Ontology of Social Order. Singapore: Marshall Cavendish Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verma, Justice J.S., et al. 2013. Report of the Committee on Amendments to Criminal Law. http://www.prsindia.org/parliamenttrack/report-summaries/justice-verma-committee-report-summary-2628/. Accessed 16 Aug 2018.

  • Voltaire. 1763/2016. Treatise on Toleration. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wade, Francis. 2017. Myanmar’s Enemy Within: Buddhist Violence and the Making of a Muslim ʻOther’. London: Zed Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waheedi, Salma, Kristen Stilt, and Swathi Gandhavadi Griffin. 2018. The Ambitions of Muslim Family Law Reform. Harvard Journal of Law and Gender 41: 301–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2003. Who Is My Neighbour? Humanity and Proximity. The Monist 86: 333–354. https://doi.org/10.5840/monist200386324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, Matthew J., Melyn McKay, and Daw Khin Mar Mar Kyi. 2015. Women and Myanmar’s “Religious Protection Laws”. The Review of Faith and International Affairs 13: 36–49. https://doi.org/10.1080/15570274.2015.1104975.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, Michael. 1994. Thick and Thin. Morality at Home and Abroad. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Spheres of Affection. In For Love of Country. Debating the Limits of Patriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen, 125–127. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1921/1972. Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriss der verstehenden Soziologie. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weidner, Stefan. 2008. Manual für den Kampf der Kulturen. Warum der Islam eine Herausforderung ist. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, Carl. 2011. The Moral Dimension of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Terrorism and Counterterrorism. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White, Chloé. 2015. Protection for Whom? Violations of International Law in Myanmar’s New “Race and Religion Protection” Laws. Washington, DC: Georgetown Institute for Women, Peace & Security. https://giwps.georgetown.edu/wp-content/uploads/2017/10/Violations-of-International-Law-in-Myanmar-2.pdf. Accessed 10 Aug 2018.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Roger. 1644/2001. The Bloudy Tenent of Persecution for Cause of Conscience. Providence: Publications of the Narragansett Club.

    Google Scholar 

  • Witte, John, and Christian M. Green, eds. 2012. Religion & Human Rights. An Introduction. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollstonecraft, Mary. 1792/1989. A Vindication of the Rights of Woman. In Collected Works, vol. 5. London: William Pickering.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yengde, Suraj. Caste Matters, Penguin Random House, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahid, Seyd Jaymal. 2014. Fatwa Declaring Kassim Ahmad an Apostate only for Terengganu, Minister Says. https://www.malaymail.com/s/698745/fatwa-declaring-kassim-ahmad-an-apostate-only-for-terengganu-minister-says. Accessed 1 Nov 2017.

  • Zampas, Christina, and Jamie H. Gher. 2008. Abortion as a Human Right: International and Regional Standards. Human Rights Law Review 8: 249–294. https://doi.org/10.1093/hrlr/ngn008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marie-Luisa Frick .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Frick, ML. (2019). The Idea of Human Rights in Global Contexts: The Equality Dimension. In: Human Rights and Relative Universalism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10785-7_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics