Skip to main content

Foundational Paths

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 386 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter is devoted to pointing out in more detail the normative fundamentals of human rights and addresses foundational questions. A key idea here is that multiple paths exist to philosophically ground the idea of human rights. At the same time, we have to mind that grounding the idea of human rights is not the same as grounding concrete rights. In addition, another differentiation has to be observed, namely between grounding the idea of human rights horizontally (why should individuals respect/care for human rights?) and justifying it vertically (why should States subject to/protect them?). The favorable account of foundational pluralism is completed by a comparison and discussion of the different theoretical approaches in that regard.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In the words of Amitai Etzioni: “Self-evident precepts may indeed elude people whose vision is obscured, either because they live in closed societies, such as fundamentalist theocracies or secular totalitarian states, or because they have closed minds even if they live in open societies” (2010, p. 194).

  2. 2.

    I borrow this term from Rainer Forst (2010), although I do not share the subsequent theoretical implications he draws according to which in this right to justification we have a quasi-Archimedean point for grounding human rights. One could interpret this maneuver as an ingenious perpetual motion machine or, less favorably, a circular argument. Cf. also Benhabib 2011, p. 11.

  3. 3.

    Someone can have a motive to affirm human rights norms because, for example, “they make the world a better place,” and still be unaware of the reasons why they hold this position and what precisely they mean with “better place.” Without normative reflexivity, in this case pertaining to the source of norms, mere motives remain blind and untranslatable. In practical matters, the difference shows when asking someone “why” they have a certain moral point of view. Pre-reflective motives will most likely be lost for words.

  4. 4.

    This systematic distinction is challenged by Jeremy Waldron’s phenomenological-historical claim “that human dignity involves universalizing, rather than superseding, the connotations of status, rank, and nobility that ‘dignity’ traditionally conveyed” (ibid., p. 67). Maintaining that “we are like a caste society with just one caste” (ibid.) and that human dignity is but the “nobility for the common man“ (ibid., p. 22), is however ignoring that no egalitarian universalization of honor can take place without at least marginalizing the concept of honor or nobility as such. For a critique of Waldron’s theory pertaining to his refusal to acknowledge moral ideas leading to the rise of human dignity, see Rosen 2012b.

  5. 5.

    This refining approach is akin to Stephen L. Darwall’s differentiation between recognition respect and appraisal respect (1977).

  6. 6.

    Cf. esp. Art. 1 UDHR; Preamble and Art. 10 ICCPR; Preamble and Art. 13 ICESCR; OSCE 1975; Preamble Protocol Nr. 13 to the ECHR on the Abolition of the Death Penalty in all Circumstances (2002); the Council of Europe Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Person with regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine (1997).

  7. 7.

    An example for such an interpretation is provided by Avishai Margalit. According to him, human rights are not grounded in human dignity, but justified precisely because they protect human dignity (1996). This is similar to Griffin (2008) as well as Thomas Hoffmann who states: “[T]he role of human rights is, ultimately, to preserve the dignity of each human being” (2014, p. 44). See also Glensy 2011.

  8. 8.

    Cf., e.g., Art. 3 of the Protocol to the ACHPR on Rights of Women in Africa (2003): “Every woman shall have the right to dignity inherent in a human being and to the recognition and protection of her human and legal rights […].”

  9. 9.

    On the relevance of the Irish constitution, see esp. Moyn 2014. In his assessment, this constitution was “epoch-making” and gave human dignity “its highest profile entry in world politics to that date” (ibid., p. 49).

  10. 10.

    “Human dignity shall be inviolable. To respect and protect it shall be the duty of all state authority” (Art. 1). See also Matthias Herdegen’s commentary (2009), whose rather relativist account of this passage sparked heated discussions among German legal theorists. The EU Charter of Fundamental Rights (2000) has adopted the German dignity-formula almost verbally (Art. 1).

  11. 11.

    The first line of the UDHR preamble reads: “[R]ecognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world […].” Art. 1 states: “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights.” According to René Cassin, member of the drafting commission, the adoption of human dignity into the text expresses the thought “that the most humble men of the most different races have among them the particular spark that distinguishes them from animals, and at the same time obligates them to more grandeur and to more duties than any other beings on earth” (UN 1947).

  12. 12.

    Its preamble states: “We the Peoples of the United Nations [are] determined to reaffirm faith in fundamental human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person.”

  13. 13.

    Thomas Paine writes: “When I contemplate the natural dignity of man, when I feel […] for the honour and happiness of its character, I become irritated at the attempt to govern mankind by force and fraud […]” (2003 [1791–1792], p. 172).

  14. 14.

    In the course of the UDHR’s drafting, an explicit reference to God was discussed on the basis of a proposal from Brazil. Due to resistance from France and the USSR, it was rejected.

  15. 15.

    This principal openness of the human dignity concept has, however, been criticized by some for its vagueness, which would amount to meaninglessness (cf. esp. Bagaric and Allan 2006).

  16. 16.

    See esp. Luków 2018, Weber-Guskar and Brandhorst 2017, Waldron 2015, Schroeder 2012, Rosen 2012a, Daly 2012, Kateb 2011, Habermas 2010, Bagaric and Allan 2006, Wetz 2005, Macklin 2003.

  17. 17.

    Manetti explicitly challenged Innocent III. and his De miseris humanae conditionis (1195) where the pope depicted the human condition as miserable and in need of salvation. Reformed Christianity later did not break with this perspective, often even enhancing the argument (“sola gratia”). The controversy between Martin Luther (De servo arbitrario, 1525) and Erasmus of Rotterdam (De libero arbitrario, 1524) is quite telling in that regard.

  18. 18.

    Kant’s own examples of such reductionist instrumentalization extend over a wide spectrum, including polygamy, denying death penalty to a murderer out of utilitarian reasons, suicide, and religious self-humiliation (cf. 1797/1836).

  19. 19.

    According to Margalit, any candidate for a dignity-endowing property should satisfy in particular the following criteria: They “must not be graded” and “must not be of the sort that can be abused” (1996, pp. 62f.). Since in his view no such property can be found, he opts for a “negative foundation” of human dignity which revolves around the claim that human beings must not be humiliated (ibid., pp. 84ff.). This, however, is but a change in focus from dignity as status to a right to dignity and raises the obvious question of its respective justification.

  20. 20.

    For a reconstruction of Arendt’s views on human dignity—a term she herself did not refer to explicitly but nevertheless a notion of profound importance in her thought—see Macready 2018.

  21. 21.

    Translation by the author.

  22. 22.

    By arguing against a God’s eye point of view in the tradition of Renaissance humanism, Williams also undermines the vigorous effect of the “speciesism” charge regularly raised against the concept of human dignity in the context of animal rights advocacy (cf. esp. Singer 1980/2011, pp. 64ff.). There are, according to Williams, no specific “reasons” for the prioritized moral consideration of humans except that we, as humans, are just more important to us. Although that need not result in moral disregard of other species, it is a preference not to be ashamed of. In his reply to Williams, Peter Singer leaves to doubt that from a “view of nowhere,” where preferences of non-human animals and human animals are considered indiscriminatorily, human rights would not be a meaningful concept. Referring to Williams’ thought experiment—wise aliens with good intentions are about to extinct humans (for the sake of other species on the planet) (2006, pp. 148ff.)—Singer confesses: “Although it is fantastic to imagine that a fair-minded, well-informed, far-sighted judge could ever decide that there was no alternative to the removal of our species in order to avoid much greater injustice and misery, if this really were the case, we should reject the tribal—or species—instinct and answer Williams’ question in the same way” (ibid., p. 70).

  23. 23.

    In this light, criticism that in Kant’s dignity ethics “[c]riminals […] are not worthy of respect” (Margalit 1996, p. 64) or that Kant’s focus on moral self-legislation would even exclude “small children to begin with, but at an extreme, everybody who is sleeping” (Schroeder 2012, p. 330) is in dire need of reconsideration.

  24. 24.

    Cf. also Dorff 2002, pp. 5ff.; Goodman 1996.

  25. 25.

    Similar to the formulation in the Russian Orthodox Church’s position paper on human dignity and rights (2008): “[T]here is a direct link between human dignity and morality.”

  26. 26.

    Cf., e.g., Alting von Geusau 2013; Schroeder 2012; Pope Benedikt XVI 2010.

  27. 27.

    Translation by the author.

  28. 28.

    Translation by the author.

  29. 29.

    Even though Nussbaum repeatedly stresses the open character of this list of capabilities allowing for further modifications (ibid., pp. 78ff.; 296), she also holds that at least those ten capabilities are not up for discussion (“we ask you to agree on these ten basic entitlements”, ibid., p. 297).

  30. 30.

    Among these entitlements Nussbaum sees only limited scope for conflicts as long as a certain threshold in the case of each capability is observed: “[I]f the capabilities list and its threshold are suitably designed, we ought to say that the presence of conflict between one capability and another is a sign that society has gone wrong somewhere” (ibid., p. 401).

  31. 31.

    For a philosophical discussion from a range of perspectives, see also Albers et al. 2014.

  32. 32.

    The question of animals is explicitly raised in Nussbaum’s account (cf. 2006). In defense of the human dignity approach, however, one must add that nothing in the concept of human dignity excludes the idea of dignity of certain animals if elaborated appropriately.

  33. 33.

    Other than the name “Hume’s law” would suggest, the Scottish philosopher did not actually set up a law according to which inferences from is-statements to ought-statements were always invalid. He merely raised the skeptical question as to how such inferences could work at all and criticized previous moral philosophers and others for not being aware of this problem (1739/1817, p. 172).

  34. 34.

    Translation by the author.

  35. 35.

    Cf., e.g., Kohen 2005; MacIntyre 1981/1984, pp. 66ff. A positive appraisal, on the other hand, is put forward in Churchill 2006/2016.

  36. 36.

    Jürgen Habermas was quite clear about the limits of his theory of communicative reason when he insisted that it is no perfect source for normativity or that a weak transcendental compulsion is not yet the “must” of a rule of action (cf. 1996, 1992, pp. 135ff.). It thus comes as no surprise that in trying to ground human rights, Habermas recently departs from transcendental argumentation and trusts in human dignity instead (cf. 2010).

  37. 37.

    For a critique of the “mirror theory,” see esp. Buchanan (2013, ch. 2) and Lohmann 2010.

  38. 38.

    For the text, its interpretation as an early affirmation of rights and popular sovereignty as well as speculations on its influence on Thomas Jefferson and others, see Klieforth and Munro 2004, pp. 190ff.

  39. 39.

    For the impact of these ideas on the English Civil War 1640–1651, see Zaret 2000.

  40. 40.

    On another occasion, he writes: “[T]hat the state of men without civil society […] is nothing else but a mere warre of all against all” (1642/1998, p. 34).

  41. 41.

    This characterization of the human condition has been criticized by many, including Scottish moral sense philosophers Anthony-Ashley Cooper (1683/1984) and Francis Hutcheson (1753). Their anthropological counter-narrative according to which (wo)man is rather inclined to cooperate than to hostility is, however, no confutation of Hobbes’ position since he would still be able to argue that the perils in a state of nature remain so long as there are a only few who lack the respective moral sentiments. After all, that human beings are able to lift themselves above the state of nature by forming a political commonwealth is but another proof that Hobbes was far from denying that human nature entails the capability to fruitful cooperation. What is true, is that altruism has no substantial relevance in Hobbes’ theory, whereas self-interest doubtlessly is the key motivational factor.

  42. 42.

    In his demand for a division of powers, Locke differs from Hobbes but also Rousseau. Locke thereby proposes a solution to Hobbes’ dilemma, according to which one always needs a greater power to confine another.

  43. 43.

    This is most obvious from Hobbes’ writings who concedes he is not certain if such a state of nature ever has existed in the past (although Native Americans would come fairly close to it) (1651/1985, p. 187). It is, however, less clear in the work of Rousseau, who seems to believe that his perfect original state embodies a historical truth still echoed in the life forms of “noble savages” (cf. 1755/2004).

  44. 44.

    Cf. also Locke 1642/1998, pp. 74ff., 98ff.; Milton 1649/1911, p. 12.

  45. 45.

    “When therefore our refusall to obey, frustrates the End for which the Soveraignty was ordained; then there is no Liberty to refuse; otherwise there is” (1651/1985, p. 269).

  46. 46.

    “[W]henever the Legislators endeavor to take away, and destroy the Property of the People, or to reduce them to Slavery under Arbitrary Power, they put themselves into a state of War with the People, who are thereupon absolved from any farther Obedience, and are left to the common Refuge, which God hath provided for all Men, against Force and Violence” (1689/2012, p. 412).

  47. 47.

    “And if we should obey a good prince, it will not therefore follow that we should not resist a wicked prince” (Buchanan 1583/1766, p. 75); “[T]he people as oft as they shall judge it for the best, [may] either choose him [the ruler] or reject him, retaine him or depose him though no tyrant, merely by the libertie and right of free born men […]” (Milton 1649/1911, p. 15).

  48. 48.

    A noteworthy exception to this dominant view on Hobbes is Eleanor Curran (2007). See also Finkelstein 2005, König 1994, Gauthier 1969/2000, Mayer-Tasch 1965.

  49. 49.

    Hobbes indeed is “one of the first writers to think seriously about the fundamental rights of individuals” (Gearty 2006, p. 73). The rights of the individual include such fundamental guarantees as the freedom from self-incrimination and torture or also to resist one’s own capture or execution (cf. Hobbes 1642/1998, pp. 58ff.; 1651/1985, pp. 199ff., 269). The last example is especially instructive about the nature of these rights to resistance, which is not a guarantee to resist effectively, but rather consists in the freedom to try to resist without fearing sanctions for the very act of resistance. In this way, Hobbes’ right to resistance at least binds the State authority in foro interno (cf. Finkelstein 2005, pp. 437ff.).

  50. 50.

    Genuine popular sovereignty always has to be understood as the sovereignty of a certain people for the time being only. In the words of Thomas Paine: “There never did, there never will, and there never can, exist a Parliament, or any description of men, or any generation of men, in any country, possessed of the rights or the power of binding and controuling posterity to ‘the end of time’ […]. The vanity and presumption of governing beyond the grave is the most ridiculous and insolent of all tyrannies” (2003 [1791–1792], p. 138). Cf. Frick 2017.

  51. 51.

    See esp. Dietrich 2017; Moyn 2015; Bloch 2007; Maritain 1986/2011.

  52. 52.

    For a critical assessment of the actual effect of this idea in the early Islamic period, see Afsaruddin 2006.

  53. 53.

    On the potential of Islamic constitutionalism, see Feldman 2010.

  54. 54.

    The concept of tiān has evolved over a long period of time from denoting “spirit” or God to a cosmological order (cf. Angle 2012, pp. 38ff.). See also Ommerborn et al. 2011, pp. 163ff., 610ff.

  55. 55.

    For the influence of Western political philosophy on Chinese legal discourse in the past, see Angle 2002.

  56. 56.

    “Religion forbids us from assuming a God-like character. […] Limiting the power of the state, division of power and the doctrine of checks and balances are established in order to prevent accumulation of power that might lead to such Godly claims” (ibid., p. 64).

References

  • Afsaruddin, Asma. 2006. The ‘Islamic State’: Genealogy, Facts, and Myths. Journal of Church and State 48: 153–174. https://doi.org/10.1093/jcs/48.1.153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albers, Marion, Thomas Hoffmann, and Jörn Reinhardt, eds. 2014. Human Rights and Human Nature. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alting von Geusau, Christian. 2013. Human Dignity and the Law in Post-War Europe. Roots and Reality of an Ambiguous Concept. Oisterwijk: Wolf Legal Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angle, Stephen C. 2002. Human Rights and Chinese Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Contemporary Confucian Political Philosophy. Towards Progressive Confucianism. Cambridge, MA: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • An-Na‘im, Abdullahī Ahmed. 1990/1996. Toward an Islamic Reformation. Civil Liberties, Human Rights, and International Law. New York: Syracuse Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 2006. Cosmopolitanism. Ethics in a World of Strangers. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, Thomas. 1949 [1265–1273]. De regno ad regem Cypri. On Kingship to the king of Cyprus. Trans. Gerald B. Phelan. Toronto: The Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1975 [1259–1265]. Summa Contra Genitles, Book 3. Trans. Vernon J. Bourke. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, Hannah. 1951. The Origins of Totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1958/1974. The Human Condition. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1969/1970. On Violence. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.

    Google Scholar 

  • AU. 2003. Protocol to the ACHPR on Rights of Women in Africa. http://www.achpr.org/instruments/women-protocol/. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • Augustine. 408 AD/1872. Letter to Vincentius. In Works of Aurelius Augustine Vol. 6. Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagaric, Mirko, and James Allan. 2006. The Vacuous Concept of Dignity. Journal of Human Rights 5: 257–270. https://doi.org/10.1080/14754830600653603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, Charles R. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Human Dignity in the Theory of Human Rights: Nothing but a Phrase? Philosophy and Public Affairs 41: 259–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, Seyla. 2011. Dignity in Adversity. Human Rights in Troubled Times. London: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 1796/1843. Anarchical Fallacies. In The Works of Jeremy Bentham, vol. 2. Edinburgh: William Tait.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bible. 1983. New International Version. Colorado Springs: Biblica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloch, Tamara. 2007. Die Stellungnahmen der römisch-katholischen Amtskirche zur Frage der Menschenrechte seit 1215. Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodin, Jean. 1576/1992. On Sovereignty. Four Chapters from the Six Books of the Commonwealth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boucher, David. 2009. The Limits of Ethics in International Relations. Natural Law, Natural Rights, and Human Rights in Transition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boylan, Michael. 2014. Natural Human Rights. A Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, George. 1583/1766. De Jure Regni apud Scotos or A Dialogue, concerning the due Privilege of Government, in the Kingdom of Scotland. Philadelphia: Andrew Steuart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, Allen. 2013. The Heart of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chung-Sho, Lo. 1949. Human Rights in the Chinese Tradition. In Human Rights. Comments and Interpretations, ed. UNESCO, 186. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchill, Robert Paul. 2006/2016. Human Rights and Global Diversity. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • CoE. 1997. Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Dignity of the Human Person with Regard to the Application of Biology and Medicine. https://www.coe.int/en/web/conventions/full-list/-/conventions/treaty/164. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • ———. 2002. ECHR Protocol Nr. 13 Convention Concerning the Abolition of the Death Penalty in all Circumstances. https://www.echr.coe.int/Documents/Library_Collection_P13_ETS187E_ENG.pdf. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • Cicero, Marco Tullius. 44 BC/2010. De officiis/Vom pflichtgemäßen Handeln. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, Joshua. 2004. Minimalism About Human Rights: The Most We Can Hope for? The Journal of Political Philosophy 12: 190–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Curran, Eleanor. 2007. Reclaiming the Rights of the Hobbesian Subject. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daly, Erin. 2012. Dignity Rights: Courts, Constitutions, and the Worth of the Human Person. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, Stephen L. 1977. Two Kinds of Respect. Ethics 88: 36–49. https://doi.org/10.1086/292054.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich, Donald J. 2017. Human Rights and the Catholic Tradition. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dorff, Elliot N. 2002. To Do the Right and the Good. A Jewish Approach to Modern Social Ethics. Philadelphia: The Jewish Society of Philadelphia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duranti, Marco. 2017. The Conservative Human Rights Revolution: European Identity, Transnational Politics, and the Origins of the European Convention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • El Fadl, Khaled Abou. 2012. The Centrality of Shari’a to Government and Constitutionalism in Islam. In Constitutionalism in Islamic Countries. Between Upheaval and Continuity, ed. Rainer Grote and Tilmann J. Röder, 35–62. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erasmus of Rotterdam. 1524/2012. A Discussion or Discourse Concerning Free Will. In Erasmus and Luther. The Battle over Free Will. Trans. Clarence H. Miller and Peter Macardle. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Etzioni, Amitai. 2010. The Normativity of Human Rights is Self-Evident. Human Rights Quarterly 32: 187–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • EU. 2000. Charta of Fundamental Rights. http://www.europarl.europa.eu/charter/pdf/text_en.pdf. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • [Federal Republic of Germany]. 1949. Basic German Law (DGG) BGBl. p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, Noah. 2010. Islamic Constitutionalism in Context: A Typology and a Warning. University of St. Thomas Law Journal 7: 435–451.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finkelstein, Claire. 2005. A Puzzle About Hobbes on Self-Defense. In Hobbes on Law, ed. Claire Finkelstein, 411–440. Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, Rainer. 2010. The Justification of Human Rights and the Basic Right to Justification: A Reflexive Approach. Ethics 120: 711–740. https://doi.org/10.1086/653434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frick, Marie-Luisa. 2010. Ummah’s Rights or Human Rights? Universalism, Individualism and Islamic Ethics in the 21st Century. American Journal of Islamic Social Sciences 27: 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Zivilisiert streiten. Zur Ethik der politischen Gegnerschaft. Stuttgart: Reclam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gade, Christian B.N. 2013. What Is Ubuntu? Different Interpretations Among South Africans of African Descent. South African Journal of Philosophy 31: 484–503. https://doi.org/10.1080/02580136.2012.10751789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, David P. 1986. Morals by Agreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1969/2000. The Logic of Leviathan. The Moral and Political Theory of Thomas Hobbes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gearty, Conor. 2006. Can Human Rights Survive? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gewirth, Alan. 1982. Human Rights. Essays on Justification and Applications. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. The Community of Rights. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghannouchi, Rached. 2016. From Political Islam to Muslim Democracy: The Ennahda Party and the Future of Tunisia. Foreign Affairs 95: 58–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glensy, Rex D. 2011. The Right to Dignity. Columbia Human Rights Review 43: 65–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godwin, William. 1793/1926. An Enquiry Concerning Political Justice and Its Influence on General Virtue and Happiness. Vol. 1. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, Lenn Evan. 1996. God of Abraham. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregg, Benjamin. 2012. Human Rights as Social Constructions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, James. 2008. On Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Between Facts and Norms—Contribution to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Trans. William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights. Metaphilosophy 41: 464–480. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9973.2010.01648.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, Louis. 1990. The Age of Rights. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herdegen, Matthias. 2009. Kommentar Art. 1. In Grundgesetz-Kommentar, ed. Maunz/Dürig. Munich: C. H. Beck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1651/1985. Leviathan. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1642/1998. The Cive. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, Otfried. 2001. Human Rights in International Discourse: Cultural Concerns. In International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, 7018–7025. https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/referenceworks/9780080430768. Accessed 28 Mar 2018.

  • Hoffmann, Thomas. 2011. Human Rights, Human Dignity, and the Human Life Form. In Human Rights and Human Nature, ed. Marion Albers, Thomas Hoffmann, and Jörn Reinhardt, 65–142. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Human Rights, Human Dignity, and the Human Life Form. In Human Rights and Human Nature, ed. Marion Albers, Thomas Hoffmann, and Jörn Reinhardt, 43–56. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hollenbach, David. 2003. The Global Face of Public Faith. Politics, Human Rights, and Christian Ethics. Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoover, Hoe. 2016. Reconstructing Human Rights. A Pragmatist und Pluralist Inquiry into Global Ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1739/1817. A Treatise of Human Nature. London: Printed for Thomas and Joseph Allman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutcheson, Francis. 1753. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue. London: Printed for R. Waren et al.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ilesanmi, Olufemi Ojo. 2015. Islamism, Statehood and Human Rights. A World of Difference. Cambridge: Intersentia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jellinek, Georg. 1922. Allgemeine Staatslehre. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamali, Mohammad Hashim. 2002/2011. The Dignity of Man: An Islamic Perspective. Cambridge: The Islamic Texts Society.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1797/1836. Metaphysics of Ethics. Trans. J.W. Semple. Edinburgh: Thomas Clark.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1796/2012. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. Mary Gregor and Jens Timmermann. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kateb, George. 2011. Human Dignity. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, Sallie B. 2012. Buddhism and Human Rights. In Religion & Human Rights. An Introduction, ed. Witte John Jr. and Christian M. Green, 103–118. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klieforth, Alexander Leslie, and Robert John Munro. 2004. The Scottish Invention of America. Democracy and Human Rights. A History of Liberty and Freedom from the Ancient Celts to the New Millennium. Dallas: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohen, Ari. 2005. The Possibility of Secular Human Rights: Alan Gewirth and the Principle of Generic Consistency. Human Rights Review 5: 49–75. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-005-1002-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • König, Siegfried. 1994. Zur Begründung der Menschenrechte. Hobbes—Locke—Kant. Munich: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraft, Viktor. 1963. Rationale Moralbegründung. Vienna: Österreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladwig, Bernd. 2016. Human Rights, Institutions and the Division of Moral Labor. Politische Vierteljahreszeitschrift 55: 472–492.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1664/1954. Essay on the Law of Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1689/2012. Two Treatises of Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1695/1999. The Reasonableness of Christianity as Delivered in the Scriptures. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lohmann, Georg. 2010. Zur moralischen, juridischen und politischen Dimension der Menschenrechte. In Recht und Moral, ed. Hans Jörg Sandkühler, 135–150. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luków, Pawel. 2018. A Difficult Legacy: Human Dignity as Founding Value of Human Rights. Human Rights Review 19: 313–329. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-018-0500-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luther, Martin. 1525/2012. The Enslaved Will. In Erasmus and Luther. The Battle Over Free Will. Trans. Clarence H. Miller and Peter Macardle. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981/1984. After Virtue. A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macklin, Ruth. 2003. Dignity Is a Useless Concept. British Medical Journal 327: 1419–1420. https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.327.7429.1419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macready, John Douglas. 2018. Hannah Arendt and the Fragility of Human Dignity. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manetti, Giannozzo. 2014 [1452–1453]. On the Dignity and Excellence of Man. In Renaissance Humanism: An Anthology of Sources. Trans. M.L. King. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margalit, Avishai. 1996. The Decent Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maritain, Jacques. 1986/2011. Christianity and Democracy and the Rights of Man and the Natural Law. San Francisco: Ignatius Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mawdudi, Abul A’la. 1977/1995. Human Rights in Islam. Lahore: Islamic Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer-Tasch, Cornelius. 1965. Thomas Hobbes und das Widerstandsrecht. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKinley Brennan, Patrick. 2015. An Essay in Christian Constitutionalism: Building in the Divine Style, for the Common Good(s). Rutgers Journal of Law and Religion 16: 478–540.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, David. 2012. Grounding Human Rights. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 15: 407–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Personhood Versus Human Needs as Grounds for Human Rights. In Griffin on Human Rights, ed. Roger Crisp, 152–169. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Milton, John. 1649/1911. The Tenure of Kings and Magistrates. New York: Henry Holt & Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Minow, Martha. 1990. Making All the Difference. Inclusion, Exclusion, and American Law. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moyn, Samuel. 2014. The Secret History of Constitutional Dignity. Yale Human Rights and Development Journal 17: 40–73. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2159248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Christian Human Rights. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ni, Peimin. 2014. Seek and You Will Find It; Let Go and You Will Loose It: Exploring a Confucian Approach to Human Dignity. Dao 13: 173–198. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11712-014-9381-2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha C. 1985. Commodities and Capabilities. New York: Elsevier Science Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Capabilities and Human Rights. Fordham Law Review 66: 273–300.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Frontiers of Justice. Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011a. Creating Capabilities. The Human Development Approach. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011b. Capabilities, Entitlements, Rights: Supplementation and Critique. Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 12: 23–37. https://doi.org/10.1080/19452829.2011.541731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • OIC. 1990. CDHRI. http://www.oic-iphrc.org/en/data/docs/legal_instruments/OIC%20Instruments/Cairo%20Declaration/Cairo%20Declaration%20on%20Human%20Rights%20in%20Islam%20-%20EV.pdf. Accessed 15 Feb 2018.

  • Ommerborn, Wolfgang, Gregor Paul, and Heiner Roetz. 2011. Das Buch Mengzi im Kontext der Menschenrechtsfrage. Vol. 2. Berlin: Lit.

    Google Scholar 

  • OSCE. 1975. Helsinki Final Act. https://www.osce.org/helsinki-final-act?download=true. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • Paine, Thomas. 2003 [1791–1792]. The Rights of Man. In Common Sense, Rights of Man, and Other Essential Writings of Thomas Paine, 129–350. New York: Signet Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pico della Mirandola, Giovanni. 1486/2014. Oration on the Dignity of Man. In Renaissance Humanism: An Anthology of Sources. Trans. M.L. King. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pope Benedict XVI. 2010. Address of His Holiness Benedict XVI to Members of the Pontifical Academy for Life. https://w2.vatican.va/content/benedict-xvi/en/speeches/2010/february/documents/hf_ben-xvi_spe_20100213_acdlife.html. Accessed 16 Apr 2018.

  • Pope Innocent III. 1195/1978. De Miseria Condicionis Humane. Trans. Robert E. Lewis. Athens: University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pope John XXIII. 1963. Encyclical Letter Pacem in Terris. http://w2.vatican.va/content/john-xxiii/de/encyclicals/documents/hf_j-xxiii_enc_11041963_pacem.html. Accessed 12 Apr 2018.

  • Pope Pius VI. 1791. Encyclical Letter Quod Aliquantum. http://digilander.libero.it/magistero/p6quodal.htm. Accessed 31 Mar 2018.

  • Quraishi-Landes, Asifa. 2015. Islamic Constitutionalism: Not Secular. Not Theocratic. Not Impossible. Rutgers Journal of Law and Religion 16: 533–579.

    Google Scholar 

  • Qur’ān. 1990. Medina: King Fahd Holy Qur’ān Printing Complex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reinbold, Jenna. 2017. Seeing the Myth in Human Rights. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Republic of Malta. 1964. Constitution. http://justiceservices.gov.mt/DownloadDocument.aspx?app=lom&itemid=8566. Accessed 9 Apr 2018.

  • Rommen, Heinrich. 1945. The State in Catholic Thought. A Treatise in Political Philosophy. London: B. Herder Book Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1993. Human Rights, Rationality, and Sentimentality. In On Human Rights. The Oxford Amnesty Lectures, ed. Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley, 112–134. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Truth and Progress. In Philosophical Papers, vol. 3. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511625404.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, Michael. 2012a. Dignity. Its History and Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Dignity Past and Present, Commentary. In Dignity, Rank, and Rights, ed. Jeremy Waldron, 79–98. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1755/2004. Discourse on the Origin of Inequality. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1762/2012. On the Social Contract. Trans. G.H.D. Cole. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sachedina, Abdulaziz. 2009. Islam & the Challenge of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • [Second Vatican Council]. 1965. Declaration Dignitatis Humanae. http://www.vatican.va/archive/hist_councils/ii_vatican_council/documents/vat-ii_decl_19651207_dignitatis-humanae_ge.html. Accessed 2018.

  • Scalon, Thomas M. 1998. What We Owe Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiller, Friedrich. 1848. Die Künstler. In Gedichte. Leipzig: Vogel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt-Leukel, Perry. 2006. Buddhism and the Idea of Human Rights: Resonances and Dissonances. Buddhist-Christian Studies 26: 33–49. https://doi.org/10.1353/bcs.2006.0024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, Doris. 2012. Human Rights and Human Dignity. An Appeal to Separate the Conjoined Twins. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 15: 323–335. https://doi.org/10.2307/23254292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaftesbury, Anthony Ashley-Cooper. 1683/1984. An Inquiry Concerning Virtue, or Merit. Stuttgart: frommann-holzboog.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter. 1980/2011. Practical Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, Quentin. 1980. The Origins of the Calvinist Theory of Revolution. In After the Reformation. Essays in Honor of J. H. Hexter, ed. Barbara C. Malament, 309–330. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, Norman. 2007. Religion and Human Rights with Special Reference to Judaism. In Does God Believe in Human Rights? ed. Nazila Ghanea, Alan Stephens, and Raphael Walden, 89–105. Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sommer, Andreas Urs. 2017. Menschenrechte gebrauchen. Zur philosophischen Relevanz ihrer Historizität. In Menschenrechte. Begründung—Universalisierbarkeit—Genese, ed. Kurt Seelmann, 126–141. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Soroush, Abdolkarim. 2000. Reason, Freedom, and Democracy in Islam. In Essential Writings of Abdolkarim Soroush. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Telushkin, Joseph. 2006. A Code of Jewish Ethics Vol. 1: You Shall Be Holy. New York: Bell Tower.

    Google Scholar 

  • [The Russian Orthodox Church]. 2008. The Bases of the Russian Orthodox Church’s Teaching on Human Dignity, Freedom and Rights. https://mospat.ru/en/documents/dignity-freedom-rights/. Accessed 15 Feb 2018.

  • Tugendhat, Ernst. 1993. Vorlesungen über Ethik. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • UN. 1945. Charta. http://www.un.org/en/charter-united-nations/. Accessed 8 Sep 2018.

  • ———. 1947. Drafting Committee Summary Record of the Eighth Meeting, E/CN.4/AC.1/SR.8.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1948. UDHR, A/RES/3/217.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966a. ICCPR, A/RES/21/2200.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966b. ICESCR, A/RES/21/2200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2012. Dignity, Rank, & Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Is Dignity the Foundation of Human Rights? In Philosophical Foundations of Human Rights, ed. Cruft Rowan, S. Matthew Liao, and Massimo Renzo, 117–137. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199688623.003.0006.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Weber-Guskar, Eva, and Mario Brandhorst, eds. 2017. Menschenwürde. Eine philosophische Debatte über Dimensionen ihrer Kontingenz. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiming, Tu. 2010. The Value of the Human in Classical Confucian Thought. In Comparative Political Theory. An Introduction, ed. Fred Dallmayr, 191–200. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wetz, Franz Josef. 2005. Illusion Menschenwürde. Aufstieg und Fall eines Grundwerts. Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Bernard. 2006. The Human Prejudice. In Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • [World Russian People’s Council]. 2006. Declaration on Human Rights and Dignity. https://mospat.ru/archive/en/2006/04/30728/. Accessed 15 Feb 2018.

  • Zhao, Tingyang. 2009. A Political World Philosophy in Terms of All-under-heaven (Tian-xia). Diogenes 56: 5–18. https://doi.org/10.1177/0392192109102149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zaret, David. 2000. Tradition, Human Rights, and the English Revolution. In Human Rights and Revolutions, ed. Jeffrey N. Wasserstrom, Lynn Hunt, and Marilyn B. Young, 43–58. New York: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marie-Luisa Frick .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Frick, ML. (2019). Foundational Paths. In: Human Rights and Relative Universalism. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-10785-7_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics